Mercurial > hg > mpdl-xml-content
comparison texts/archimedesOldCVSRepository/archimedes/raw/heath_mathe_01_en_1981.raw @ 6:22d6a63640c6
moved texts from SVN https://it-dev.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/svn/mpdl-project-content/trunk/texts/eXist/
author | casties |
---|---|
date | Fri, 07 Dec 2012 17:05:22 +0100 |
parents | |
children |
comparison
equal
deleted
inserted
replaced
5:0d8b27aa70aa | 6:22d6a63640c6 |
---|---|
1 <pb> | |
2 <C><B>A HISTORY OF | |
3 GREEK MATHEMATICS</B></C> | |
4 <C><B>SIR THOMAS HEATH</B></C> | |
5 <C><B>VOLUME I</B></C> | |
6 <C><B>FROM THALES TO EUCLID</B></C> | |
7 <C><B><I>An independent world, | |
8 Created out of pure intelligence. | |
9 —Wordsworth</I></B></C> | |
10 <C><B>Dover Publications, Inc. | |
11 New York</B></C> | |
12 <pb> | |
13 <C>Published in Canada by General Publishing Company, | |
14 Ltd., 30 Lesmill Road, Don Mills, Toronto, Ontario.</C> | |
15 <C>Published in the United Kingdom by Constable and Com- | |
16 pany, Ltd.</C> | |
17 <C>This Dover edition, first published in 1981, is an unabridged | |
18 republication of the work first published in 1921 by the | |
19 Clarendon Press, Oxford. For this edition the errata of the first | |
20 edition have been corrected.</C> | |
21 <C><I>International Standard Book Number: 0-486-24073-8 | |
22 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 80-70126</I></C> | |
23 <C>Manufactured in the United States of America</C> | |
24 <C>Dover Publications, Inc.</C> | |
25 <C>180 Varick Street</C> | |
26 <C>New York, N.Y. 10014</C> | |
27 <pb> | |
28 <head><B>PREFACE</B></head> | |
29 <p>THE idea may seem quixotic, but it is nevertheless the | |
30 author's confident hope that this book will give a fresh interest | |
31 to the story of Greek mathematics in the eyes both of | |
32 mathematicians and of classical scholars. | |
33 <p>For the mathematician the important consideration is that | |
34 the foundations of mathematics and a great portion of its | |
35 content are Greek. The Greeks laid down the first principles, | |
36 invented the methods <I>ab initio,</I> and fixed the terminology, | |
37 Mathematics in short is a Greek science, whatever new | |
38 developments modern analysis has brought or may bring. | |
39 <p>The interest of the subject for the classical scholar is no | |
40 doubt of a different kind. Greek mathematics reveals an | |
41 important aspect of the Greek genius of which the student of | |
42 Greek culture is apt to lose sight. Most people, when they | |
43 think of the Greek genius, naturally call to mind its master- | |
44 pieces in literature and art with their notes of beauty, truth, | |
45 freedom and humanism. But the Greek, with his insatiable | |
46 desire to know the true meaning of everything in the uni- | |
47 verse and to be able to give a rational explanation of it, was | |
48 just as irresistibly driven to natural science, mathematics, and | |
49 exact reasoning in general or logic. This austere side of the | |
50 Greek genius found perhaps its most complete expression in | |
51 Aristotle. Aristotle would, however, by no means admit that | |
52 mathematics was divorced from aesthetic; he could conceive, | |
53 he said, of nothing more beautiful than the objects of mathe- | |
54 matics. Plato delighted in geometry and in the wonders of | |
55 numbers; <G>a)gewme/trhtos mhdei\s ei)si/tw</G>, said the inscription | |
56 over the door of the Academy. Euclid was a no less typical | |
57 Greek. Indeed, seeing that so much of Greek is mathematics, | |
58 <pb n=vi> | |
59 <head>PREFACE</head> | |
60 it is arguable that, if one would understand the Greek genius | |
61 fully, it would be a good plan to begin with their geometry. | |
62 <p>The story of Greek mathematics has been written before. | |
63 Dr. James Gow did a great service by the publication in 1884 | |
64 of his <I>Short History of Greek Mathematics</I>, a scholarly and | |
65 useful work which has held its own and has been quoted with | |
66 respect and appreciation by authorities on the history of | |
67 mathematics in all parts of the world. At the date when he | |
68 wrote, however, Dr. Gow had necessarily to rely upon the | |
69 works of the pioneers Bretschneider, Hankel, Allman, and | |
70 Moritz Cantor (first edition). Since then the subject has been | |
71 very greatly advanced; new texts have been published, im- | |
72 portant new documents have been discovered, and researches | |
73 by scholars and mathematicians in different countries have | |
74 thrown light on many obscure points. It is, therefore, high | |
75 time for the complete story to be rewritten. | |
76 <p>It is true that in recent years a number of attractive | |
77 histories of mathematics have been published in England and | |
78 America, but these have only dealt with Greek mathematics | |
79 as part of the larger subject, and in consequence the writers | |
80 have been precluded, by considerations of space alone, from | |
81 presenting the work of the Greeks in sufficient detail. | |
82 <p>The same remark applies to the German histories of mathe- | |
83 matics, even to the great work of Moritz Cantor, who treats | |
84 of the history of Greek mathematics in about 400 pages of | |
85 vol. i. While no one would wish to disparage so great a | |
86 monument of indefatigable research, it was inevitable that | |
87 a book on such a scale would in time prove to be inadequate, | |
88 and to need correction in details; and the later editions have | |
89 unfortunately failed to take sufficient account of the new | |
90 materials which have become available since the first edition | |
91 saw the light. | |
92 <p>The best history of Greek mathematics which exists at | |
93 present is undoubtedly that of Gino Loria under the title | |
94 <I>Le scienze esatte nell' antica Grecia</I> (second edition 1914, | |
95 <pb n=vii> | |
96 <head>PREFACE</head> | |
97 Ulrico Hoepli, Milano). Professor Loria arranges his material | |
98 in five Books, (1) on pre-Euclidean geometry, (2) on the | |
99 Golden Age of Greek geometry (Euclid to Apollonius), (3) on | |
100 applied mathematics, including astronomy, sphaeric, optics, | |
101 &c., (4) on the Silver Age of Greek geometry, (5) on the | |
102 arithmetic of the Greeks. Within the separate Books the | |
103 arrangement is chronological, under the names of persons or | |
104 schools. I mention these details because they raise the | |
105 question whether, in a history of this kind, it is best to follow | |
106 chronological order or to arrange the material according to | |
107 subjects, and, if the latter, in what sense of the word ‘subject’ | |
108 and within what limits. As Professor Loria says, his arrange- | |
109 ment is ‘a compromise between arrangement according to | |
110 subjects and a strict adherence to chronological order, each of | |
111 which plans has advantages and disadvantages of its own’. | |
112 <p>In this book I have adopted a new arrangement, mainly | |
113 according to subjects, the nature of which and the reasons for | |
114 which will be made clear by an illustration. Take the case of | |
115 a famous problem which plays a great part in the history of | |
116 Greek geometry, the doubling of the cube, or its equivalent, | |
117 the finding of two mean proportionals in continued proportion | |
118 between two given straight lines. Under a chronological | |
119 arrangement this problem comes up afresh on the occasion of | |
120 each new solution. Now it is obvious that, if all the recorded | |
121 solutions are collected together, it is much easier to see the | |
122 relations, amounting in some cases to substantial identity, | |
123 between them, and to get a comprehensive view of the history | |
124 of the problem. I have therefore dealt with this problem in | |
125 a separate section of the chapter devoted to ‘Special Problems’, | |
126 and I have followed the same course with the other famous | |
127 problems of squaring the circle and trisecting any angle. | |
128 <p>Similar considerations arise with regard to certain well- | |
129 defined subjects such as conic sections. It would be incon- | |
130 venient to interrupt the account of Menaechmus's solution | |
131 of the problem of the two mean proportionals in order to | |
132 <pb n=viii> | |
133 <head>PREFACE</head> | |
134 consider the way in which he may have discovered the conic | |
135 sections and their fundamental properties. It seems to me | |
136 much better to give the complete story of the origin and | |
137 development of the geometry of the conic sections in one | |
138 place, and this has been done in the chapter on conic sections | |
139 associated with the name of Apollonius of Perga. Similarly | |
140 a chapter has been devoted to algebra (in connexion with | |
141 Diophantus) and another to trigonometry (under Hipparchus, | |
142 Menelaus and Ptolemy). | |
143 <p>At the same time the outstanding personalities of Euclid | |
144 and Archimedes demand chapters to themselves. Euclid, the | |
145 author of the incomparable <I>Elements</I>, wrote on almost all | |
146 the other branches of mathematics known in his day. Archi- | |
147 medes's work, all original and set forth in treatises which are | |
148 models of scientific exposition, perfect in form and style, was | |
149 even wider in its range of subjects. The imperishable and | |
150 unique monuments of the genius of these two men must be | |
151 detached from their surroundings and seen as a whole if we | |
152 would appreciate to the full the pre-eminent place which they | |
153 occupy, and will hold for all time, in the history of science. | |
154 <p>The arrangement which I have adopted necessitates (as does | |
155 any other order of exposition) a certain amount of repetition | |
156 and cross-references; but only in this way can the necessary | |
157 unity be given to the whole narrative. | |
158 <p>One other point should be mentioned. It is a defect in the | |
159 existing histories that, while they state generally the contents | |
160 of, and the main propositions proved in, the great treatises of | |
161 Archimedes and Apollonius, they make little attempt to | |
162 describe the procedure by which the results are obtained. | |
163 I have therefore taken pains, in the most significant cases, | |
164 to show the course of the argument in sufficient detail to | |
165 enable a competent mathematician to grasp the method used | |
166 and to apply it, if he will, to other similar investigations. | |
167 <p>The work was begun in 1913, but the bulk of it was | |
168 written, as a distraction, during the first three years of the | |
169 <pb n=ix> | |
170 <head>PREFACE</head> | |
171 war, the hideous course of which seemed day by day to | |
172 enforce the profound truth conveyed in the answer of Plato | |
173 to the Delians. When they consulted him on the problem set | |
174 them by the Oracle, namely that of duplicating the cube, he | |
175 replied, ‘It must be supposed, not that the god specially | |
176 wished this problem solved, but that he would have the | |
177 Greeks desist from war and wickedness and cultivate the | |
178 Muses, so that, their passions being assuaged by philosophy | |
179 and mathematics, they might live in innocent and mutually | |
180 helpful intercourse with one another’. | |
181 <p>Truly | |
182 Greece and her foundations are<lb> | |
183 Built below the tide of war,<lb> | |
184 Based on the crystàlline sea<lb> | |
185 Of thought and its eternity.<lb> | |
186 T. L. H. | |
187 <pb> | |
188 <table> | |
189 <caption><B>CONTENTS OF VOL. I</B></caption> | |
190 <tr><td>I. INTRODUCTORY</td><td align=right>PAGES 1-25</td></tr> | |
191 <tr><td>The Greeks and mathematics</td><td align=right>1-3</td></tr> | |
192 <tr><td>Conditions favouring development of philosophy among the Greeks</td><td align=right>3-10</td></tr> | |
193 <tr><td>Meaning and classification of mathematics</td><td align=right>10-18</td></tr> | |
194 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Arithmetic and logistic</td><td align=right>13-16</td></tr> | |
195 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) Geometry and geodaesia</td><td align=right>16</td></tr> | |
196 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Physical subjects, mechanics, optics, &c.</td><td align=right>17-18</td></tr> | |
197 <tr><td>Mathematics in Greek education</td><td align=right>18-25</td></tr> | |
198 <tr><td>II. GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION AND ARITHMETICAL OPERATIONS</td><td align=right>26-64</td></tr> | |
199 <tr><td>The decimal system</td><td align=right>26-27</td></tr> | |
200 <tr><td>Egyptian numerical notation</td><td align=right>27-28</td></tr> | |
201 <tr><td>Babylonian systems</td></tr> | |
202 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Decimal. (<G>b</G>) Sexagesimal</td><td align=right>28-29</td></tr> | |
203 <tr><td>Greek numerical notation</td><td align=right>29-45</td></tr> | |
204 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) The ‘Herodianic’ signs</td><td align=right>30-31</td></tr> | |
205 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The ordinary alphabetic numerals</td><td align=right>31-35</td></tr> | |
206 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Mode of writing numbers in the ordinary alphabetic notation</td><td align=right>36-37</td></tr> | |
207 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) Comparison of the two systems of numerical notation</td><td align=right>37-39</td></tr> | |
208 <tr><td>(<G>e</G>) Notation, for large numbers</td><td align=right>39-41</td></tr> | |
209 <tr><td>(i) Apollonius's ‘tetrads’</td><td align=right>40</td></tr> | |
210 <tr><td>(ii) Archimedes's system (by octads)</td><td align=right>40-41</td></tr> | |
211 <tr><td>Fractions</td></tr> | |
212 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) The Egyptian system</td><td align=right>41-42</td></tr> | |
213 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The ordinary Greek form, variously written</td><td align=right>42-44</td></tr> | |
214 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Sexagesimal fractions</td><td align=right>44-45</td></tr> | |
215 <tr><td>Practical calculation</td></tr> | |
216 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) The abacus</td><td align=right>46-52</td></tr> | |
217 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) Addition and subtraction</td><td align=right>52</td></tr> | |
218 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Multiplication</td></tr> | |
219 <tr><td>(i) The Egyptian method</td><td align=right>52-53</td></tr> | |
220 <tr><td>(ii) The Greek method</td><td align=right>53-54</td></tr> | |
221 <tr><td>(iii) Apollonius's continued multiplications</td><td align=right>54-57</td></tr> | |
222 <tr><td>(iv) Examples of ordinary multiplications</td><td align=right>57-58</td></tr> | |
223 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) Division</td><td align=right>58-60</td></tr> | |
224 <tr><td>(<G>e</G>) Extraction of the square root</td><td align=right>60-63</td></tr> | |
225 <tr><td>(<G>z</G>) Extraction of the cube root</td><td align=right>63-64</td></tr> | |
226 </table> | |
227 <pb n=xii> | |
228 <head>CONTENTS</head> | |
229 <table> | |
230 <tr><td>III. PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</td><td align=right>PAGES 65-117</td></tr> | |
231 <tr><td>Numbers and the universe</td><td align=right>67-69</td></tr> | |
232 <tr><td>Definitions of the unit and of number</td><td align=right>69-70</td></tr> | |
233 <tr><td>Classification of numbers</td><td align=right>70-74</td></tr> | |
234 <tr><td>‘Perfect’ and ‘Friendly’ numbers</td><td align=right>74-76</td></tr> | |
235 <tr><td>Figured numbers</td></tr> | |
236 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Triangular numbers</td><td align=right>76-77</td></tr> | |
237 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) Square numbers and gnomons</td><td align=right>77</td></tr> | |
238 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) History of the term ‘gnomon’</td><td align=right>78-79</td></tr> | |
239 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) Gnomons of the polygonal numbers</td><td align=right>79</td></tr> | |
240 <tr><td>(<G>e</G>) Right-angled triangles with sides in rational numbers</td><td align=right>79-82</td></tr> | |
241 <tr><td>(<G>z</G>) Oblong numbers</td><td align=right>82-84</td></tr> | |
242 <tr><td>The theory of proportion and means</td><td align=right>84-90</td></tr> | |
243 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Arithmetic, geometric and harmonic means</td><td align=right>85-86</td></tr> | |
244 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) Seven other means distinguished</td><td align=right>86-89</td></tr> | |
245 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Plato on geometric means between two squares or two cubes</td><td align=right>89-90</td></tr> | |
246 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) A theorem of Archytas</td><td align=right>90</td></tr> | |
247 <tr><td>The ‘irrational’</td><td align=right>90-91</td></tr> | |
248 <tr><td>Algebraic equations</td></tr> | |
249 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) ‘Side-’ and ‘diameter-’ numbers, giving successive approximations to √2 (solutions of <MATH>2<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP> - <I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP> = ± 1</MATH>)</td><td align=right>91-93</td></tr> | |
250 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The <G>e)pa/nqhua</G> (‘bloom’) of Thymaridas</td><td align=right>94-96</td></tr> | |
251 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Area of rectangles in relation to perimeter (equation <MATH><I>xy</I> = 2<I>x</I> + <I>y</I></MATH>)</td><td align=right>96-97</td></tr> | |
252 <tr><td>Systematic treatises on arithmetic (theory of numbers)</td><td align=right>97-115</td></tr> | |
253 <tr><td>Nicomachus, <I>Introductio Arithmetica</I></td><td align=right>97-112</td></tr> | |
254 <tr><td>Sum of series of cube numbers</td><td align=right>108-110</td></tr> | |
255 <tr><td>Theon of Smyrna</td><td align=right>112-113</td></tr> | |
256 <tr><td>Iamblichus, Commentary on Nicomachus</td><td align=right>113-115</td></tr> | |
257 <tr><td>The <I>pythmen</I> and the rule of nine or seven</td><td align=right>115-117</td></tr> | |
258 <tr><td>IV. THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</td><td align=right>118-140</td></tr> | |
259 <tr><td>The ‘Summary’ of Proclus</td><td align=right>118-121</td></tr> | |
260 <tr><td>Tradition as to the origin of geometry</td><td align=right>121-122</td></tr> | |
261 <tr><td>Egyptian geometry, i.e. mensuration</td><td align=right>122-128</td></tr> | |
262 <tr><td>The beginnings of Greek geometry. Thales</td><td align=right>128-139</td></tr> | |
263 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Measurement of height of pyramid</td><td align=right>129-130</td></tr> | |
264 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) Geometrical theorems attributed to Thales</td><td align=right>130-137</td></tr> | |
265 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Thales as astronomer</td><td align=right>137-139</td></tr> | |
266 <tr><td>From Thales to Pythagoras</td><td align=right>139-140</td></tr> | |
267 <tr><td>V. PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</td><td align=right>141-169</td></tr> | |
268 <tr><td>Pythagoras</td><td align=right>141-142</td></tr> | |
269 <tr><td>Discoveries attributed to the Pythagoreans</td></tr> | |
270 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Equality of sum of angles of any triangle to two right angles</td><td align=right>143-144</td></tr> | |
271 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The ‘Theorem of Pythagoras’</td><td align=right>144-149</td></tr> | |
272 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Application of areas and geometrical algebra (solu-tion of quadratic equations)</td><td align=right>150-154</td></tr> | |
273 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) The irrational</td><td align=right>154-157</td></tr> | |
274 <tr><td>(<G>e</G>) The five regular solids</td><td align=right>158-162</td></tr> | |
275 <tr><td>(<G>z</G>) Pythagorean astronomy</td><td align=right>162-165</td></tr> | |
276 <tr><td>Recapitulation</td><td align=right>165-169</td></tr> | |
277 </table> | |
278 <pb n=xiii> | |
279 <head>CONTENTS</head> | |
280 <table> | |
281 <tr><td>VI. PROGRESS IN THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</td><td align=right>PAGES 170-217</td></tr> | |
282 <tr><td>Extract from Proclus's summary</td><td align=right>170-172</td></tr> | |
283 <tr><td>Anaxagoras</td><td align=right>172-174</td></tr> | |
284 <tr><td>Oenopides of Chios</td><td align=right>174-176</td></tr> | |
285 <tr><td>Democritus</td><td align=right>176-181</td></tr> | |
286 <tr><td>Hippias of Elis</td><td align=right>182</td></tr> | |
287 <tr><td>Hippocrates of Chios</td><td align=right>182-202</td></tr> | |
288 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Hippocrates's quadrature of lunes</td><td align=right>183-200</td></tr> | |
289 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) Reduction of the problem of doubling the cube to the finding of two mean proportionals</td><td align=right>200-201</td></tr> | |
290 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) The Elements as known to Hippocrates</td><td align=right>201-202</td></tr> | |
291 <tr><td>Theodorus of Cyrene</td><td align=right>202-209</td></tr> | |
292 <tr><td>Theaetetus</td><td align=right>209-212</td></tr> | |
293 <tr><td>Archytas</td><td align=right>213-216</td></tr> | |
294 <tr><td>Summary</td><td align=right>216-217</td></tr> | |
295 <tr><td>VII. SPECIAL PROBLEMS</td><td align=right>218-270</td></tr> | |
296 <tr><td>The squaring of the circle</td><td align=right>220-235</td></tr> | |
297 <tr><td>Antiphon</td><td align=right>221-223</td></tr> | |
298 <tr><td>Bryson</td><td align=right>223-225</td></tr> | |
299 <tr><td>Hippias, Dinostratus, Nicomedes, &c.</td><td align=right>225-226</td></tr> | |
300 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) The quadratrix of Hippias</td><td align=right>226-230</td></tr> | |
301 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The spiral of Archimedes</td><td align=right>230-231</td></tr> | |
302 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Solutions by Apollonius and Carpus</td><td align=right>231-232</td></tr> | |
303 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) Approximations to the value of <G>p</G></td><td align=right>232-235</td></tr> | |
304 <tr><td>The trisection of any angle</td><td align=right>235-244</td></tr> | |
305 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Reduction to a certain <G>neu=sis</G>, solved by conics</td><td align=right>235-237</td></tr> | |
306 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The <G>neu=sis</G> equivalent to a cubic equation</td><td align=right>237-238</td></tr> | |
307 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) The conchoids of Nicomedes</td><td align=right>238-240</td></tr> | |
308 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) Another reduction to a <G>neu=sis</G> (Archimedes)</td><td align=right>240-241</td></tr> | |
309 <tr><td>(<G>e</G>) Direct solutions by means of conics (Pappus)</td><td align=right>241-244</td></tr> | |
310 <tr><td>The duplication of the cube, or the problem of the two mean proportionals</td><td align=right>244-270</td></tr> | |
311 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) History of the problem</td><td align=right>244-246</td></tr> | |
312 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) Archytas</td><td align=right>246-249</td></tr> | |
313 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Eudoxus</td><td align=right>249-251</td></tr> | |
314 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) Menaechmus</td><td align=right>251-255</td></tr> | |
315 <tr><td>(<G>e</G>) The solution attributed to Plato</td><td align=right>255-258</td></tr> | |
316 <tr><td>(<G>z</G>) Eratosthenes</td><td align=right>258-260</td></tr> | |
317 <tr><td>(<G>h</G>) Nicomedes</td><td align=right>260-262</td></tr> | |
318 <tr><td>(<G>q</G>) Apollonius, Heron, Philon of Byzantium</td><td align=right>262-264</td></tr> | |
319 <tr><td>(<G>i</G>) Diocles and the cissoid</td><td align=right>264-266</td></tr> | |
320 <tr><td>(<G>k</G>) Sporus and Pappus</td><td align=right>266-268</td></tr> | |
321 <tr><td>(<G>l</G>) Approximation to a solution by plane methods only</td><td align=right>268-270</td></tr> | |
322 <tr><td>VIII. ZENO OF ELEA</td><td align=right>271-283</td></tr> | |
323 <tr><td>Zeno's arguments about motion</td><td align=right>273-283</td></tr> | |
324 <tr><td>IX. PLATO</td><td align=right>284-315</td></tr> | |
325 <tr><td>Contributions to the philosophy of mathematics</td><td align=right>288-294</td></tr> | |
326 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) The hypotheses of mathematics</td><td align=right>289-290</td></tr> | |
327 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The two intellectual methods</td><td align=right>290-292</td></tr> | |
328 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Definitions</td><td align=right>292-294</td></tr> | |
329 </table> | |
330 <pb n=xiv> | |
331 <head>CONTENTS</head> | |
332 <table> | |
333 <tr><td>IX. CONTINUED</td></tr> | |
334 <tr><td>Summary of the mathematics in Plato</td><td align=right>PAGES 294-308</td></tr> | |
335 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Regular and semi-regular solids</td><td align=right>294-295</td></tr> | |
336 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The construction of the regular solids</td><td align=right>296-297</td></tr> | |
337 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Geometric means between two square numbers or two cubes</td><td align=right>297</td></tr> | |
338 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) The two geometrical passages in the <I>Meno</I></td><td align=right>297-303</td></tr> | |
339 <tr><td>(<G>e</G>) Plato and the doubling of the cube</td><td align=right>303</td></tr> | |
340 <tr><td>(<G>z</G>) Solution of <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP> + <I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP> = <I>z</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> in integers</td><td align=right>304</td></tr> | |
341 <tr><td>(<G>h</G>) Incommensurables</td><td align=right>304-305</td></tr> | |
342 <tr><td>(<G>q</G>) The Geometrical Number</td><td align=right>305-308</td></tr> | |
343 <tr><td>Mathematical ‘arts’</td><td align=right>308-315</td></tr> | |
344 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Optics</td><td align=right>309</td></tr> | |
345 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) Music</td><td align=right>310</td></tr> | |
346 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Astronomy</td><td align=right>310-315</td></tr> | |
347 <tr><td>X. FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</td><td align=right>316-353</td></tr> | |
348 <tr><td>Heraclides of Pontus: astronomical discoveries</td><td align=right>316-317</td></tr> | |
349 <tr><td>Theory of numbers (Speusippus, Xenocrates)</td><td align=right>318-319</td></tr> | |
350 <tr><td>The Elements. Proclus's summary (<I>continued</I>)</td><td align=right>319-321</td></tr> | |
351 <tr><td>Eudoxus</td><td align=right>322-335</td></tr> | |
352 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Theory of proportion</td><td align=right>325-327</td></tr> | |
353 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The method of exhaustion</td><td align=right>327-329</td></tr> | |
354 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Theory of concentric spheres</td><td align=right>329-335</td></tr> | |
355 <tr><td>Aristotle</td><td align=right>335-348</td></tr> | |
356 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) First principles</td><td align=right>336-338</td></tr> | |
357 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) Indications of proofs differing from Euclid's</td><td align=right>338-340</td></tr> | |
358 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Propositions not found in Euclid</td><td align=right>340-341</td></tr> | |
359 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) Curves and solids known to Aristotle</td><td align=right>341-342</td></tr> | |
360 <tr><td>(<G>e</G>) The continuous and the infinite</td><td align=right>342-344</td></tr> | |
361 <tr><td>(<G>z</G>) Mechanics</td><td align=right>344-346</td></tr> | |
362 <tr><td>The Aristotclian tract on indivisible lines</td><td align=right>346-348</td></tr> | |
363 <tr><td>Sphaeric</td></tr> | |
364 <tr><td>Autolycus of Pitane</td><td align=right>348-353</td></tr> | |
365 <tr><td>A lost text-book on Sphaeric</td><td align=right>349-350</td></tr> | |
366 <tr><td>Autolycus, <I>On the Moving Sphere</I>: relation to Euclid</td><td align=right>351-352</td></tr> | |
367 <tr><td>Autolycus, <I>On Risings and Settings</I></td><td align=right>352-353</td></tr> | |
368 <tr><td>XI. EUCLID</td><td align=right>354-446</td></tr> | |
369 <tr><td>Date and traditions</td><td align=right>354-357</td></tr> | |
370 <tr><td>Ancient commentaries, criticisms and references</td><td align=right>357-360</td></tr> | |
371 <tr><td>The text of the <I>Elements</I></td><td align=right>360-361</td></tr> | |
372 <tr><td>Latin and Arabic translations</td><td align=right>361-364</td></tr> | |
373 <tr><td>The first printed editions</td><td align=right>364-365</td></tr> | |
374 <tr><td>The study of Euclid in the Middle Ages</td><td align=right>365-369</td></tr> | |
375 <tr><td>The first English editions</td><td align=right>369-370</td></tr> | |
376 <tr><td>Technical terms</td></tr> | |
377 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) Terms for the formal divisions of a proposition</td><td align=right>370-371</td></tr> | |
378 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The <G>diorismo/s</G> or statement of conditions of possi-bility</td><td align=right>371</td></tr> | |
379 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Analysis, synthesis, reduction, <I>reductio ad absurdum</I></td><td align=right>371-372</td></tr> | |
380 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) Case, objection, porism, lemma</td><td align=right>372-373</td></tr> | |
381 <tr><td>Analysis of the <I>Elements</I></td></tr> | |
382 <tr><td>Book I</td><td align=right>373-379</td></tr> | |
383 <tr><td>" II</td><td align=right>379-380</td></tr> | |
384 </table> | |
385 <pb n=xv> | |
386 <head>CONTENTS</head> | |
387 <table> | |
388 <tr><td>Book III</td><td align=right>PAGES 380-383</td></tr> | |
389 <tr><td>" IV</td><td align=right>383-384</td></tr> | |
390 <tr><td>" V</td><td align=right>384-391</td></tr> | |
391 <tr><td>" VI</td><td align=right>391-397</td></tr> | |
392 <tr><td>" VII</td><td align=right>397-399</td></tr> | |
393 <tr><td>" VIII</td><td align=right>399-400</td></tr> | |
394 <tr><td>" IX</td><td align=right>400-402</td></tr> | |
395 <tr><td>" X</td><td align=right>402-412</td></tr> | |
396 <tr><td>" XI</td><td align=right>412-413</td></tr> | |
397 <tr><td>" XII</td><td align=right>413-415</td></tr> | |
398 <tr><td>" XIII</td><td align=right>415-419</td></tr> | |
399 <tr><td>The so-called Books XIV, XV</td><td align=right>419-421</td></tr> | |
400 <tr><td>The <I>Data</I></td><td align=right>421-425</td></tr> | |
401 <tr><td><I>On divisions</I> (<I>of figures</I>)</td><td align=right>425-430</td></tr> | |
402 <tr><td>Lost geometrical works</td></tr> | |
403 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) The <I>Pseudaria</I></td><td align=right>430-431</td></tr> | |
404 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) The <I>Porisms</I></td><td align=right>431-438</td></tr> | |
405 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) The <I>Conics</I></td><td align=right>438-439</td></tr> | |
406 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) The <I>Surface Loci</I></td><td align=right>439-440</td></tr> | |
407 <tr><td>Applied mathematics</td></tr> | |
408 <tr><td>(<G>a</G>) The <I>Phaenomena</I></td><td align=right>440-441</td></tr> | |
409 <tr><td>(<G>b</G>) <I>Optics</I> and <I>Catoptrica</I></td><td align=right>441-444</td></tr> | |
410 <tr><td>(<G>g</G>) Music</td><td align=right>444-445</td></tr> | |
411 <tr><td>(<G>d</G>) Works on mechanics attributed to Euclid</td><td align=right>445-446</td></tr> | |
412 </table> | |
413 <pb> | |
414 <C>I</C> | |
415 <C>INTRODUCTORY</C> | |
416 <C>The Greeks and mathematics.</C> | |
417 <p>IT is an encouraging sign of the times that more and more | |
418 effort is being directed to promoting a due appreciation and | |
419 a clear understanding of the gifts of the Greeks to mankind. | |
420 What we owe to Greece, what the Greeks have done for | |
421 civilization, aspects of the Greek genius: such are the themes | |
422 of many careful studies which have made a wide appeal and | |
423 will surely produce their effect. In truth all nations, in the | |
424 West at all events, have been to school to the Greeks, in art, | |
425 literature, philosophy, and science, the things which are essen- | |
426 tial to the rational use and enjoyment of human powers and | |
427 activities, the things which make life worth living to a rational | |
428 human being. ‘Of all peoples the Greeks have dreamed the | |
429 dream of life the best.’ And the Greeks were not merely the | |
430 pioneers in the branches of knowledge which they invented | |
431 and to which they gave names. What they began they carried | |
432 to a height of perfection which has not since been surpassed; | |
433 if there are exceptions, it is only where a few crowded centuries | |
434 were not enough to provide the accumulation of experience | |
435 required, whether for the purpose of correcting hypotheses | |
436 which at first could only be of the nature of guesswork, or of | |
437 suggesting new methods and machinery. | |
438 <p>Of all the manifestations of the Greek genius none is more | |
439 impressive and even awe-inspiring than that which is revealed | |
440 by the history of Greek mathematics. Not only are the range | |
441 and the sum of what the Greek mathematicians actually | |
442 accomplished wonderful in themselves; it is necessary to bear | |
443 in mind that this mass of original work was done in an almost | |
444 incredibly short space of time, and in spite of the comparative | |
445 inadequacy (as it would seem to us) of the only methods at | |
446 their disposal, namely those of pure geometry, supplemented, | |
447 where necessary, by the ordinary arithmetical operations. | |
448 <pb n=2><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
449 Let us, confining ourselves to the main subject of pure | |
450 geometry by way of example, anticipate so far as to mark | |
451 certain definite stages in its development, with the intervals | |
452 separating them. In Thales's time (about 600 B. C.) we find | |
453 the first glimmerings of a theory of geometry, in the theorems | |
454 that a circle is bisected by any diameter, that an isosceles | |
455 triangle has the angles opposite to the equal sides equal, and | |
456 (if Thales really discovered this) that the angle in a semicircle | |
457 is a right angle. Rather more than half a century later | |
458 Pythagoras was taking the first steps towards the theory of | |
459 numbers and continuing the work of making geometry a | |
460 theoretical science; he it was who first made geometry one of | |
461 the subjects of a liberal education. The Pythagoreans, before | |
462 the next century was out (i. e. before, say, 450 B. C.), had practi- | |
463 cally completed the subject-matter of Books I-II, IV, VI (and | |
464 perhaps III) of Euclid's <I>Elements</I>, including all the essentials | |
465 of the ‘geometrical algebra’ which remained fundamental in | |
466 Greek geometry; the only drawback was that their theory of | |
467 proportion was not applicable to incommensurable but only | |
468 to commensurable magnitudes, so that it proved inadequate | |
469 as soon as the incommensurable came to be discovered. | |
470 In the same fifth century the difficult problems of doubling | |
471 the cube and trisecting any angle, which are beyond the | |
472 geometry of the straight line and circle, were not only mooted | |
473 but solved theoretically, the former problem having been first | |
474 reduced to that of finding two mean proportionals in continued | |
475 proportion (Hippocrates of Chios) and then solved by a | |
476 remarkable construction in three dimensions (Archytas), while | |
477 the latter was solved by means of the curve of Hippias of | |
478 Elis known as the <I>quadratrix</I>; the problem of squaring the | |
479 circle was also attempted, and Hippocrates, as a contribution | |
480 to it, discovered and squared three out of the five lunes which | |
481 can be squared by means of the straight line and circle. In | |
482 the fourth century Eudoxus discovered the great theory of | |
483 proportion expounded in Euclid, Book V, and laid down the | |
484 principles of the <I>method of exhaustion</I> for measuring areas and | |
485 volumes; the conic sections and their fundamental properties | |
486 were discovered by Menaechmus; the theory of irrationals | |
487 (probably discovered, so far as √(2) is concerned, by the | |
488 early Pythagoreans) was generalized by Theaetetus; and the | |
489 <pb n=3><head>THE GREEKS AND MATHEMATICS</head> | |
490 geometry of the sphere was worked out in systematic trea- | |
491 tises. About the end of the century Euclid wrote his | |
492 <I>Elements</I> in thirteen Books. The next century, the third, | |
493 is that of Archimedes, who may be said to have anticipated | |
494 the integral calculus, since, by performing what are practi- | |
495 cally <I>integrations</I>, he found the area of a parabolic segment | |
496 and of a spiral, the surface and volume of a sphere and a | |
497 segment of a sphere, the volume of any segment of the solids | |
498 of revolution of the second degree, the centres of gravity of | |
499 a semicircle, a parabolic segment, any segment of a paraboloid | |
500 of revolution, and any segment of a sphere or spheroid. | |
501 Apollonius of Perga, the ‘great geometer’, about 200 B. C., | |
502 completed the theory of geometrical conics, with specialized | |
503 investigations of normals as maxima and minima leading | |
504 quite easily to the determination of the circle of curvature | |
505 at any point of a conic and of the equation of the evolute of | |
506 the conic, which with us is part of analytical conics. With | |
507 Apollonius the main body of Greek geometry is complete, and | |
508 we may therefore fairly say that four centuries sufficed to | |
509 complete it. | |
510 <p>But some one will say, how did all this come about? What | |
511 special aptitude had the Greeks for mathematics? The answer | |
512 to this question is that their genius for mathematics was | |
513 simply one aspect of their genius for philosophy. Their | |
514 mathematics indeed constituted a large part of their philo- | |
515 sophy down to Plato. Both had the same origin. | |
516 <C>Conditions favouring the development of philosophy | |
517 among the Greeks.</C> | |
518 <p>All men by nature desire to know, says Aristotle.<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> A. 1, 980 a 21.</note> The | |
519 Greeks, beyond any other people of antiquity, possessed the | |
520 love of knowledge for its own sake; with them it amounted | |
521 to an instinct and a passion.<note>Cf. Butcher, <I>Some Aspects of the Greek Genius</I>, 1892, p. 1.</note> We see this first of all in their | |
522 love of adventure. It is characteristic that in the <I>Odyssey</I> | |
523 Odysseus is extolled as the hero who had ‘seen the cities of | |
524 many men and learned their mind’,<note><I>Od.</I> i. 3.</note> often even taking his life | |
525 in his hand, out of a pure passion for extending his horizon, | |
526 <pb n=4><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
527 as when he went to see the Cyclopes in order to ascertain ‘what | |
528 sort of people they were, whether violent and savage, with no | |
529 sense of justice, or hospitable and godfearing’.<note><I>Od.</I> ix. 174-6.</note> Coming | |
530 nearer to historical times, we find philosophers and statesmen | |
531 travelling in order to benefit by all the wisdom that other | |
532 nations with a longer history had gathered during the cen- | |
533 turies. Thales travelled in Egypt and spent his time with | |
534 the priests. Solon, according to Herodotus,<note>Herodotus, i. 30.</note> travelled ‘to see | |
535 the world’ (<G>qewri/hs ei(/neken</G>), going to Egypt to the court of | |
536 Amasis, and visiting Croesus at Sardis. At Sardis it was not | |
537 till ‘after he had seen and examined everything’ that he had | |
538 the famous conversation with Croesus; and Croesus addressed | |
539 him as the Athenian of whose wisdom and peregrinations he | |
540 had heard great accounts, proving that he had covered much | |
541 ground in seeing the world and pursuing philosophy. | |
542 (Herodotus, also a great traveller, is himself an instance of | |
543 the capacity of the Greeks for assimilating anything that | |
544 could be learnt from any other nations whatever; and, | |
545 although in Herodotus's case the object in view was less the | |
546 pursuit of philosophy than the collection of interesting infor- | |
547 mation, yet he exhibits in no less degree the Greek passion | |
548 for seeing things as they are and discerning their meaning | |
549 and mutual relations; ‘he compares his reports, he weighs the | |
550 evidence, he is conscious of his own office as an inquirer after | |
551 truth’.) But the same avidity for learning is best of all | |
552 illustrated by the similar tradition with regard to Pythagoras's | |
553 travels. Iamblichus, in his account of the life of Pythagoras,<note>Iamblichus, <I>De vita Pythagorica</I>, cc. 2-4.</note> | |
554 says that Thales, admiring his remarkable ability, communi- | |
555 cated to him all that he knew, but, pleading his own age and | |
556 failing strength, advised him for his better instruction to go | |
557 and study with the Egyptian priests. Pythagoras, visiting | |
558 Sidon on the way, both because it was his birthplace and | |
559 because he properly thought that the passage to Egypt would | |
560 be easier by that route, consorted there with the descendants | |
561 of Mochus, the natural philosopher and prophet, and with the | |
562 other Phoenician hierophants, and was initiated into all | |
563 the rites practised in Biblus, Tyre, and in many parts of | |
564 Syria, a regimen to which he submitted, not out of religious | |
565 <pb n=5><head>DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY</head> | |
566 enthusiasm, ‘<I>as you might think</I>’ (<G>w(s a)/n tis a(plw=s u(pola/boi</G>), | |
567 but much more through love and desire for philosophic | |
568 inquiry, and in order to secure that he should not overlook | |
569 any fragment of knowledge worth acquiring that might lie | |
570 hidden in the mysteries or ceremonies of divine worship; | |
571 then, understanding that what he found in Phoenicia was in | |
572 some sort an offshoot or descendant of the wisdom of the | |
573 priests of Egypt, he concluded that he should acquire learning | |
574 more pure and more sublime by going to the fountain-head in | |
575 Egypt itself. | |
576 <p>‘There’, continues the story, ‘he studied with the priests | |
577 and prophets and instructed himself on every possible topic, | |
578 neglecting no item of the instruction favoured by the best | |
579 judges, no individual man among those who were famous for | |
580 their knowledge, no rite practised in the country wherever it | |
581 was, and leaving no place unexplored where he thought he | |
582 could discover something more. . . . And so he spent 22 | |
583 years in the shrines throughout Egypt, pursuing astronomy | |
584 and geometry and, of set purpose and not by fits and starts or | |
585 casually, entering into all the rites of divine worship, until he | |
586 was taken captive by Cambyses's force and carried off to | |
587 Babylon, where again he consorted with the Magi, a willing | |
588 pupil of willing masters. By them he was fully instructed in | |
589 their solemn rites and religious worship, and in their midst he | |
590 attained to the highest eminence in arithmetic, music, and the | |
591 other branches of learning. After twelve years more thus | |
592 spent he returned to Samos, being then about 56 years old.’ | |
593 <p>Whether these stories are true in their details or not is | |
594 a matter of no consequence. They represent the traditional | |
595 and universal view of the Greeks themselves regarding the | |
596 beginnings of their philosophy, and they reflect throughout | |
597 the Greek spirit and outlook. | |
598 <p>From a scientific point of view a very important advantage | |
599 possessed by the Greeks was their remarkable capacity for | |
600 accurate observation. This is attested throughout all periods, | |
601 by the similes in Homer, by vase-paintings, by the ethno- | |
602 graphic data in Herodotus, by the ‘Hippocratean’ medical | |
603 books, by the biological treatises of Aristotle, and by the | |
604 history of Greek astronomy in all its stages. To take two | |
605 commonplace examples. Any person who examines the | |
606 under-side of a horse's hoof, which we call a ‘frog’ and the | |
607 <pb n=6><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
608 Greeks called a ‘swallow’, will agree that the latter is | |
609 the more accurate description. Or again, what exactness | |
610 of perception must have been possessed by the architects and | |
611 workmen to whom we owe the pillars which, seen from below, | |
612 appear perfectly straight, but, when measured, are found to | |
613 bulge out (<G>e)/ntasis</G>). | |
614 <p>A still more essential fact is that the Greeks were a race of | |
615 <I>thinkers.</I> It was not enough for them to know the fact (the | |
616 <G>o(/ti</G>); they wanted to know the why and wherefore (the <G>dia\ ti/</G>), | |
617 and they never rested until they were able to give a rational | |
618 explanation, or what appeared to them to be such, of every | |
619 fact or phenomenon. The history of Greek astronomy fur- | |
620 nishes a good example of this, as well as of the fact that no | |
621 visible phenomenon escaped their observation. We read in | |
622 Cleomedes<note>Cleomedes, <I>De motu circulari</I>, ii. 6, pp. 218 sq.</note> that there were stories of extraordinary lunar | |
623 eclipses having been observed which ‘the more ancient of the | |
624 mathematicians’ had vainly tried to explain; the supposed | |
625 ‘paradoxical’ case was that in which, while the sun appears | |
626 to be still above the western horizon, the <I>eclipsed</I> moon is | |
627 seen to rise in the east. The phenomenon was seemingly | |
628 inconsistent with the recognized explanation of lunar eclipses | |
629 as caused by the entrance of the moon into the earth's | |
630 shadow; how could this be if both bodies were above the | |
631 horizon at the same time? The ‘more ancient’ mathemati- | |
632 cians tried to argue that it was possible that a spectator | |
633 standing on an <I>eminence</I> of the spherical earth might see | |
634 along the generators of a <I>cone</I>, i.e. a little downwards on all | |
635 sides instead of merely in the plane of the horizon, and so | |
636 might see both the sun and the moon although the latter was | |
637 in the earth's shadow. Cleomedes denies this, and prefers to | |
638 regard the whole story of such cases as a fiction designed | |
639 merely for the purpose of plaguing astronomers and philoso- | |
640 phers; but it is evident that the cases had actually been | |
641 observed, and that astronomers did not cease to work at the | |
642 problem until they had found the real explanation, namely | |
643 that the phenomenon is due to atmospheric refraction, which | |
644 makes the sun visible to us though it is actually beneath the | |
645 horizon. Cleomedes himself gives this explanation, observing | |
646 that such cases of atmospheric refraction were especially | |
647 <pb n=7><head>DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY</head> | |
648 noticeable in the neighbourhood of the Black Sea, and com- | |
649 paring the well-known experiment of the ring at the bottom | |
650 of a jug, where the ring, just out of sight when the jug is | |
651 empty, is brought into view when water is poured in. We do | |
652 not know who the ‘more ancient’ mathematicians were who | |
653 were first exercised by the ‘paradoxical’ case; but it seems | |
654 not impossible that it was the observation of this phenomenon, | |
655 and the difficulty of explaining it otherwise, which made | |
656 Anaxagoras and others adhere to the theory that there are | |
657 other bodies besides the earth which sometimes, by their | |
658 interposition, cause lunar eclipses. The story is also a good | |
659 illustration of the fact that, with the Greeks, pure theory | |
660 went hand in hand with observation. Observation gave data | |
661 upon which it was possible to found a theory; but the theory | |
662 had to be modified from time to time to suit observed new | |
663 facts; they had continually in mind the necessity of ‘saving | |
664 the phenomena’ (to use the stereotyped phrase of Greek | |
665 astronomy). Experiment played the same part in Greek | |
666 medicine and biology. | |
667 <p>Among the different Greek stocks the Ionians who settled | |
668 on the coast of Asia Minor were the most favourably situated | |
669 in respect both of natural gifts and of environment for initiat- | |
670 ing philosophy and theoretical science. When the colonizing | |
671 spirit first arises in a nation and fresh fields for activity and | |
672 development are sought, it is naturally the younger, more | |
673 enterprising and more courageous spirits who volunteer to | |
674 leave their homes and try their fortune in new countries; | |
675 similarly, on the intellectual side, the colonists will be at | |
676 least the equals of those who stay at home, and, being the | |
677 least wedded to traditional and antiquated ideas, they will be | |
678 the most capable of striking out new lines. So it was with | |
679 the Greeks who founded settlements in Asia Minor. The | |
680 geographical position of these settlements, connected with the | |
681 mother country by intervening islands, forming stepping- | |
682 stones as it were from the one to the other, kept them in | |
683 continual touch with the mother country; and at the same | |
684 time their geographical horizon was enormously extended by | |
685 the development of commerce over the whole of the Mediter- | |
686 ranean. The most adventurous seafarers among the Greeks | |
687 of Asia Minor, the Phocaeans, plied their trade successfully | |
688 <pb n=8><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
689 as far as the Pillars of Hercules, after they had explored the | |
690 Adriatic sea, the west coast of Italy, and the coasts of the | |
691 Ligurians and Iberians. They are said to have founded | |
692 Massalia, the most important Greek colony in the western | |
693 countries, as early as 600 B. C. Cyrene, on the Libyan coast, | |
694 was founded in the last third of the seventh century. The | |
695 Milesians had, soon after 800 B. C., made settlements on the | |
696 east coast of the Black Sea (Sinope was founded in 785); the | |
697 first Greek settlements in Sicily were made from Euboea and | |
698 Corinth soon after the middle of the eighth century (Syracuse | |
699 734). The ancient acquaintance of the Greeks with the south | |
700 coast of Asia Minor and with Cyprus, and the establishment | |
701 of close relations with Egypt, in which the Milesians had a | |
702 large share, belongs to the time of the reign of Psammetichus I | |
703 (664-610 B. C.), and many Greeks had settled in that country. | |
704 <p>The free communications thus existing with the whole of | |
705 the known world enabled complete information to be collected | |
706 with regard to the different conditions, customs and beliefs | |
707 prevailing in the various countries and races; and, in parti- | |
708 cular, the Ionian Greeks had the inestimable advantage of | |
709 being in contact, directly and indirectly, with two ancient | |
710 civilizations, the Babylonian and the Egyptian. | |
711 <p>Dealing, at the beginning of the <I>Metaphysics</I>, with the | |
712 evolution of science, Aristotle observes that science was | |
713 preceded by the arts. The arts were invented as the result | |
714 of general notions gathered from experience (which again was | |
715 derived from the exercise of memory); those arts naturally | |
716 came first which are directed to supplying the necessities of | |
717 life, and next came those which look to its amenities. It was | |
718 only when all such arts had been established that the sciences, | |
719 which do not aim at supplying the necessities or amenities | |
720 of life, were in turn discovered, and this happened first in | |
721 the places where men began to have leisure. This is why | |
722 the mathematical arts were founded in Egypt; for there the | |
723 priestly caste was allowed to be at leisure. Aristotle does not | |
724 here mention Babylon; but, such as it was, Babylonian | |
725 science also was the monopoly of the priesthood. | |
726 <p>It is in fact true, as Gomperz says,<note><I>Griechische Denker</I>, i, pp. 36, 37.</note> that the first steps on | |
727 the road of scientific inquiry were, so far as we know from | |
728 <pb n=9><head>DEVELOPMENT OF PHILOSOPHY</head> | |
729 history, never accomplished except where the existence of an | |
730 organized caste of priests and scholars secured the necessary | |
731 industry, with the equally indispensable continuity of tradi- | |
732 tion. But in those very places the first steps were generally | |
733 the last also, because the scientific doctrines so attained tend, | |
734 through their identification with religious prescriptions, to | |
735 become only too easily, like the latter, mere lifeless dogmas. | |
736 It was a fortunate chance for the unhindered spiritual de- | |
737 velopment of the Greek people that, while their predecessors | |
738 in civilization had an organized priesthood, the Greeks never | |
739 had. To begin with, they could exercise with perfect freedom | |
740 their power of unerring eclecticism in the assimilation of every | |
741 kind of lore. ‘It remains their everlasting glory that they | |
742 discovered and made use of the serious scientific elements in | |
743 the confused and complex mass of exact observations and | |
744 superstitious ideas which constitutes the priestly wisdom of | |
745 the East, and threw all the fantastic rubbish on one side.’<note>Cumont, <I>Neue Jahrbücher</I>, xxiv, 1911, p. 4.</note> | |
746 For the same reason, while using the earlier work of | |
747 Egyptians and Babylonians as a basis, the Greek genius | |
748 could take an independent upward course free from every | |
749 kind of restraint and venture on a flight which was destined | |
750 to carry it to the highest achievements. | |
751 <p>The Greeks then, with their ‘unclouded clearness of mind’ | |
752 and their freedom of thought, untrammelled by any ‘Bible’ or | |
753 its equivalent, were alone capable of creating the sciences as | |
754 they did create them, i.e. as living things based on sound first | |
755 principles and capable of indefinite development. It was a | |
756 great boast, but a true one, which the author of the <I>Epinomis</I> | |
757 made when he said, ‘Let us take it as an axiom that, whatever | |
758 the Greeks take from the barbarians, they bring it to fuller | |
759 perfection’.<note><I>Epinomis</I>, 987 D.</note> He has been speaking of the extent to which | |
760 the Greeks had been able to explain the relative motions and | |
761 speeds of the sun, moon and planets, while admitting that | |
762 there was still much progress to be made before absolute | |
763 certainty could be achieved. He adds a characteristic sen- | |
764 tence, which is very relevant to the above remarks about the | |
765 Greek's free outlook: | |
766 <p>‘Let no Greek ever be afraid that we ought not at any time | |
767 to study things divine because we are mortal. We ought to | |
768 <pb n=10><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
769 maintain the very contrary view, namely, that God cannot | |
770 possibly be without intelligence or be ignorant of human | |
771 nature: rather he knows that, when he teaches them, men | |
772 will follow him and learn what they are taught. And he is | |
773 of course perfectly aware that he does teach us, and that we | |
774 learn, the very subject we are now discussing, number and | |
775 counting; if he failed to know this, he would show the | |
776 greatest want of intelligence; the God we speak of would in | |
777 fact not know himself, if he took it amiss that a man capable | |
778 of learning should learn, and if he did not rejoice unreservedly | |
779 with one who became good by divine influence.’<note><I>Epinomis</I>, 988 A.</note> | |
780 <p>Nothing could well show more clearly the Greek conviction | |
781 that there could be no opposition between religion and scien- | |
782 tific truth, and therefore that there could be no impiety in the | |
783 pursuit of truth. The passage is a good parallel to the state- | |
784 ment attributed to Plato that <G>qeo\s a)ei\ lewmetrei=</G>. | |
785 <C>Meaning and classification of mathematics.</C> | |
786 <p>The words <G>maqh/mata</G> and <G>maqhmatiko/s</G> do not appear to | |
787 have been definitely appropriated to the special meaning of | |
788 mathematics and mathematicians or things mathematical until | |
789 Aristotle's time. With Plato <G>ma/qhma</G> is quite general, mean- | |
790 ing any subject of instruction or study; he speaks of <G>kala\ | |
791 maqh/mata</G>, good subjects of instruction, as of <G>kala\ e)pithdeu/- | |
792 mata</G>, good pursuits, of women's subjects as opposed to men's, | |
793 of the Sophists hawking sound <G>maqh/mata</G>; what, he asks in | |
794 the <I>Republic</I>, are the greatest <G>maqh/mata</G>? and he answers that | |
795 the greatest <G>ma/qhma</G> is the Idea of the Good.<note><I>Republic</I>, vi. 505 A.</note> But in the | |
796 <I>Laws</I> he speaks of <G>tri/a maqh/mata</G>, three subjects, as fit for | |
797 freeborn men, the subjects being arithmetic, the science of | |
798 measurement (geometry), and astronomy<note><I>Laws</I>, vii. 817 E.</note>; and no doubt the | |
799 pre-eminent place given to mathematical subjects in his scheme | |
800 of education would have its effect in encouraging the habit of | |
801 speaking of these subjects exclusively as <G>maqh/mata</G>. The | |
802 Peripatetics, we are told, explained the special use of the | |
803 word in this way; they pointed out that, whereas such things | |
804 as rhetoric and poetry and the whole of popular <G>mousikh/</G> can | |
805 be understood even by one who has not learnt them, the sub- | |
806 jects called by the special name of <G>maqh/mata</G> cannot be known | |
807 <pb n=11><head>CLASSIFICATION OF MATHEMATICS</head> | |
808 by any one who has not first gone through a course of instruc- | |
809 tion in them; they concluded that it was for this reason that | |
810 these studies were called <G>maqhmatikh/</G>.<note>Anatolius in Hultsch's Heron, pp. 276-7 (Heron, vol. iv, Heiberg, | |
811 p. 160. 18-24).</note> The special use of the | |
812 word <G>maqhmatikh/</G> seems actually to have originated in the | |
813 school of Pythagoras. It is said that the esoteric members | |
814 of the school, those who had learnt the theory of know- | |
815 ledge in its most complete form and with all its elaboration | |
816 of detail, were known as <G>maqhmatikoi/</G>, mathematicians (as | |
817 opposed to the <G>a)kousmatikoi/</G>, the exoteric learners who were | |
818 entrusted, not with the inner theory, but only with the prac- | |
819 tical rules of conduct); and, seeing that the Pythagorean | |
820 philosophy was mostly mathematics, the term might easily | |
821 come to be identified with the mathematical subjects as | |
822 distinct from others. According to Anatolius, the followers | |
823 of Pythagoras are said to have applied the term <G>maqhmatikh/</G> | |
824 more particularly to the two subjects of geometry and | |
825 arithmetic, which had previously been known by their own | |
826 separate names only and not by any common designation | |
827 covering both.<note>Heron, ed. Hultsch, p. 277; vol. iv, p. 160. 24-162. 2, Heiberg.</note> There is also an apparently genuine frag- | |
828 ment of Archytas, a Pythagorean and a contemporary and | |
829 friend of Plato, in which the word <G>maqh/mata</G> appears as | |
830 definitely appropriated to mathematical subjects: | |
831 <p>‘The mathematicians (<G>toi\ peri\ ta\ maqh/mata</G>) seem to me to | |
832 have arrived at correct conclusions, and it is not therefore | |
833 surprising that they have a true conception of the nature of | |
834 each individual thing: for, having reached such correct con- | |
835 clusions regarding the nature of the universe, they were | |
836 bound to see in its true light the nature of particular things | |
837 as well. Thus they have handed down to us clear knowledge | |
838 about the speed of the stars, their risings and settings, and | |
839 about geometry, arithmetic, and sphaeric, and last, not least, | |
840 about music; for these <G>maqh/mata</G> seem to be sisters.’<note>Diels, <I>Vorsokratiker</I>, i<SUP>3</SUP>, pp. 330-1.</note> | |
841 <p>This brings us to the Greek classification of the different | |
842 branches of mathematics. Archytas, in the passage quoted, | |
843 specifies the four subjects of the Pythagorean <I>quadrivium</I>, | |
844 geometry, arithmetic, astronomy, and music (for ‘sphaeric’ | |
845 means astronomy, being the geometry of the sphere con- | |
846 <pb n=12><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
847 sidered solely with reference to the problem of accounting for | |
848 the motions of the heavenly bodies); the same list of subjects | |
849 is attributed to the Pythagoreans by Nicomachus, Theon of | |
850 Smyrna, and Proclus, only in a different order, arithmetic, | |
851 music, geometry, and sphaeric; the idea in this order was | |
852 that arithmetic and music were both concerned with number | |
853 (<G>poso/n</G>), arithmetic with number in itself, music with number | |
854 in relation to something else, while geometry and sphaeric were | |
855 both concerned with magnitude (<G>phli/kon</G>), geometry with mag- | |
856 nitude at rest, sphaeric with magnitude in motion. In Plato's | |
857 curriculum for the education of statesmen the same subjects, | |
858 with the addition of stereometry or solid geometry, appear, | |
859 arithmetic first, then geometry, followed by solid geometry, | |
860 astronomy, and lastly harmonics. The mention of stereometry | |
861 as an independent subject is Plato's own idea; it was, however, | |
862 merely a formal addition to the curriculum, for of course | |
863 solid problems had been investigated earlier, as a part of | |
864 geometry, by the Pythagoreans, Democritus and others. | |
865 Plato's reason for the interpolation was partly logical. Astro- | |
866 nomy treats of the motion of solid bodies. There is therefore | |
867 a gap between plane geometry and astronomy, for, after con- | |
868 sidering plane figures, we ought next to add the third dimen- | |
869 sion and consider solid figures in themselves, before passing | |
870 to the science which deals with such figures in motion. But | |
871 Plato emphasized stereometry for another reason, namely that | |
872 in his opinion it had not been sufficiently studied. ‘The | |
873 properties of solids do not yet seem to have been discovered.’ | |
874 He adds: | |
875 <p>‘The reasons for this are two. First, it is because no State | |
876 holds them in honour that these problems, which are difficult, | |
877 are feebly investigated; and, secondly, those who do investi- | |
878 gate them are in need of a superintendent, without whose | |
879 guidance they are not likely to make discoveries. But, to | |
880 begin with, it is difficult to find such a superintendent, and | |
881 then, even supposing him found, as matters now stand, those | |
882 who are inclined to these researches would be prevented by | |
883 their self-conceit from paying any heed to him.’<note>Plato, <I>Republic</I>, vii. 528 A-C.</note> | |
884 <p>I have translated <G>w(s nu=n e)/xei</G> (‘as matters now stand’) in | |
885 this passage as meaning ‘in present circumstances’, i.e. so | |
886 <pb n=13><head>CLASSIFICATION OF MATHEMATICS</head> | |
887 long as the director has not the authority of the State behind | |
888 him: this seems to be the best interpretation in view of the | |
889 whole context; but it is possible, as a matter of construction, | |
890 to connect the phrase with the preceding words, in which case | |
891 the meaning would be ‘and, even when such a superintendent | |
892 has been found, as is the case at present’, and Plato would | |
893 be pointing to some distinguished geometer among his con- | |
894 temporaries as being actually available for the post. If Plato | |
895 intended this, it would presumably be either Archytas or | |
896 Eudoxus whom he had in mind. | |
897 <p>It is again on a logical ground that Plato made harmonics | |
898 or music follow astronomy in his classification. As astronomy | |
899 is the motion of bodies (<G>fora\ ba/qous</G>) and appeals to the eye, | |
900 so there is a harmonious motion (<G>e)narmo/nios fora/</G>), a motion | |
901 according to the laws of harmony, which appeals to the ear. | |
902 In maintaining the sisterhood of music and astronomy Plato | |
903 followed the Pythagorean view (cf. the passage of Archytas | |
904 above quoted and the doctrine of the ‘harmony of the | |
905 spheres’). | |
906 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Arithmetic and logistic.</I></C> | |
907 <p>By arithmetic Plato meant, not arithmetic in our sense, but | |
908 the science which considers numbers in themselves, in other | |
909 words, what we mean by the Theory of Numbers. He does | |
910 not, however, ignore the art of calculation (arithmetic in our | |
911 sense); he speaks of number and calculation (<G>a)riqmo\n kai\ | |
912 logismo/n</G>) and observes that ‘the art of calculation (<G>logistikh/</G>) | |
913 and arithmetic (<G>a)riqmhtikh/</G>) are both concerned with number’; | |
914 those who have a natural gift for calculation (<G>oi( fu/sei logi- | |
915 stikoi/</G>) have, generally speaking, a talent for learning of all | |
916 kinds, and even those who are slow are, by practice in it, | |
917 made smarter.<note><I>Republic</I>, vii. 522 C, 525 A, 526 B.</note> But the art of calculation (<G>logistikh/</G>) is only | |
918 preparatory to the true science; those who are to govern the | |
919 city are to get a grasp of <G>logistikh/</G>, not in the popular | |
920 sense with a view to use in trade, but only for the purpose of | |
921 knowledge, until they are able to contemplate the nature of | |
922 number in itself by thought alone.<note><I>Ib.</I> vii. 525 B, C.</note> This distinction between | |
923 <G>a)riqmhtikh/</G> (the theory of numbers) and <G>logistikh/</G> (the art of | |
924 <pb n=14><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
925 calculation) was a fundamental one in Greek mathematics. | |
926 It is found elsewhere in Plato,<note>Cf. <I>Gorgias</I>, 451 B, C; <I>Theaetetus</I>, 145 A with 198 A, &c.</note> and it is clear that it was well | |
927 established in Plato's time. Archytas too has <G>logistikh/</G> in | |
928 the same sense; the art of calculation, he says, seems to be far | |
929 ahead of other arts in relation to wisdom or philosophy, nay | |
930 it seems to make the things of which it chooses to treat even | |
931 clearer than geometry does; moreover, it often succeeds even | |
932 where geometry fails.<note>Diels, <I>Vorsokratiker</I>, i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 337. 7-11.</note> But it is later writers on the classification | |
933 of mathematics who alone go into any detail of what <G>logistikh/</G> | |
934 included. Geminus in Proclus, Anatolius in the <I>Variae Collec- | |
935 tiones</I> included in Hultsch's Heron, and the scholiast to Plato's | |
936 <I>Charmides</I> are our authorities. Arithmetic, says Geminus,<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 39. 14-20.</note> is | |
937 divided into the theory of linear numbers, the theory of plane | |
938 numbers, and the theory of solid numbers. It investigates, | |
939 in and by themselves, the species of number as they are succes- | |
940 sively evolved from the unit, the formation of plane numbers, | |
941 similar and dissimilar, and the further progression to the third | |
942 dimension. As for the <G>logistiko/s</G>, it is not in and by themselves | |
943 that he considers the properties of numbers but with refer- | |
944 ence to sensible objects; and for this reason he applies to | |
945 them names adapted from the objects measured, calling some | |
946 (numbers) <G>mhli/ths</G> (from <G>mh=lon</G>, a sheep, or <G>mh=lon</G>, an apple, | |
947 more probably the latter) and others <G>fiali/ths</G> (from <G>fia/lh</G>, | |
948 a bowl).<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 40. 2-5.</note> The scholiast to the <I>Charmides</I> is fuller still:<note>On <I>Charmides</I>, 165 E.</note> | |
949 <p>‘Logistic is the science which deals with numbered things, | |
950 not numbers; it does not take number in its essence, | |
951 but it presupposes 1 as unit, and the numbered object as | |
952 number, e.g. it regards 3 as a triad, 10 as a decad, and | |
953 applies the theorems of arithmetic to such (particular) cases. | |
954 Thus it is logistic which investigates on the one hand what | |
955 Archimedes called the cattle-problem, and on the other hand | |
956 <I>melites</I> and <I>phialites</I> numbers, the latter relating to bowls, | |
957 the former to flocks (he should probably have said “apples”); | |
958 in other kinds too it investigates the numbers of sensible | |
959 bodies, treating them as absolute (<G>w(s peri\ telei/wn</G>). Its sub- | |
960 ject-matter is everything that is numbered. Its branches | |
961 include the so-called Greek and Egyptian methods in multi- | |
962 plications and divisions,<note>See Chapter II, pp. 52-60.</note> the additions and decompositions | |
963 <pb n=15><head>ARITHMETIC AND LOGISTIC</head> | |
964 of fractions; which methods it uses to explore the secrets of | |
965 the theory of triangular and polygonal numbers with reference | |
966 to the subject-matter of particular problems.’ | |
967 <p>The content of <I>logistic</I> is for the most part made fairly | |
968 clear by the scholia just quoted. First, it comprised the | |
969 ordinary arithmetical operations, addition, subtraction, multi- | |
970 plication, division, and the handling of fractions; that is, it | |
971 included the elementary parts of what we now call <I>arithmetic.</I> | |
972 Next, it dealt with problems about such things as sheep | |
973 (or apples), bowls, &c.; and here we have no difficulty in | |
974 recognizing such problems as we find in the arithmetical | |
975 epigrams included in the Greek anthology. Several of them | |
976 are problems of dividing a number of apples or nuts among | |
977 a certain number of persons; others deal with the weights of | |
978 bowls, or of statues and their pedestals, and the like; as a | |
979 rule, they involve the solution of simple equations with one | |
980 unknown, or easy simultaneous equations with two unknowns; | |
981 two are indeterminate equations of the first degree to be solved | |
982 in positive integers. From Plato's allusions to such problems | |
983 it is clear that their origin dates back, at least, to the fifth | |
984 century B. C. The cattle-problem attributed to Archimedes | |
985 is of course a much more difficult problem, involving the | |
986 solution of a ‘Pellian’ equation in numbers of altogether | |
987 impracticable size. In this problem the sums of two pairs | |
988 of unknowns have to be respectively a square and a tri- | |
989 angular number; the problem would therefore seem to | |
990 correspond to the description of those involving ‘the theory | |
991 of triangular and polygonal numbers’. Tannery takes the | |
992 allusion in the last words to be to problems in indeter- | |
993 minate analysis like those of Diophantus's <I>Arithmetica.</I> The | |
994 difficulty is that most of Diophantus's problems refer to num- | |
995 bers such that their sums, differences, &c., are <I>squares</I>, whereas | |
996 the scholiast mentions only triangular and polygonal numbers. | |
997 Tannery takes squares to be included among polygons, or to | |
998 have been accidentally omitted by a copyist. But there is | |
999 only one use in Diophantus's <I>Arithmetica</I> of a triangular | |
1000 number (in IV. 38), and none of a polygonal number; nor can | |
1001 the <G>trigw/nous</G> of the scholiast refer, as Tannery supposes, to | |
1002 right-angled triangles with sides in rational numbers (the | |
1003 main subject of Diophantus's Book VI), the use of the mascu- | |
1004 <pb n=16><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
1005 line showing that only <G>trigw/nous a)riqmou/s</G>, triangular <I>num- | |
1006 bers</I>, can be meant. Nevertheless there can, I think, be no | |
1007 doubt that Diophantus's <I>Arithmetica</I> belongs to <I>Logistic.</I> | |
1008 Why then did Diophantus call his thirteen books <I>Arithmetica</I>? | |
1009 The explanation is probably this. Problems of the Diophan- | |
1010 tine type, like those of the arithmetical epigrams, had pre- | |
1011 viously been enunciated of concrete numbers (numbers of | |
1012 apples, bowls, &c.), and one of Diophantus's problems (V. 30) | |
1013 is actually in epigram form, and is about measures of wine | |
1014 with prices in drachmas. Diophantus then probably saw that | |
1015 there was no reason why such problems should refer to | |
1016 numbers of any one particular thing rather than another, but | |
1017 that they might more conveniently take the form of finding | |
1018 numbers <I>in the abstract</I> with certain properties, alone or in | |
1019 combination, and therefore that they might claim to be part | |
1020 of arithmetic, the abstract science or theory of numbers. | |
1021 <p>It should be added that to the distinction between <I>arith- | |
1022 metic</I> and <I>logistic</I> there corresponded (up to the time of | |
1023 Nicomachus) different methods of treatment. With rare | |
1024 exceptions, such as Eratosthenes's <G>ko/skinon</G>, or sieve, a device | |
1025 for separating out the successive prime numbers, the theory | |
1026 of numbers was only treated in connexion with geometry, and | |
1027 for that reason only the geometrical form of proof was used, | |
1028 whether the figures took the form of dots marking out squares, | |
1029 triangles, gnomons, &c. (as with the early Pythagoreans), or of | |
1030 straight lines (as in Euclid VII-IX); even Nicomachus did | |
1031 not entirely banish geometrical considerations from his work, | |
1032 and in Diophantus's treatise on Polygonal Numbers, of which | |
1033 a fragment survives, the geometrical form of proof is used. | |
1034 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>Geometry and geodaesia.</I></C> | |
1035 <p>By the time of Aristotle there was separated out from | |
1036 geometry a distinct subject, <G>gewdaisi/a</G>, <I>geodesy</I>, or, as we | |
1037 should say, <I>mensuration</I>, not confined to land-measuring, but | |
1038 covering generally the practical measurement of surfaces and | |
1039 volumes, as we learn from Aristotle himself,<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> B. 2, 997 b 26, 31.</note> as well as from | |
1040 a passage of Geminus quoted by Proclus.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 39. 20-40. 2.</note> | |
1041 <pb n=17><head>PHYSICAL SUBJECTS AND THEIR BRANCHES</head> | |
1042 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Physical subjects, mechanics, optics, harmonics, | |
1043 astronomy, and their branches.</I></C> | |
1044 <p>In applied mathematics Aristotle recognizes optics and | |
1045 mechanics in addition to astronomy and harmonics. He calls | |
1046 optics, harmonics, and astronomy the <I>more physical</I> (branches) | |
1047 of mathematics,<note>Arist. <I>Phys.</I> ii. 2, 194 a 8.</note> and observes that these subjects and mechanics | |
1048 depend for the proofs of their propositions upon the pure | |
1049 mathematical subjects, optics on geometry, mechanics on | |
1050 geometry or stereometry, and harmonics on arithmetic; simi- | |
1051 larly, he says, <I>Phaenomena</I> (that is, observational astronomy) | |
1052 depend on (theoretical) astronomy.<note>Arist. <I>Anal. Post.</I> i. 9, 76 a 22-5; i. 13, 78 b 35-9.</note> | |
1053 <p>The most elaborate classification of mathematics is that given | |
1054 by Geminus.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 38. 8-12.</note> After arithmetic and geometry, which treat of | |
1055 non-sensibles, or objects of pure thought, come the branches | |
1056 which are concerned with sensible objects, and these are six | |
1057 in number, namely mechanics, astronomy, optics, geodesy, | |
1058 <I>canonic</I> (<G>kanonikh/</G>), <I>logistic.</I> Anatolius distinguishes the same | |
1059 subjects but gives them in the order <I>logistic</I>, geodesy, optics, | |
1060 <I>canonic</I>, mechanics, astronomy.<note>See Heron, ed. Hultsch, p. 278; ed. Heiberg, iv, p. 164.</note> <I>Logistic</I> has already been | |
1061 discussed. Geodesy too has been described as <I>mensuration</I>, | |
1062 the practical measurement of surfaces and volumes; as | |
1063 Geminus says, it is the function of geodesy to measure, not | |
1064 a cylinder or a cone (as such), but heaps as cones, and tanks | |
1065 or pits as cylinders.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 39. 23-5.</note> <I>Canonic</I> is the theory of the musical | |
1066 intervals as expounded in works like Euclid's <G>katatomh\ | |
1067 kano/nos</G>, <I>Division of the canon.</I> | |
1068 <p>Optics is divided by Geminus into three branches.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 40. 13-22.</note> (1) The | |
1069 first is Optics proper, the business of which is to explain why | |
1070 things appear to be of different sizes or different shapes | |
1071 according to the way in which they are placed and the | |
1072 distances at which they are seen. Euclid's <I>Optics</I> consists | |
1073 mainly of propositions of this kind; a circle seen edge- | |
1074 wise looks like a straight line (Prop. 22), a cylinder seen by | |
1075 one eye appears less than half a cylinder (Prop. 28); if the | |
1076 line joining the eye to the centre of a circle is perpendicular | |
1077 <pb n=18><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
1078 to the plane of the circle, all its diameters will look equal | |
1079 (Prop. 34), but if the joining line is neither perpendicular to | |
1080 the plane of the circle nor equal to its radius, diameters with | |
1081 which it makes unequal angles will appear unequal (Prop. 35); | |
1082 if a visible object remains stationary, there exists a locus such | |
1083 that, if the eye is placed at any point on it, the object appears | |
1084 to be of the same size for every position of the eye (Prop. 38). | |
1085 (2) The second branch is <I>Catoptric</I>, or the theory of mirrors, | |
1086 exemplified by the <I>Catoptrica</I> of Heron, which contains, | |
1087 e.g., the theorem that the angles of incidence and reflexion | |
1088 are equal, based on the assumption that the broken line | |
1089 connecting the eye and the object reflected is a minimum. | |
1090 (3) The third branch is <G>skhnografikh/</G> or, as we might say, | |
1091 <I>scene-painting</I>, i.e. applied perspective. | |
1092 <p>Under the general term of mechanics Geminus<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 41. 3-18.</note> dis- | |
1093 tinguishes (1) <G>o)rganopoii+kh/</G>, the art of making engines of war | |
1094 (cf. Archimedes's reputed feats at the siege of Syracuse and | |
1095 Heron's <G>belopoii+ka/</G>), (2) <G>qaumatopoii+kh/</G>, the art of making | |
1096 <I>wonderful machines</I>, such as those described in Heron's | |
1097 <I>Pneumatica</I> and <I>Automatic Theatre</I>, (3) Mechanics proper, | |
1098 the theory of centres of gravity, equilibrium, the mechanical | |
1099 powers, &c., (4) <I>Sphere-making</I>, the imitation of the move- | |
1100 ments of the heavenly bodies; Archimedes is said to have | |
1101 made such a sphere or orrery. Last of all,<note><I>Ib.</I>, pp. 41. 19-42. 6.</note> astronomy | |
1102 is divided into (1) <G>gnwmonikh/</G>, the art of the gnomon, or the | |
1103 measurement of time by means of the various forms of | |
1104 sun-dials, such as those enumerated by Vitruvius,<note>Vitruvius, <I>De architectura</I>, ix. 8.</note> (2) <G>metewro- | |
1105 skopikh/</G>, which seems to have included, among other things, | |
1106 the measurement of the heights at which different stars cross | |
1107 the meridian, (3) <G>dioptrikh/</G>, the use of the <I>dioptra</I> for the | |
1108 purpose of determining the relative positions of the sun, | |
1109 moon, and stars. | |
1110 <C>Mathematics in Greek education.<note>Cf. Freeman, <I>Schools of Hellas</I>, especially pp. 100-7, 159.</note></C> | |
1111 <p>The elementary or primary stage in Greek education lasted | |
1112 till the age of fourteen. The main subjects were letters | |
1113 (reading and writing followed by dictation and the study of | |
1114 <pb n=19><head>MATHEMATICS IN GREEK EDUCATION</head> | |
1115 literature), music and gymnastics; but there is no reasonable | |
1116 doubt that practical arithmetic (in our sense), including | |
1117 weights and measures, was taught along with these subjects. | |
1118 Thus, at the stage of spelling, a common question asked of | |
1119 the pupils was, How many letters are there in such and such | |
1120 a word, e.g. Socrates, and in what order do they come?<note>Xenophon, <I>Econ.</I> viii. 14.</note> This | |
1121 would teach the cardinal and ordinal numbers. In the same | |
1122 connexion Xenophon adds, ‘Or take the case of numbers. | |
1123 Some one asks, What is twice five?’<note>Xenophon, <I>Mem.</I> iv. 4. 7.</note> This indicates that | |
1124 counting was a part of learning letters, and that the multipli- | |
1125 cation table was a closely connected subject. Then, again, | |
1126 there were certain games, played with cubic dice or knuckle- | |
1127 bones, to which boys were addicted and which involved some | |
1128 degree of arithmetical skill. In the game of knucklebones in | |
1129 the <I>Lysis</I> of Plato each boy has a large basket of them, and | |
1130 the loser in each game pays so many over to the winner.<note>Plato, <I>Lysis</I>, 206 E; cf. Apollonius Rhodius, iii. 117.</note> | |
1131 Plato connects the art of playing this game with mathe- | |
1132 matics<note><I>Phaedrus</I>, 274 C-D.</note>; so too he associates <G>pettei/a</G> (games with <G>pessoi/</G>, | |
1133 somewhat resembling draughts or chess) with arithmetic in | |
1134 general.<note><I>Politicus</I>, 299 E; <I>Laws</I>, 820 C.</note> When in the <I>Laws</I> Plato speaks of three subjects | |
1135 fit for freeborn citizens to learn, (1) calculation and the science | |
1136 of numbers, (2) mensuration in one, two and three dimen- | |
1137 sions, and (3) astronomy in the sense of the knowledge of | |
1138 the revolutions of the heavenly bodies and their respective | |
1139 periods, he admits that profound and accurate knowledge of | |
1140 these subjects is not for people in general but only for a few.<note><I>Laws</I>, 817 E-818 A.</note> | |
1141 But it is evident that practical arithmetic was, after letters | |
1142 and the lyre, to be a subject for all, so much of arithmetic, | |
1143 that is, as is necessary for purposes of war, household | |
1144 management, and the work of government. Similarly, enough | |
1145 astronomy should be learnt to enable the pupil to understand | |
1146 the calendar.<note><I>Ib.</I> 809 C, D.</note> Amusement should be combined with instruc- | |
1147 tion so as to make the subjects attractive to boys. Plato was | |
1148 much attracted by the Egyptian practice in this matter:<note><I>Ib.</I> 819 A-C.</note> | |
1149 <p>‘Freeborn boys should learn so much of these things as | |
1150 vast multitudes of boys in Egypt learn along with their | |
1151 <pb n=20><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
1152 letters. First there should be calculations specially devised | |
1153 as suitable for boys, which they should learn with amusement | |
1154 and pleasure, for example, distributions of apples or garlands | |
1155 where the same number is divided among more or fewer boys, | |
1156 or (distributions) of the competitors in boxing or wrestling | |
1157 matches on the plan of drawing pairs with byes, or by taking | |
1158 them in consecutive order, or in any of the usual ways<note>The Greek of this clause is,(<G>dianomai\</G>) <G>puktw=n kai\ palaistw=n e)fedrei/as | |
1159 te kai\ sullh/xews e)n me/rei kai\ e)fexh=s kai\ w(s pefu/kasi gi/gnesqai</G>. So far as | |
1160 I can ascertain, <G>e)n me/rei</G> (by itself) and <G>e)fexh=s</G> have always been taken | |
1161 as indicating alternative methods, ‘in turn and in consecutive order’. | |
1162 But it is impossible to get any satisfactory contrast of meaning between | |
1163 ‘in turn’ and ‘in consecutive order’. It is clear to me that we have | |
1164 here merely an instance of Plato's habit of changing the order of words | |
1165 for effect, and that <G>e)n me/rei</G> must be taken with the genitives <G>e)fedrei/as kai\ | |
1166 sullh/xews</G>; i.e. we must translate as if we had <G>e)n e)fedrei/as te kai\ sullh/- | |
1167 xews me/rei</G>, ‘<I>by way of</I> byes and drawings’. This gives a proper distinction | |
1168 between (1) drawings with byes and (2) taking competitors in consecutive | |
1169 order.</note>; and | |
1170 again there should be games with bowls containing gold, | |
1171 bronze, and silver (coins?) and the like mixed together,<note>It is difficult to decide between the two possible interpretations | |
1172 of the phrase <G>fia/las a(/ma xrusou= kai\ xalkou= kai\ a)rgu/rou kai\ toiou/twn tinw=n | |
1173 a)/llwn kerannu/ntes</G>. It may mean ‘taking bowls made of gold, bronze, | |
1174 silver and other metals mixed together (in certain proportions)’ or | |
1175 ‘filling bowls with gold, bronze, silver, &c. (<I>sc.</I> objects such as coins) | |
1176 mixed together’. The latter version seems to agree best with <G>pai/zontes</G> | |
1177 (making a game out of the process) and to give the better contrast to | |
1178 ‘distributing the bowls <I>as wholes</I>’ (<G>o(/las pws diadido/ntes</G>).</note> or the | |
1179 bowls may be distributed as undivided units; for, as I said, | |
1180 by connecting with games the essential operations of practical | |
1181 arithmetic, you supply the boy with what will be useful to | |
1182 him later in the ordering of armies, marches and campaigns, | |
1183 as well as in household management; and in any case you | |
1184 make him more useful to himself and more wide awake. | |
1185 Then again, by calculating measurements of things which | |
1186 have length, breadth, and depth, questions on all of which | |
1187 the natural condition of all men is one of ridiculous and dis- | |
1188 graceful ignorance, they are enabled to emerge from this | |
1189 state.’ | |
1190 <p>It is true that these are Plato's ideas of what elementary | |
1191 education <I>should</I> include; but it can hardly be doubted that | |
1192 such methods were actually in use in Attica. | |
1193 <p>Geometry and astronomy belonged to secondary education, | |
1194 which occupied the years between the ages of fourteen and | |
1195 eighteen. The pseudo-Platonic <I>Axiochus</I> attributes to Prodi- | |
1196 cus a statement that, when a boy gets older, i. e. after he has | |
1197 <pb n=21><head>MATHEMATICS IN GREEK EDUCATION</head> | |
1198 passed the primary stage under the <I>paidagogos, grammatistes</I>, | |
1199 and <I>paidotribes</I>, he comes under the tyranny of the ‘critics’, | |
1200 the <I>geometers</I>, the tacticians, and a host of other masters.<note><I>Axiochus</I>, 366 E.</note> | |
1201 Teles, the philosopher, similarly, mentions arithmetic and | |
1202 geometry among the plagues of the lad.<note>Stobaeus, <I>Ecl.</I> iv. 34, 72 (vol. v, p. 848, 19 sq., Wachsmuth and | |
1203 Hense).</note> It would appear | |
1204 that geometry and astronomy were newly introduced into the | |
1205 curriculum in the time of Isocrates. ‘I am so far’, he says,<note>See Isocrates, <I>Panathenaicus</I>, §§ 26-8 (238 b-d); <G>*peri\ a)ntido/sews</G>, | |
1206 §§ 261-8.</note> | |
1207 ‘from despising the instruction which our ancestors got, that | |
1208 I am a supporter of that which has been established in our | |
1209 time, I mean geometry, astronomy, and the so-called eristic | |
1210 dialogues.’ Such studies, even if they do no other good, | |
1211 keep the young out of mischief, and in Isocrates's opinion no | |
1212 other subjects could have been invented more useful and | |
1213 more fitting; but they should be abandoned by the time that | |
1214 the pupils have reached man's estate. Most people, he says, | |
1215 think them idle, since (say they) they are of no use in private | |
1216 or public affairs; moreover they are forgotten directly because | |
1217 they do not go with us in our daily life and action, nay, they | |
1218 are altogether outside everyday needs. He himself, however, | |
1219 is far from sharing these views. True, those who specialize in | |
1220 such subjects as astronomy and geometry get no good from | |
1221 them unless they choose to teach them for a livelihood; and if | |
1222 they get too deeply absorbed, they become unpractical and | |
1223 incapable of doing ordinary business; but the study of these | |
1224 subjects up to the proper point trains a boy to keep his atten- | |
1225 tion fixed and not to allow his mind to wander; so, being | |
1226 practised in this way and having his wits sharpened, he will be | |
1227 capable of learning more important matters with greater ease | |
1228 and speed. Isocrates will not give the name of ‘philosophy’ to | |
1229 studies like geometry and astronomy, which are of no imme- | |
1230 diate use for producing an orator or man of business; they | |
1231 are rather means of training the mind and a preparation for | |
1232 philosophy. They are a more manly discipline than the sub- | |
1233 jects taught to boys, such as literary study and music, but in | |
1234 other respects have the same function in making them quicker | |
1235 to learn greater and more important subjects. | |
1236 <pb n=22><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
1237 <p>It would appear therefore that, notwithstanding the in- | |
1238 fluence of Plato, the attitude of cultivated people in general | |
1239 towards mathematics was not different in Plato's time from | |
1240 what it is to-day. | |
1241 <p>We are told that it was one of the early Pythagoreans, | |
1242 unnamed, who first taught geometry for money: ‘One of the | |
1243 Pythagoreans lost his property, and when this misfortune | |
1244 befell him he was allowed to make money by teaching | |
1245 geometry.’<note>Iamblichus, <I>Vit. Pyth.</I> 89.</note> We may fairly conclude that Hippocrates of | |
1246 Chios, the first writer of <I>Elements</I>, who also made himself | |
1247 famous by his quadrature of lunes, his reduction of the | |
1248 duplication of the cube to the problem of finding two mean | |
1249 proportionals, and his proof that the areas of circles are in | |
1250 the ratio of the squares on their diameters, also taught for | |
1251 money and for a like reason. One version of the story is that | |
1252 he was a merchant, but lost all his property through being | |
1253 captured by a pirate vessel. He then came to Athens to | |
1254 prosecute the offenders and, during a long stay, attended | |
1255 lectures, finally attaining such proficiency in geometry that | |
1256 he tried to square the circle.<note>Philoponus on Arist. <I>Phys.</I>, p. 327 b 44-8, Brandis.</note> Aristotle has the different | |
1257 version that he allowed himself to be defrauded of a large | |
1258 sum by custom-house officers at Byzantium, thereby proving, | |
1259 in Aristotle's opinion, that, though a good geometer, he was | |
1260 stupid and incompetent in the business of ordinary life.<note><I>Eudemian Ethics</I>, H. 14, 1247 a 17.</note> | |
1261 <p>We find in the Platonic dialogues one or two glimpses of | |
1262 mathematics being taught or discussed in school- or class- | |
1263 rooms. In the <I>Erastae</I><note><I>Erastae</I>, 32 A, B.</note> Socrates is represented as going into | |
1264 the school of Dionysius (Plato's own schoolmaster<note>Diog. L. iii. 5.</note>) and find- | |
1265 ing two lads earnestly arguing some point of astronomy; | |
1266 whether it was Anaxagoras or Oenopides whose theories they | |
1267 were discussing he could not catch, but they were drawing | |
1268 circles and imitating some inclination or other with their | |
1269 hands. In Plato's <I>Theaetetus</I><note><I>Theaetetus</I>, 147 D-148 B.</note> we have the story of Theodorus | |
1270 lecturing on surds and proving separately, for the square root | |
1271 of every non-square number from 3 to 17, that it is incom- | |
1272 mensurable with 1, a procedure which set Theaetetus and the | |
1273 <pb n=23><head>MATHEMATICS IN GREEK EDUCATION</head> | |
1274 younger Socrates thinking whether it was not possible to | |
1275 comprehend all such surds under one definition. In these two | |
1276 cases we have advanced or selected pupils discussing among | |
1277 themselves the subject of lectures they had heard and, in the | |
1278 second case, trying to develop a theory of a more general | |
1279 character. | |
1280 <p>But mathematics was not only taught by regular masters | |
1281 in schools; the Sophists, who travelled from place to place | |
1282 giving lectures, included mathematics (arithmetic, geometry, | |
1283 and astronomy) in their very wide list of subjects. Theo- | |
1284 dorus, who was Plato's teacher in mathematics and is | |
1285 described by Plato as a master of geometry, astronomy, | |
1286 <I>logistic</I> and music (among other subjects), was a pupil of | |
1287 Protagoras, the Sophist, of Abdera.<note><I>Theaetetus</I>, 164 E, 168 E.</note> Protagoras himself, if we | |
1288 may trust Plato, did not approve of mathematics as part of | |
1289 secondary education; for he is made to say that | |
1290 <p>‘the other Sophists maltreat the young, for, at an age when | |
1291 the young have escaped the arts, they take them against their | |
1292 will and plunge them once more into the arts, teaching them | |
1293 the art of calculation, astronomy, geometry, and music—and | |
1294 here he cast a glance at Hippias—whereas, if any one comes | |
1295 to me, he will not be obliged to learn anything except what | |
1296 he comes for.’<note><I>Protagoras</I>, 318 D, E.</note> | |
1297 <p>The Hippias referred to is of course Hippias of Elis, a really | |
1298 distinguished mathematician, the inventor of a curve known | |
1299 as the <I>quadratrix</I> which, originally intended for the solution | |
1300 of the problem of trisecting any angle, also served (as the | |
1301 name implies) for squaring the circle. In the <I>Hippias Minor</I><note><I>Hippias Minor</I>, pp. 366 C-368 E.</note> | |
1302 there is a description of Hippias's varied accomplishments. | |
1303 He claimed, according to this passage, to have gone once to | |
1304 the Olympian festival with everything that he wore made by | |
1305 himself, ring and seal (engraved), oil-bottle, scraper, shoes, | |
1306 clothes, and a Persian girdle of expensive type; he also took | |
1307 poems, epics, tragedies, dithyrambs, and all sorts of prose | |
1308 works. He was a master of the science of calculation | |
1309 (<I>logistic</I>), geometry, astronomy, ‘rhythms and harmonies | |
1310 and correct writing’. He also had a wonderful system of | |
1311 mnemonics enabling him, if he once heard a string of fifty | |
1312 <pb n=24><head>INTRODUCTORY</head> | |
1313 names, to remember them all. As a detail, we are told that | |
1314 he got no fees for his lectures in Sparta, and that the Spartans | |
1315 could not endure lectures on astronomy or geometry or | |
1316 <I>logistic</I>; it was only a small minority of them who could | |
1317 even count; what they liked was history and archaeology. | |
1318 <p>The above is almost all that we know of the part played | |
1319 by mathematics in the Greek system of education. Plato's | |
1320 attitude towards mathematics was, as we have seen, quite | |
1321 exceptional; and it was no doubt largely owing to his influence | |
1322 and his inspiration that mathematics and astronomy were so | |
1323 enormously advanced in his school, and especially by Eudoxus | |
1324 of Cnidos and Heraclides of Pontus. But the popular atti- | |
1325 tude towards Plato's style of lećturing was not encouraging. | |
1326 There is a story of a lecture of his on ‘The Good’ which | |
1327 Aristotle was fond of telling.<note>Aristoxenus, <I>Harmonica</I>, ii <I>ad init.</I></note> The lecture was attended by | |
1328 a great crowd, and ‘every one went there with the idea that | |
1329 he would be put in the way of getting one or other of the | |
1330 things in human life which are usually accounted good, such | |
1331 as Riches, Health, Strength, or, generally, any extraordinary | |
1332 gift of fortune. But when they found that Plato discoursed | |
1333 about mathematics, arithmetic, geometry, and astronomy, and | |
1334 finally declared the One to be the Good, no wonder they were | |
1335 altogether taken by surprise; insomuch that in the end some | |
1336 of the audience were inclined to scoff at the whole thing, while | |
1337 others objected to it altogether.’ Plato, however, was able to | |
1338 pick and choose his pupils, and he could therefore insist on | |
1339 compliance with the notice which he is said to have put over | |
1340 his porch, ‘Let no one unversed in geometry enter my doors’;<note>Tzetzes, <I>Chiliad.</I> viii. 972.</note> | |
1341 and similarly Xenocrates, who, after Speusippus, succeeded to | |
1342 the headship of the school, could turn away an applicant for | |
1343 admission who knew no geometry with the words, ‘Go thy | |
1344 way, for thou hast not the means of getting a grip of | |
1345 philosophy’.<note>Diog. L. iv. 10.</note> | |
1346 <p>The usual attitude towards mathematics is illustrated by | |
1347 two stories of Pythagoras and Euclid respectively. Pytha- | |
1348 goras, we are told,<note>Iamblichus, <I>Vit. Pyth.</I> c. 5.</note> anxious as he was to transplant to his own | |
1349 country the system of education which he had seen in opera- | |
1350 <pb n=25><head>MATHEMATICS IN GREEK EDUCATION</head> | |
1351 tion in Egypt, and the study of mathematics in particular, | |
1352 could get none of the Samians to listen to him. He adopted | |
1353 therefore this plan of communicating his arithmetic and | |
1354 geometry, so that it might not perish with him. Selecting | |
1355 a young man who from his behaviour in gymnastic exercises | |
1356 seemed adaptable and was withal poor, he promised him that, | |
1357 if he would learn arithmetic and geometry systematically, he | |
1358 would give him sixpence for each ‘figure’ (proposition) that he | |
1359 mastered. This went on until the youth got interested in | |
1360 the subject, when Pythagoras rightly judged that he would | |
1361 gladly go on without the sixpence. He therefore hinted | |
1362 that he himself was poor and must try to earn his daily bread | |
1363 instead of doing mathematics; whereupon the youth, rather | |
1364 than give up the study, volunteered to pay sixpence himself | |
1365 to Pythagoras for each proposition. We must presumably | |
1366 connect with this story the Pythagorean motto, ‘a figure and | |
1367 a platform (from which to ascend to the next higher step), not | |
1368 a figure and sixpence’.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 84. 16.</note> | |
1369 <p>The other story is that of a pupil who began to learn | |
1370 geometry with Euclid and asked, when he had learnt one | |
1371 proposition, ‘What advantage shall I get by learning these | |
1372 things?’ And Euclid called the slave and said, ‘Give him | |
1373 sixpence, since he must needs gain by what he learns.’ | |
1374 <p>We gather that the education of kings in the Macedonian | |
1375 period did not include much geometry, whether it was Alex- | |
1376 ander who asked Menaechmus, or Ptolemy who asked Euclid, | |
1377 for a short-cut to geometry, and got the reply that ‘for travel- | |
1378 ling over the country there are royal roads and roads for com- | |
1379 mon citizens: but in geometry there is one road for all’.<note>Stobaeus, <I>Ecl.</I> ii. 31, 115 (vol. ii, p. 228, 30, Wachsmuth).</note> | |
1380 <pb> | |
1381 <C>II</C> | |
1382 <C>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION AND ARITH- | |
1383 METICAL OPERATIONS</C> | |
1384 <C>The decimal system.</C> | |
1385 <p>THE Greeks, from the earliest historical times, followed the | |
1386 decimal system of numeration, which had already been | |
1387 adopted by civilized peoples all the world over. There are, | |
1388 it is true, traces of <I>quinary</I> reckoning (reckoning in terms of | |
1389 five) in very early times; thus in Homer <G>pempa/zein</G> (to ‘five’) | |
1390 is used for ‘to count’.<note>Homer, <I>Od</I>. iv. 412.</note> But the counting by fives was pro- | |
1391 bably little more than auxiliary to counting by tens; five was | |
1392 a natural halting-place between the unit and ten, and the use | |
1393 of five times a particular power of ten as a separate category | |
1394 intermediate between that power and the next was found | |
1395 convenient in the earliest form of numerical symbolism estab- | |
1396 lished in Greece, just as it was in the Roman arithmetical | |
1397 notation. The reckoning by five does not amount to such a | |
1398 variation of the decimal system as that which was in use | |
1399 among the Celts and Danes; these peoples had a vigesimal | |
1400 system, traces of which are still left in the French <I>quatre- | |
1401 vingts, quatre-vingt-treize</I>, &c., and in our <I>score</I>, three-score | |
1402 and ten, twenty-one, &c. | |
1403 <p>The natural explanation of the origin of the decimal system, | |
1404 as well as of the quinary and vigesimal variations, is to | |
1405 suppose that they were suggested by the primitive practice of | |
1406 reckoning with the fingers, first of one hand, then of both | |
1407 together, and after that with the ten toes in addition (making | |
1408 up the 20 of the vigesimal system). The subject was mooted | |
1409 in the Aristotelian <I>Problems</I>,<note>XV. 3, 910 b 23-911 a 4.</note> where it is asked: | |
1410 <p>‘Why do all men, whether barbarians or Greeks, count up | |
1411 to ten, and not up to any other number, such as 2, 3, 4, or 5, | |
1412 so that, for example, they do not say one-<I>plus</I>-five (for 6), | |
1413 <pb n=27><head>THE DECIMAL SYSTEM</head> | |
1414 two-<I>plus</I>-five (for 7), as they say one-<I>plus</I>-ten (<G>e(/ndeka</G>, for 11), | |
1415 two-<I>plus</I>-ten (<G>dw/deka</G>, for 12), while on the other hand they | |
1416 do not go beyond ten for the first halting-place from which to | |
1417 start again repeating the units? For of course any number | |
1418 is the next before it <I>plus</I> 1, or the next before that <I>plus</I> 2, | |
1419 and so with those preceding numbers; yet men fixed definitely | |
1420 on ten as the number to count up to. It cannot have been | |
1421 chance; for chance will not account for the same thing being | |
1422 done always: what is always and universally done is not due | |
1423 to chance but to some natural cause.’ | |
1424 <p>Then, after some fanciful suggestions (e.g. that 10 is a | |
1425 ‘perfect number’), the author proceeds: | |
1426 <p>‘Or is it because men were born with ten fingers and so, | |
1427 because they possess the equivalent of pebbles to the number | |
1428 of their own fingers, come to use this number for counting | |
1429 everything else as well?’ | |
1430 <p>Evidence for the truth of this latter view is forthcoming in | |
1431 the number of cases where the word for 5 is either the same | |
1432 as, or connected with, the word for ‘hand’. Both the Greek | |
1433 <G>xei/r</G> and the Latin <I>manus</I> are used to denote ‘a number’ (of | |
1434 men). The author of the so-called geometry of Boëtius says, | |
1435 moreover, that the ancients called all the numbers below ten | |
1436 by the name <I>digits</I> (‘fingers’).<note>Boëtius, <I>De Inst. Ar.</I>, &c., p. 395. 6-9, Friedlein.</note> | |
1437 <p>Before entering on a description of the Greek numeral signs | |
1438 it is proper to refer briefly to the systems of notation used | |
1439 by their forerunners in civilization, the Egyptians and | |
1440 Babylonians. | |
1441 <C>Egyptian numerical notation.</C> | |
1442 <p>The Egyptians had a purely decimal system, with the signs | |
1443 <G>*i</G> for the unit, <FIG> for 10, <FIG> for 100, <FIG> for 1,000, <FIG> for 10,000, | |
1444 <FIG> for 100,000. The number of each denomination was | |
1445 expressed by repeating the sign that number of times; when | |
1446 the number was more than 4 or 5, lateral space was saved by | |
1447 arranging them in two or three rows, one above the other. | |
1448 The greater denomination came before the smaller. Numbers | |
1449 could be written from left to right or from right to left; in | |
1450 the latter case the above signs were turned the opposite way. | |
1451 The fractions in use were all submultiples or single aliquot | |
1452 <pb n=28><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
1453 parts, except 2/3, which had a special sign <FIG> or <FIG>; the | |
1454 submultiples were denoted by writing <FIG> over the corre- | |
1455 sponding whole number; thus | |
1456 <MATH><FIG>=1/23, <FIG>=1/324 <FIG>=1/2190</MATH>. | |
1457 <C>Babylonian systems.</C> | |
1458 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Decimal</I>. (<G>b</G>) <I>Sexagesimal</I>.</C> | |
1459 <p>The ancient Babylonians had two systems of numeration. | |
1460 The one was purely decimal based on the following signs. | |
1461 The simple wedge <FIG> represented the unit, which was repeated | |
1462 up to nine times: where there were more than three, they | |
1463 were placed in two or three rows, e.g. <MATH><FIG>=4, <FIG>=7</MATH>. 10 | |
1464 was represented by <FIG>; 11 would therefore be <FIG>. 100 had | |
1465 the compound sign <FIG>, and 1000 was expressed as 10 hun- | |
1466 dreds, by <FIG>, the prefixed <FIG> (10) being here multiplicative. | |
1467 Similarly, the <FIG> was regarded as one sign, and <FIG> de- | |
1468 noted not 2000 but 10000, the prefixed <FIG> being again multi- | |
1469 plicative. Multiples of 10000 seem to have been expressed | |
1470 as multiples of 1000; at least, 120000 seems to be attested | |
1471 in the form 100.1000 + 20.1000. The absence of any definite | |
1472 unit above 1000 (if it was really absent) must have rendered | |
1473 the system very inconvenient as a means of expressing large | |
1474 numbers. | |
1475 <p>Much more interesting is the second Babylonian system, | |
1476 the sexagesimal. This is found in use on the Tables of | |
1477 Senkereh, discovered by W. K. Loftus in 1854, which may go | |
1478 back as far as the time between 2300 and 1600 B.C. In this | |
1479 system numbers above the units (which go from 1 to 59) are | |
1480 arranged according to powers of 60. 60 itself was called | |
1481 <I>sussu</I> (=<I>soss</I>), 60<SUP>2</SUP> was called <I>sar</I>, and there was a name also | |
1482 (<I>ner</I>) for the intermediate number 10.60=600. The multi- | |
1483 ples of the several powers of 60, 60<SUP>2</SUP>, 60<SUP>3</SUP>, &c., contained in the | |
1484 number to be written down were expressed by means of the | |
1485 same wedge-notation as served for the units, and the multi- | |
1486 ples were placed in columns side by side, the columns being | |
1487 appropriated to the successive powers of 60. The unit-term | |
1488 <pb n=29><head>EGYPTIAN AND BABYLONIAN NOTATION</head> | |
1489 was followed by similar columns appropriated, in order, to the | |
1490 successive submultiples 1/60, 1/60<SUP>2</SUP>, &c., the number of sixtieths, | |
1491 &c., being again denoted by the ordinary wedge-numbers. | |
1492 Thus <FIG> represents <MATH>44.60<SUP>2</SUP>+26.60+40=160,000; | |
1493 <FIG>=27.60<SUP>2</SUP>+21.60+36=98,496</MATH>. Simi- | |
1494 larly we find <FIG> representing 30+30/60 and <FIG> | |
1495 representing 30+27/60; the latter case also shows that the | |
1496 Babylonians, on occasion, used the subtractive plan, for the 27 | |
1497 is here written 30 <I>minus</I> 3. | |
1498 <p>The sexagesimal system only required a definite symbol | |
1499 for 0 (indicating the absence of a particular denomination), | |
1500 and a fixed arrangement of columns, to become a complete | |
1501 position-value system like the Indian. With a sexagesimal | |
1502 system 0 would occur comparatively seldom, and the Tables of | |
1503 Senkereh do not show a case; but from other sources it | |
1504 appears that a gap often indicated a zero, or there was a sign | |
1505 used for the purpose, namely <G>c</G>, called the ‘divider’. The | |
1506 inconvenience of the system was that it required a multipli- | |
1507 cation table extending from 1 times 1 to 59 times 59. It had, | |
1508 however, the advantage that it furnished an easy means of | |
1509 expressing very large numbers. The researches of H. V. | |
1510 Hilprecht show that 60<SUP>4</SUP>=12,960,000 played a prominent | |
1511 part in Babylonian arithmetic, and he found a table con- | |
1512 taining certain quotients of the number <MATH><FIG> | |
1513 =60<SUP>8</SUP>+10.60<SUP>7</SUP></MATH>, or 195,955,200,000,000. Since the number of | |
1514 units of any denomination are expressed in the purely decimal | |
1515 notation, it follows that the latter system preceded the sexa- | |
1516 gesimal. What circumstances led to the adoption of 60 as | |
1517 the base can only be conjectured, but it may be presumed that | |
1518 the authors of the system were fully alive to the convenience | |
1519 of a base with so many divisors, combining as it does the | |
1520 advantages of 12 and 10. | |
1521 <C>Greek numerical notation.</C> | |
1522 <p>To return to the Greeks. We find, in Greek inscriptions of | |
1523 all dates, instances of numbers and values written out in full; | |
1524 but the inconvenience of this longhand, especially in such | |
1525 things as accounts, would soon be felt, and efforts would be | |
1526 made to devise a scheme for representing numbers more | |
1527 <pb n=30><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
1528 concisely by means of conventional signs of some sort. The | |
1529 Greeks conceived the original idea of using the letters of the | |
1530 ordinary Greek alphabet for this purpose. | |
1531 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>The ‘Herodianic’ signs</I>.</C> | |
1532 <p>There were two main systems of numerical notation in use in | |
1533 classical times. The first, known as the Attic system and | |
1534 used for cardinal numbers exclusively, consists of the set of | |
1535 signs somewhat absurdly called ‘Herodianic’ because they are | |
1536 described in a fragment<note>Printed in the Appendix to Stephanus's <I>Thesaurus</I>, vol. viii.</note> attributed to Herodian, a gram- | |
1537 marian of the latter half of the second century A.D. The | |
1538 authenticity of the fragment is questioned, but the writer | |
1539 says that he has seen the signs used in Solon's laws, where | |
1540 the prescribed pecuniary fines were stated in this notation, | |
1541 and that they are also to be found in various ancient inscrip- | |
1542 tions, decrees and laws. These signs cannot claim to be | |
1543 numerals in the proper sense; they are mere compendia or | |
1544 abbreviations; for, except in the case of the stroke <G>*i</G> repre- | |
1545 senting a unit, the signs are the first letters of the full words | |
1546 for the numbers, and all numbers up to 50000 were repre- | |
1547 sented by combinations of these signs. <G>*i</G>, representing the | |
1548 unit, may be repeated up to four times; <G><*></G> (the first letter of | |
1549 <G>pe/nte</G>) stands for 5, <G>*d</G> (the first letter of <G>de/ka</G>) for 10, <G>*h</G> | |
1550 (representing <G>e(/katon</G>) for 100, <G>*x</G> (<G>xi/lioi</G>) for 1000, and <G>*m</G> | |
1551 (<G>mu/rioi</G>) for 10000. The half-way numbers 50, 500, 5000 | |
1552 were expressed by combining <G><*></G> (five) with the other signs | |
1553 respectively; <G><*></G>, <G><*></G>, <G><*></G>, made up of <G><*></G> (5) and <G>*d</G> (10), = 50; | |
1554 <G><*></G>, made up of <G><*></G> and <G>*h</G>,=500; <G><*></G>=5000; and <G><*></G>=50000. | |
1555 There are thus six simple and four compound symbols, and all | |
1556 other numbers intermediate between those so represented are | |
1557 made up by juxtaposition on an additive basis, so that each | |
1558 of the simple signs may be repeated not more than four times; | |
1559 the higher numbers come before the lower. For example, | |
1560 <G><*>*i</G>=6, <G>*d*i*i*i*i</G>=14, <G>*h<*></G>=105, <G>*x*x*x*x<*>*h*h*h*h<*>*d*d*d*d<*>*i*i*i*i</G> | |
1561 =4999. Instances of this system of notation are found in | |
1562 Attic inscriptions from 454 to about 95 B.C. Outside Attica | |
1563 the same system was in use, the precise form of the symbols | |
1564 varying with the form of the letters in the local alphabets. | |
1565 Thus in Boeotian inscriptions <G><*></G> or <G><*></G>=50, <G><*></G>=100, <G><*></G>=500, | |
1566 <pb n=31><head>THE ‘HERODIANIC’ SIGNS</head> | |
1567 <G><*></G>=1000, <G><*></G>=5000; and <G><*><*><*><*><*><*><*>*i*i*i</G>=5823. But, | |
1568 in consequence of the political influence of Athens, the Attic | |
1569 system, sometimes with unimportant modifications, spread to | |
1570 other states.<note>Larfeld, <I>Handbuch der griechischen Epigraphik</I>, vol. i, p. 417.</note> | |
1571 <p>In a similar manner compendia were used to denote units | |
1572 of coinage or of weight. Thus in Attica <G>*t</G>=<G>ta/lanton</G> (6000 | |
1573 drachmae), <G>*m</G>=<G>mna=</G> (1000 drachmae), <G>*s</G> or <G><*></G>=<G>stath/r</G> | |
1574 (1/3000th of a talent or 2 drachmae), <G><*></G>=<G>draxmh/</G>, <G>*i</G>=<G>o)bolo/s</G> | |
1575 (1/6th of a drachma), <G><*></G>=<G>h(miwbe/lion</G> (1/12th of a drachma), | |
1576 &c; or <G>*t</G>=<G>tetarthmo/rion</G> (1/4th of an obol or 1/24th of a | |
1577 drachma), <G>*x</G>=<G>xalkou=s</G> (1/8th of an obol or 1/48th of a | |
1578 drachma). Where a number of one of these units has to be | |
1579 expressed, the sign for the unit is written on the left of that | |
1580 for the number; thus <G><*><*>*d*i</G>=61 drachmae. The two com- | |
1581 pendia for the numeral and the unit are often combined into | |
1582 one; e.g. <G><*></G>, <G><*></G>=5 talents, <G><*></G>=50 talents, <G><*></G>=100 talents, | |
1583 <G><*></G>=500 talents, <G><*></G>=1000 talents, <G><*></G>=10 minas, <G><*></G>=5 drach- | |
1584 mae, <G><*></G>, <G><*></G>, <G><*></G>=10 staters, &c. | |
1585 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The ordinary alphabetic numerals</I>.</C> | |
1586 <p>The second main system, used for all kinds of numerals, is | |
1587 that with which we are familiar, namely the alphabetic | |
1588 system. The Greeks took their alphabet from the Phoe- | |
1589 nicians. The Phoenician alphabet contained 22 letters, and, | |
1590 in appropriating the different signs, the Greeks had the | |
1591 happy inspiration to use for the vowels, which were not | |
1592 written in Phoenician, the signs for certain spirants for which | |
1593 the Greeks had no use; Aleph became A, He was used for E, | |
1594 Yod for I, and Ayin for O; when, later, the long E was | |
1595 differentiated, Cheth was used, <G><*></G> or <G>*h</G>. Similarly they | |
1596 utilized superfluous signs for sibilants. Out of Zayin and | |
1597 Samech they made the letters <G>*z</G> and <G>*e</G>. The remaining two | |
1598 sibilants were Ssade and Shin. From the latter came the | |
1599 simple Greek <G>*s</G> (although the name Sigma seems to corre- | |
1600 spond to the Semitic Samech, if it is not simply the ‘hissing’ | |
1601 letter, from <G>si/zw</G>). Ssade, a softer sibilant (=<G>ss</G>), also called | |
1602 San in early times, was taken over by the Greeks in the | |
1603 place it occupied after <G><*></G>, and written in the form <G><*></G> or <G><*></G>. | |
1604 The form <G><*></G> (=<G>ss</G>) appearing in inscriptions of Halicarnassus | |
1605 <pb n=32><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
1606 (e.g. <G>*(alikarna<*></G>[<G>e/wn</G>]=<G>*(alikarnacce/wn</G>) and Teos ([<G>q</G>]<G>ala/<*>hs</G>; | |
1607 cf. <G>qa/laccan</G> in another place) seems to be derived from some | |
1608 form of Ssade; this <G><*></G>, after its disappearance from the | |
1609 literary alphabet, remained as a numeral, passing through | |
1610 the forms <G><*></G>, <G><*></G>, <G><*></G>, <G><*></G>, and <G><*></G> to the fifteenth century form <G><*></G>, | |
1611 to which in the second half of the seventeenth century the | |
1612 name Sampi was applied (whether as being the San which | |
1613 followed Pi or from its resemblance to the cursive form of <G>p</G>). | |
1614 The original Greek alphabetalso retained the Phoenician Vau (<G><*></G>) | |
1615 in its proper place between E and Z and the Koppa=Qoph (<G>O|</G>) | |
1616 immediately before P. The Phoenician alphabet ended with | |
1617 T; the Greeks first added <G><*></G>, derived from Vau apparently | |
1618 (notwithstanding the retention of <G><*></G>), then the letters <G>*f</G>, <G>*x</G>, <G>*y</G> | |
1619 and, still later, <G>*w</G>. The 27 letters used for numerals are | |
1620 divided into three sets of nine each; the first nine denote | |
1621 the units, 1, 2, 3, &c., up to 9; the second nine the tens, from | |
1622 10 to 90; and the third nine the hundreds, from 100 to 900. | |
1623 The following is the scheme: | |
1624 <table> | |
1625 <tr><td><G>*a</G> =1</td><td><G>*i</G>=10</td><td><G>*p</G> =100</td></tr> | |
1626 <tr><td><G>*b</G> =2</td><td><G>*k</G>=20</td><td><G>*s</G> =200</td></tr> | |
1627 <tr><td><G>*g</G> =3</td><td><G>*l</G>=30</td><td><G>*t</G> =300</td></tr> | |
1628 <tr><td><G>*d</G> =4</td><td><G>*m</G>=40</td><td><G>*u</G> =400</td></tr> | |
1629 <tr><td><G>*e</G> =5</td><td><G>*n</G>=50</td><td><G>*f</G> =500</td></tr> | |
1630 <tr><td><G><*></G>[<G>s</G>]=6</td><td><G>*c</G>=60</td><td><G>*x</G> =600</td></tr> | |
1631 <tr><td><G>*z</G> =7</td><td><G>*o</G>=70</td><td><G>*y</G> =700</td></tr> | |
1632 <tr><td><G>*h</G> =8</td><td><G>*p</G>=80</td><td><G>*w</G> =800</td></tr> | |
1633 <tr><td><G>*q</G> =9</td><td><G>O|</G>=90</td><td><G>*t</G>[<G><*></G>] =900</td></tr> | |
1634 </table> | |
1635 <p>The sixth sign in the first column (<G><*></G>) is a form of the | |
1636 digamma <*>. It came, in the seventh and eighth centuries | |
1637 A. D., to be written in the form <G><*></G> and then, from its similarity | |
1638 to the cursive <G>s</G> (=<G>st</G>), was called Stigma. | |
1639 <p>This use of the letters of the alphabet as numerals was | |
1640 original with the Greeks; they did not derive it from the | |
1641 Phoenicians, who never used their alphabet for numerical | |
1642 purposes but had separate signs for numbers. The earliest | |
1643 occurrence of numerals written in this way appears to be in | |
1644 a Halicarnassian inscription of date not long after 450 B.C. | |
1645 Two caskets from the ruins of a famous mausoleum built at | |
1646 Halicarnassus in 351 B.C., which are attributed to the time | |
1647 of Mausolus, about 350 B.C., are inscribed with the letters | |
1648 <pb n=33><head>THE ORDINARY ALPHABETIC NUMERALS</head> | |
1649 <G>*y*n*d</G>=754 and <G>*sO|*g</G>=293. A list of priests of Poseidon | |
1650 at Halicarnassus, attributable to a date at least as early as the | |
1651 fourth century, is preserved in a copy of the second or first | |
1652 century, and this copy, in which the numbers were no doubt | |
1653 reproduced from the original list, has the terms of office of the | |
1654 several priests stated on the alphabetical system. Again, a | |
1655 stone inscription found at Athens and perhaps belonging to | |
1656 the middle of the fourth century B.C. has, in five fragments | |
1657 of columns, numbers in tens and units expressed on the same | |
1658 system, the tens on the right and the units on the left. | |
1659 <p>There is a difference of opinion as to the approximate date | |
1660 of the actual formulation of the alphabetical system of | |
1661 numerals. According to one view, that of Larfeld, it must | |
1662 have been introduced much earlier than the date (450 B.C. or | |
1663 a little later) of the Halicarnassus inscription, in fact as early | |
1664 as the end of the eighth century, the place of its origin being | |
1665 Miletus. The argument is briefly this. At the time of the | |
1666 invention of the system all the letters from <G>*a</G> to <G>*w</G>, including | |
1667 <G><*></G> and <G>O|</G> in their proper places, were still in use, while | |
1668 Ssade (<G><*></G>, the double <I>ss</I>) had dropped out; this is why the | |
1669 last-named sign (afterwards <G><*></G>) was put at the end. If | |
1670 <G><*></G> (=6) and <G>O|</G> (=90) had been no longer in use as letters, | |
1671 they too would have been put, like Ssade, at the end. The | |
1672 place of origin of the numeral system must have been one in | |
1673 which the current alphabet corresponded to the content and | |
1674 order of the alphabetic numerals. The order of the signs | |
1675 <G>*f</G>, <G>*x</G>, <G>*y</G> shows that it was one of the <I>Eastern</I> group of | |
1676 alphabets. These conditions are satisfied by one alphabet, | |
1677 and one only, that of Miletus, at a stage which still recognized | |
1678 the Vau (<G><*></G>) as well as the Koppa (<G>O|</G>). The <G>O|</G> is found along | |
1679 with the so-called complementary letters including <G>*w</G>, the | |
1680 latest of all, in the oldest inscriptions of the Milesian colony | |
1681 Naucratis (about 650 B.C.); and, although there are no | |
1682 extant Milesian inscriptions containing the <G><*></G>, there is at all | |
1683 events one very early example of <G><*></G> in Ionic, namely <G>*)aga- | |
1684 sile/<*>o</G> (<G>*)agasilh/<*>ou</G>) on a vase in the Boston (U.S.) Museum | |
1685 of Fine Arts belonging to the end of the eighth or (at latest) | |
1686 the middle of the seventh century. Now, as <G>*w</G> is fully | |
1687 established at the date of the earliest inscriptions at Miletus | |
1688 (about 700 B.C.) and Naucratis (about 650 B.C.), the earlier | |
1689 <pb n=34><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
1690 extension of the alphabet by the letters <G>*f *x *y</G> must have | |
1691 taken place not later than 750 B.C. Lastly, the presence in | |
1692 the alphabet of the Vau indicates a time which can hardly | |
1693 be put later than 700 B.C. The conclusion is that it was | |
1694 about this time, if not earlier, that the numerical alphabet | |
1695 was invented. | |
1696 <p>The other view is that of Keil, who holds that it originated | |
1697 in Dorian Caria, perhaps at Halicarnassus itself, about | |
1698 550-425 B.C., and that it was artificially put together by | |
1699 some one who had the necessary knowledge to enable him | |
1700 to fill up his own alphabet, then consisting of twenty-four | |
1701 letters only, by taking over <G><*></G> and <G>O|</G> from other alphabets and | |
1702 putting them in their proper places, while he completed the | |
1703 numeral series by adding <G><*></G> at the end.<note><I>Hermes</I>, 29, 1894, p. 265 sq.</note> Keil urges, as | |
1704 against Larfeld, that it is improbable that <G><*></G> and <G>*w</G> ever | |
1705 existed together in the Milesian alphabet. Larfeld's answer<note>Larfeld, <I>op. cit.</I>, i, p. 421.</note> | |
1706 is that, although <G><*></G> had disappeared from ordinary language | |
1707 at Miletus towards the end of the eighth century, we cannot | |
1708 say exactly when it disappeared, and even if it was practically | |
1709 gone at the time of the formulation of the numerical alphabet, | |
1710 it would be in the interest of instruction in schools, where | |
1711 Homer was read, to keep the letter as long as possible in the | |
1712 official alphabet. On the other hand, Keil's argument is open | |
1713 to the objection that, if the Carian inventor could put the | |
1714 <G><*></G> and <G>O|</G> into their proper places in the series, he would hardly | |
1715 have failed to put the Ssade <G><*></G> in its proper place also, instead | |
1716 of at the end, seeing that <G><*></G> is found in Caria itself, namely | |
1717 in a Halicarnassus (Lygdamis) inscription of about 453 B.C., | |
1718 and also in Ionic Teos about 476 B.C.<note><I>Ib.</I>, i, p. 358.</note> (see pp. 31-2 above). | |
1719 <p>It was a long time before the alphabetic numerals found | |
1720 general acceptance. They were not officially used until the | |
1721 time of the Ptolemies, when it had become the practice to write, | |
1722 in inscriptions and on coins, the year of the reign of the ruler | |
1723 for the time being. The conciseness of the signs made them | |
1724 particularly suitable for use on coins, where space was limited. | |
1725 When coins went about the world, it was desirable that the | |
1726 notation should be uniform, instead of depending on local | |
1727 alphabets, and it only needed the support of some paramount | |
1728 <pb n=35><head>THE ORDINARY ALPHABETIC NUMERALS</head> | |
1729 political authority to secure the final triumph of the alphabetic | |
1730 system. The alphabetic numerals are found at Alexandria | |
1731 on coins of Ptolemy II, Philadelphus, assigned to 266 B.C. | |
1732 A coin with the inscription <G>*)alexa/ndrou *k*d</G> (twenty-fourth | |
1733 year after Alexander's death) belongs, according to Keil, to | |
1734 the end of the third century.<note><I>Hermes</I>, 29, 1894, p. 276 <I>n</I>.</note> A very old Graeco-Egyptian | |
1735 papyrus (now at Leyden, No. 397), ascribed to 257 B.C., | |
1736 contains the number <G>kq</G>=29. While in Boeotia the Attic | |
1737 system was in use in the middle of the third century, along | |
1738 with the corresponding local system, it had to give way about | |
1739 200 B.C. to the alphabetic system, as is shown by an inventory | |
1740 from the temple of Amphiaraus at Oropus<note>Keil in <I>Hermes</I>, 25, 1890, pp. 614-15.</note>; we have here | |
1741 the first official use of the alphabetic system in Greece proper. | |
1742 From this time Athens stood alone in retaining the archaic | |
1743 system, and had sooner or later to come into line with other | |
1744 states. The last certainly attested use of the Attic notation | |
1745 in Athens was about 95 B.C.; the alphabetic numerals were | |
1746 introduced there some time before 50 B.C., the first example | |
1747 belonging to the time of Augustus, and by A.D. 50 they were | |
1748 in official use. | |
1749 <p>The two systems are found side by side in a number of | |
1750 papyrus-rolls found at Herculaneum (including the treatise | |
1751 of Philodemus <I>De pietate</I>, so that the rolls cannot be older than | |
1752 40 or 50 B.C.); these state on the title page, after the name of | |
1753 the author, the number of books in alphabetic numerals, and | |
1754 the number of lines in the Attic notation, e.g. <G>*e*r*i*k*o*u*p*o*u <*> | |
1755 *r*e*p*i <*> *f*u*s*e*w*s <*> *i*e a)riq</G> . . <G>*x*x*x*h*h</G> (where <G>*i*e</G> = 15 and | |
1756 <G>*x*x*x*h*h</G> = 3200), just as we commonly use Roman figures | |
1757 to denote <I>Books</I> and Arabic figures for <I>sections</I> or <I>lines</I>.<note>Reference should be made, in passing, to another, <I>quasi</I>-numerical, | |
1758 use of the letters of the ordinary alphabet, as current at the time, for | |
1759 numbering particular things. As early as the fifth century we find in | |
1760 a Locrian bronze-inscription the letters A to <FIG> (including <G><*></G> then and | |
1761 there current) used to distinguish the nine paragraphs of the text. At | |
1762 the same period the Athenians, instead of following the old plan of | |
1763 writing out ordinal numbers in full, adopted the more convenient device | |
1764 of denoting them by the letters of the alphabet. In the oldest known | |
1765 example <G>o(/ros</G> K indicated ‘boundary stone No. 10’; and in the fourth | |
1766 century the tickets of the ten panels of jurymen were marked with the | |
1767 letters A to K. In like manner the Books in certain works of Aristotle | |
1768 (the <I>Ethics, Metaphysics, Politics</I>, and <I>Topics</I>) were at some time | |
1769 numbered on the same principle; so too the Alexandrine scholars | |
1770 (about 280 B.C.) numbered the twenty-four Books of Homer with the | |
1771 letters A to <G>*w</G>. When the number of objects exceeded 24, doubled | |
1772 letters served for continuing the series, as AA, BB, &c. For example, | |
1773 a large quantity of building-stones have been found; among these are | |
1774 stones from the theatre at the Piraeus marked AA, BB, &c., and again | |
1775 AA|BB, BB|BB, &c. when necessary. Sometimes the numbering by | |
1776 double letters was on a different plan, the letter A denoting the full | |
1777 number of the first set of letters (24); thus AP would be <MATH>24+17=41</MATH>.</note> | |
1778 <pb n=36><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
1779 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Mode of writing numbers in the ordinary alphabetic | |
1780 notation</I>.</C> | |
1781 <p>Where, in the alphabetical notation, the number to be | |
1782 written contained more than one denomination, say, units | |
1783 with tens, or with tens and hundreds, the higher numbers | |
1784 were, as a rule, put before the lower. This was generally the | |
1785 case in European Greece; on the other hand, in the inscrip- | |
1786 tions of Asia Minor, the smaller number comes first, i. e. the | |
1787 letters are arranged in alphabetical order. Thus 111 may be | |
1788 represented either by <G>*p*i*a</G> or by <G>*a*i*p</G>; the arrangement is | |
1789 sometimes mixed, as <G>*p*a*i</G>. The custom of writing the numbers | |
1790 in descending order became more firmly established in later | |
1791 times through the influence of the corresponding Roman | |
1792 practice.<note>Larfeld, <I>op. cit.</I>, i, p. 426.</note> | |
1793 <p>The alphabetic numerals sufficed in themselves to express | |
1794 all numbers from 1 to 999. For thousands (up to 9000) the | |
1795 letters were used again with a distinguishing mark; this was | |
1796 generally a sloping stroke to the left, e.g. <G>*/a</G> or <G>*<SUB>'</SUB>a</G>=1000, | |
1797 but other forms are also found, e.g. the stroke might be | |
1798 combined with the letter as <G><*></G>=1000 or again <G>*(a</G>=1000, | |
1799 <G>(<*></G>=6000. For tens of thousands the letter <G>*m</G> (<G>mu/rioi</G>) was | |
1800 borrowed from the other system, e.g. 2 myriads would be | |
1801 <G>*b*m</G>, <G>*m*b</G>, or <FIG>. | |
1802 <p>To distinguish letters representing numbers from the | |
1803 letters of the surrounding text different devices are used: | |
1804 sometimes the number is put between dots <FIG> or:, or separ- | |
1805 ated by spaces from the text on both sides of it. In Imperial | |
1806 times distinguishing marks, such as a horizontal stroke above | |
1807 the letter, become common, e.g. <G>h( boulh\ tw=n ―*x</G>, other | |
1808 variations being <G><*></G>, <G><*></G>, <G><*></G> and the like. | |
1809 <p>In the cursive writing with which we are familiar the | |
1810 <pb n=37><head>ORDINARY ALPHABETIC NOTATION</head> | |
1811 orthodox way of distinguishing numerals was by a horizontal | |
1812 stroke above each sign or collection of signs; the following | |
1813 was therefore the scheme (with <G>s</G> substituted for <G><*></G> repre- | |
1814 senting 6, and with <G><*></G>=900 at the end): | |
1815 <table> | |
1816 <tr><td>units (1 to 9)</td><td><G>―a</G>, <G>―b</G>, <G>―g</G>, <G>―d</G>, <G>―e</G>, <G>―s</G>, <G>―z</G>, <G>―h</G>, <G>―q</G>;</td></tr> | |
1817 <tr><td>tens (10 to 90)</td><td><G>―i</G>, <G>―k</G>, <G>―l</G>, <G>―m</G>, <G>―n</G>, <G>―x</G>, <G>―o</G>, <G>―p</G>, <G>―O|</G>;</td></tr> | |
1818 <tr><td>hundreds (100 to 900)</td><td><G>―r</G>, <G>―s</G>, <G>―t</G>, <G>―u</G>, <G>―f</G>, <G>―*x</G>, <G>―*y</G>, <G>―w</G>, <G>―<*></G>;</td></tr> | |
1819 <tr><td>thousands (1000 to 9000)</td><td><G><SUB>'</SUB>―a</G>, <G><SUB>'</SUB>―b</G>, <G><SUB>'</SUB>―g</G>, <G><SUB>'</SUB>―d</G>, <G><SUB>'</SUB>―e</G>, <G><SUB>'</SUB>―s</G>, <G><SUB>'</SUB>―z</G>, | |
1820 <G><SUB>'</SUB>―h</G>, <G><SUB>'</SUB>―q</G>;</td></tr> | |
1821 </table> | |
1822 (for convenience of printing, the horizontal stroke above the | |
1823 sign will hereafter, as a rule, be omitted). | |
1824 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>Comparison of the two systems of numerical notation</I>.</C> | |
1825 <p>The relative merits of the two systems of numerical | |
1826 notation used by the Greeks have been differently judged. | |
1827 It will be observed that the <I>initial</I>-numerals correspond | |
1828 closely to the Roman numerals, except that there is no | |
1829 formation of numbers by subtraction as <G>*i*x</G>, <G>*x<*></G>, <G>*x<*></G>; thus | |
1830 <G>*x*x*x*x<*>*h*h*h*h<*>*d*d*d*d<*>*i*i*i*i</G>=<G>*m*m*m*mDCCCCL*x*x*x*x<*>*i*i*i*i</G> | |
1831 as compared with <G>*m*m*m*mC*m*xC*i*x</G>=4999. The absolute | |
1832 inconvenience of the Roman system will be readily appreci- | |
1833 ated by any one who has tried to read Boëtius (Boëtius | |
1834 would write the last-mentioned number as <G>―*i<*></G>.<G><*><*><*><*><*>*xCV*i*i*i*i</G>). | |
1835 Yet Cantor<note>Cantor, <I>Gesch. d. Math</I>. I<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 129.</note> draws a comparison between the two systems | |
1836 much to the disadvantage of the alphabetic numerals. | |
1837 ‘Instead’, he says, ‘of an advance we have here to do with | |
1838 a decidedly retrograde step, especially so far as its suitability | |
1839 for the further development of the numeral system is con- | |
1840 cerned. If we compare the older “Herodianic” numerals | |
1841 with the later signs which we have called alphabetic numerals, | |
1842 we observe in the latter two drawbacks which do not attach | |
1843 to the former. There now had to be more signs, with values | |
1844 to be learnt by heart; and to reckon with them required | |
1845 a much greater effort of memory. The addition | |
1846 <MATH><G>*d*d*d</G>+<G>*d*d*d*d</G>=<G><*>*d*d</G>(30+40=70)</MATH> | |
1847 could be coordinated in one act of memory with that of | |
1848 <MATH><G>*h*h*h</G>+<G>*h*h*h*h</G>=<G><*>*h*h</G>(300+400=700)</MATH> | |
1849 in so far as the sum of 3 and 4 units of the same kind added | |
1850 <pb n=38><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
1851 up to 5 and 2 units of the same kind. On the other hand | |
1852 <MATH><G>l</G>+<G>m</G>=<G>o</G></MATH> did not at all immediately indicate that <MATH><G>t</G>+<G>u</G>=<G>*y</G></MATH>. | |
1853 The new notation had only one advantage over the other, | |
1854 namely that it took less space. Consider, for instance, 849, | |
1855 which in the “Herodianic” form is <G><*>*h*h*h*d*d*d*d<*>*i*i*i*i</G>, but | |
1856 in the alphabetic system is <G>wmq</G>. The former is more self- | |
1857 explanatory and, for reckoning with, has most important | |
1858 advantages.’ Gow follows Cantor, but goes further and says | |
1859 that ‘the alphabetical numerals were a fatal mistake and | |
1860 hopelessly confined such nascent arithmetical faculty as the | |
1861 Greeks may have possessed’!<note>Gow, <I>A Short History of Greek Mathematics</I>, p. 46.</note> On the other hand, Tannery, | |
1862 holding that the merits of the alphabetic numerals could only | |
1863 be tested by using them, practised himself in their use until, | |
1864 applying them to the whole of the calculations in Archimedes's | |
1865 <I>Measurement of a Circle</I>, he found that the alphabetic nota- | |
1866 tion had practical advantages which he had hardly suspected | |
1867 before, and that the operations took little longer with Greek | |
1868 than with modern numerals.<note>Tannery, <I>Mémoires scientifiques</I> (ed. Heiberg and Zeuthen), i, | |
1869 pp. 200-1.</note> Opposite as these two views are, | |
1870 they seem to be alike based on a misconception. Surely we do | |
1871 not ‘reckon with’ the numeral <I>signs</I> at all, but with the | |
1872 <I>words</I> for the numbers which they represent. For instance, | |
1873 in Cantor's illustration, we do not conclude that the <I>figure</I> 3 | |
1874 and the <I>figure</I> 4 added together make the <I>figure</I> 7; what we | |
1875 do is to say ‘three and four are seven’. Similarly the Greek | |
1876 would not say to himself ‘<G>g</G> and <G>d</G>=<G>z</G>’ but <G>trei=s kai\ te/ssares | |
1877 e(pta/</G>; and, notwithstanding what Cantor says, this <I>would</I> | |
1878 indicate the corresponding addition ‘three hundred and four | |
1879 hundred are seven hundred’, <G>triako/sioi kai\ tetrako/sioi | |
1880 e(ptako/sioi</G>, and similarly with multiples of ten or of 1000 or | |
1881 10000. Again, in using the multiplication table, we say | |
1882 ‘three times four is twelve’, or ‘three multiplied by four = | |
1883 twelve’; the Greek would say <G>tri\s te/ssares</G>, or <G>trei=s e)pi\ | |
1884 te/ssaras, dw/deka</G>, and this would equally indicate that ‘<I>thirty</I> | |
1885 times <I>forty</I> is <I>twelve</I> hundred or one thousand two hundred’, | |
1886 or that ‘<I>thirty</I> times <I>four</I> hundred is <I>twelve</I> thousand or a | |
1887 myriad and two thousand’ (<G>triakonta/kis tessara/konta xi/lioi | |
1888 kai\ diako/sioi</G>, or <G>triakonta/kis tetrako/sioi mu/rioi kai\ disxi/lioi</G>). | |
1889 <pb n=39><head>COMPARISON OF THE TWO SYSTEMS</head> | |
1890 The truth is that in mental calculation (whether the opera- | |
1891 tion be addition, subtraction, multiplication, or division), we | |
1892 reckon with the corresponding <I>words</I>, not with the symbols, | |
1893 and it does not matter a jot to the calculation how we choose | |
1894 to write the figures down. While therefore the alphabetical | |
1895 numerals had the advantage over the ‘Herodianic’ of being | |
1896 so concise, their only disadvantage was that there were more | |
1897 signs (twenty-seven) the meaning of which had to be com- | |
1898 mitted to memory: truly a very slight disadvantage. The | |
1899 one real drawback to the alphabetic system was the absence | |
1900 of a sign for 0 (zero); for the <G>*o</G> for <G>ou)demi/a</G> or <G>ou)de/n</G> which | |
1901 we find in Ptolemy was only used in the notation of sexa- | |
1902 gesimal fractions, and not as part of the numeral system. If | |
1903 there had been a sign or signs to indicate the absence in | |
1904 a number of a particular denomination, e.g. units or tens or | |
1905 hundreds, the Greek symbols could have been made to serve | |
1906 as a position-value system scarcely less effective than ours. | |
1907 For, while the position-values are clear in such a number | |
1908 as 7921 (<G><SUB>'</SUB>z<*>ka</G>), it would only be necessary in the case of | |
1909 such a number as 7021 to show a blank in the proper place | |
1910 by writing, say, <G><SUB>'</SUB>z-ka</G>. Then, following Diophantus's plan | |
1911 of separating any number of myriads by a dot from the | |
1912 thousands, &c., we could write <G>z<*>ka . <SUB>'</SUB>stpd</G> for 79216384 or | |
1913 <G><SUB>'</SUB>z---.-t-d</G> for 70000304, while we could continually add | |
1914 sets of four figures to the left, separating each set from the | |
1915 next following by means of a dot. | |
1916 <C>(<G>e</G>) <I>Notation for large numbers</I>.</C> | |
1917 <p>Here too the orthodox way of writing tens of thousands | |
1918 was by means of the letter <G>*m</G> with the number of myriads | |
1919 above it, e.g. <FIG>=20000, <FIG> <G><SUB>'</SUB>ewoe</G>=71755875 (Aristarchus | |
1920 of Samos); another method was to write <G>*m</G> or <FIG> for the | |
1921 myriad and to put the number of myriads after it, separated | |
1922 by a dot from the remaining thousands, &c., e.g. | |
1923 <FIG> <G>rn.<SUB>'</SUB>z<*>pd</G>=1507984 | |
1924 (Diophantus, IV. 28). Yet another way of expressing myriads | |
1925 was to use the symbol representing the number of myriads | |
1926 with two dots over it; thus <G>a+<SUB>'</SUB>hfo|b</G>=18592 (Heron, <I>Geo- | |
1927 metrica</I>, 17. 33). The word <G>muria/des</G> could, of course, be | |
1928 <pb n=40><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
1929 written in full, e.g. <G>muria/des <SUB>'</SUB>bsoh kai\ <*>ib</G>=22780912 | |
1930 (<I>ib.</I> 17. 34). To express still higher numbers, powers of | |
1931 myriads were used; a myriad (10000) was a <I>first myriad</I> | |
1932 (<G>prw/th muria/s</G>) to distinguish it from a <I>second myriad</I> (<G>deute/ra | |
1933 muria/s</G>) or 10000<SUP>2</SUP>, and so on; the words <G>prw=tai muria/des, | |
1934 deu/terai muria/des</G>, &c., could either be written in full or | |
1935 expressed by <FIG>, &c., respectively; thus <G>deu/terai muria/des | |
1936 is prw=tai</G> (<G>muria/des</G>) <G><SUB>'</SUB>b<*>nh</G> <FIG> <G><SUB>'</SUB>sfx</G>=1629586560 (Dio | |
1937 phantus, V. 8), where <FIG>=<G>mona/des</G> (units) is inserted to | |
1938 distinguish the <G><SUB>'</SUB>b<*>nh</G>, the number of the ‘first myriads’, | |
1939 from the <G><SUB>'</SUB>sfx</G> denoting 6560 <I>units</I>. | |
1940 <C>(i) Apollonius's ‘tetrads’.</C> | |
1941 <p>The latter system is the same as that adopted by Apollonius | |
1942 in an arithmetical work, now lost, the character of which is, | |
1943 however, gathered from the elucidations in Pappus, Book II; | |
1944 the only difference is that Apollonius called his <I>tetrads</I> (sets | |
1945 of four digits) <G>muria/des a(plai=</G>, <G>diplai=</G>, <G>triplai=</G>, &c., ‘simple | |
1946 myriads’, ‘double’, ‘triple’, &c., meaning 10000, 10000<SUP>2</SUP>, | |
1947 10000<SUP>3</SUP>, and so on. The abbreviations for these successive | |
1948 powers in Pappus are <G>m<SUP>a</SUP></G>, <G>m<SUP>b</SUP></G>, <G>m<SUP><*></SUP></G>, &c.; thus <G>m<SUP><*></SUP> <SUB>'</SUB>euxb kai\ m<SUP>b</SUP> <SUB>'</SUB>gx | |
1949 kai\ m<SUP>a</SUP> <SUB>'</SUB>su</G>=5462360064000000. Another, but a less con- | |
1950 venient, method of denoting the successive powers of 10000 | |
1951 is indicated by Nicolas Rhabdas (fourteenth century A.D.) | |
1952 who says that, while a pair of dots above the ordinary | |
1953 numerals denoted the number of myriads, the ‘double | |
1954 myriad’ was indicated by two pairs of dots one above the other, | |
1955 the ‘triple myriad’ by three pairs of dots, and so on. Thus | |
1956 <G><*><SUP>..</SUP></G>=9000000, <G>b<SUP>....</SUP></G>=2(10000)<SUP>2</SUP>, <G>m<SUP>......</SUP></G>=40(10000)<SUP>3</SUP>, and so on. | |
1957 <C>(ii) Archimedes's system (by octads).</C> | |
1958 <p>Yet another special system invented for the purpose of | |
1959 expressing very large numbers is that of Archimedes's | |
1960 <I>Psammites</I> or <I>Sand-reckoner</I>. This goes by <I>octads</I>: | |
1961 <MATH>10000<SUP>2</SUP>=100000000=10<SUP>8</SUP></MATH>, | |
1962 and all the numbers from 1 to 10<SUP>8</SUP> form the <I>first order</I>; | |
1963 the last number, 10<SUP>8</SUP>, of the <I>first order</I> is taken as the unit | |
1964 of the <I>second order</I>, which consists of all the numbers from | |
1965 <pb n=41><head>ARCHIMEDES'S SYSTEM (BY OCTADS)</head> | |
1966 10<SUP>8</SUP>, or 100000000, to 10<SUP>16</SUP>, or 100000000<SUP>2</SUP>; similarly 10<SUP>16</SUP> is | |
1967 taken as the unit of the <I>third order</I>, which consists of all | |
1968 numbers from 10<SUP>16</SUP> to 10<SUP>24</SUP>, and so on, the <I>100000000th order</I> | |
1969 consisting of all the numbers from (100000000)<SUP>99999999</SUP> to | |
1970 (100000000)<SUP>100000000</SUP>, i.e. from 10<SUP>8.(10<SUP>8</SUP>-1)</SUP> to 10<SUP>8.10<SUP>8</SUP></SUP>. The aggre- | |
1971 gate of all the <I>orders</I> up to the 100000000th form the <I>first | |
1972 period</I>; that is, if <I>P</I>&equalse;(100000000)<SUP>10<SUP>8</SUP></SUP>, the numbers of the | |
1973 <I>first period</I> go from 1 to <I>P.</I> Next, <I>P</I> is the unit of the <I>first | |
1974 order</I> of the <I>second period</I>; the <I>first order</I> of the <I>second | |
1975 period</I> then consists of all numbers from <I>P</I> up to 100000000 <I>P</I> | |
1976 or <I>P</I>.10<SUP>8</SUP>; <I>P</I>.10<SUP>8</SUP> is the unit of the <I>second order</I> (of the | |
1977 <I>second period</I>) which ends with (100000000)<SUP>2</SUP> <I>P</I> or <I>P</I>.10<SUP>16</SUP>; | |
1978 <I>P</I>.10<SUP>16</SUP> begins the <I>third order</I> of the <I>second period</I>, and so | |
1979 on; the <I>100000000th order</I> of the <I>second period</I> consists of | |
1980 the numbers from (100000000)<SUP>99999999</SUP> <I>P</I> or <I>P</I>.10<SUP>8.(10<SUP>8</SUP>-1)</SUP> to | |
1981 (100000000)<SUP>100000000</SUP> <I>P</I> or <I>P</I>.10<SUP>8.10<SUP>8</SUP></SUP>, i.e. <I>P</I><SUP>2</SUP>. Again, <I>P</I><SUP>2</SUP> is the | |
1982 unit of the <I>first order</I> of the <I>third period</I>, and so on. The | |
1983 <I>first order</I> of the <I>100000000th period</I> consists of the numbers | |
1984 from <I>P</I><SUP>10<SUP>8</SUP>-1</SUP> to <I>P</I><SUP>10<SUP>8</SUP>-1</SUP>.10<SUP>8</SUP>, the <I>second order</I> of the same | |
1985 <I>period</I> of the numbers from <I>P</I><SUP>10<SUP>8</SUP>-1</SUP>.10<SUP>8</SUP> to <I>P</I><SUP>10<SUP>8</SUP>-1</SUP>.10<SUP>16</SUP>, and so | |
1986 on, the (10<SUP>8</SUP>)th <I>order</I> of the (10<SUP>8</SUP>)th <I>period</I>, or the <I>period</I> | |
1987 itself, ending with <I>P</I><SUP>10<SUP>8</SUP>-1</SUP>.10<SUP>8.10<SUP>8</SUP></SUP>, i.e. <I>P</I><SUP>10<SUP>8</SUP></SUP>. The last number | |
1988 is described by Archimedes as a ‘myriad-myriad units of the | |
1989 myriad-myriadth order of the myriad-myriadth period (<G>ai( | |
1990 muriakismuriosta=s perio/dou muriakismuriostw=n a)riqmw=n mu/riai | |
1991 muria/des</G>)’. This system was, however, a <I>tour de force</I>, and has | |
1992 nothing to do with the ordinary Greek numerical notation. | |
1993 <C>Fractions.</C> | |
1994 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>The Egyptian system</I></C> | |
1995 <p>We now come to the methods of expressing fractions. A | |
1996 fraction may be either a submultiple (an ‘aliquot part’, i.e. | |
1997 a fraction with numerator unity) or an ordinary proper | |
1998 fraction with a number not unity for numerator and a | |
1999 greater number for denominator. The Greeks had a pre- | |
2000 ference for expressing ordinary proper fractions as the sum | |
2001 of two or more submultiples; in this they followed the | |
2002 Egyptians, who always expressed fractions in this way, with | |
2003 the exception that they had a single sign for 2/3, whereas we | |
2004 <pb n=42><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2005 should have expected them to split it up into 1/2+1/6, as 3/4 was | |
2006 split up into 1/2+1/4. The orthodox sign for a submultiple | |
2007 was the letter for the corresponding number (the denomi- | |
2008 nator) but with an accent instead of a horizontal stroke | |
2009 above it; thus <G>g′</G>=1/3, the full expression being <G>g′ me/ros</G>= | |
2010 <G>tri/ton me/ros</G>, a third part (<G>g′</G> is in fact short for <G>tri/tos</G>, so | |
2011 that it is also used for the ordinal number ‘third’ as well | |
2012 as for the fraction 1/3, and similarly with all other accented | |
2013 numeral signs); <G>lb′</G>=1/32, <G>rib′</G>=1/112, &c. There were | |
2014 special signs for 1/2, namely <G>∢′</G> or <G><*>′</G>,<note>It has been suggested that the forms <G><*></G> and <G><*></G> for 1/2 found in | |
2015 inscriptions may perhaps represent half an <G>*o</G>, the sign, at all events | |
2016 in Boeotia, for 1 obol.</note> and for 2/3, namely <G>w′</G>. | |
2017 When a number of submultiples are written one after the | |
2018 other, the sum of them is meant, and similarly when they | |
2019 follow a whole number; e.g. <G>∢′d′</G>=1/2 1/4 or 3/4 (Archimedes); | |
2020 <MATH><G>kq w′ ig′ lq′</G>=29 2/3 1/13 1/39=29 2/3+1/13+1/39 or 29 10/13; | |
2021 <G>mq∢′iz′ld′na′</G>=49 1/2 1/17 1/34 1/51=49 31/51</MATH> | |
2022 (Heron, <I>Geom</I>. 15. 8, 13). But <G>ig′ to\ ig′</G> means 1/13th times | |
2023 1/13 or 1/169 (<I>ibid.</I> 12. 5), &c. A less orthodox method found | |
2024 in later manuscripts was to use two accents and to write, | |
2025 e.g., <G>z″</G> instead of <G>z′</G>, for 1/7. In Diophantus we find a different | |
2026 mark in place of the accent; Tannery considers the genuine | |
2027 form of it to be χ, so that <G>g</G><SUP>χ</SUP>=1/3, and so on. | |
2028 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The ordinary Greek form, variously written</I>.</C> | |
2029 <p>An ordinary proper fraction (called by Euclid <G>me/rh</G>, <I>parts</I>, | |
2030 in the plural; as meaning a certain number of aliquot parts, | |
2031 in contradistinction to <G>me/ros</G>, <I>part</I>, in the singular, which he | |
2032 restricts to an aliquot part or submultiple) was expressed in | |
2033 various ways. The first was to use the ordinary cardinal | |
2034 number for the numerator followed by the accented number | |
2035 representing the denominator. Thus we find in Archimedes | |
2036 <G>―i oa′</G>=10/71 and <G>―<SUB>'</SUB>awlh ―q ia′</G>=1838 9/11: (it should be noted, | |
2037 however, that the <G>―i oa′</G> is a correction from <G>oia</G>, and this | |
2038 seems to indicate that the original reading was <FIG>, which | |
2039 would accord with Diophantus's and Heron's method of | |
2040 writing fractions). The method illustrated by these cases is | |
2041 open to objection as likely to lead to confusion, since <G>i oa′</G> | |
2042 <pb n=43><head>FRACTIONS</head> | |
2043 would naturally mean 10 1/71 and <G>q ia′</G> 9 1/11; the context alone | |
2044 shows the true meaning. Another form akin to that just | |
2045 mentioned was a little less open to misconstruction; the | |
2046 numerator was written in full with the accented numeral | |
2047 (for the denominator) following, e.g. <G>du/o me′</G> for 2/45ths | |
2048 (Aristarchus of Samos). A better way was to turn the | |
2049 aliquot part into an abbreviation for the ordinal number | |
2050 with a termination superposed to represent the <I>case</I>, e.g. | |
2051 <G>d<SUP>wn</SUP> s</G>=6/4 (Dioph. Lemma to V. 8), <G>n kg<SUP>wn</SUP></G>=50/23 (<I>ibid.</I> I. 23), | |
2052 <G>rka<SUP>wn</SUP> <SUB>'</SUB>awld∢′</G>=1834 1/2/121 (<I>ibid.</I> IV. 39), just as <G>g<SUP>os</SUP></G> was | |
2053 written for the ordinal <G>tri/tos</G> (cf. <G>to\ s<SUP>on</SUP></G>, the 1/6th part, Dioph. | |
2054 IV. 39; <G>ai)/rw ta\ ig<SUP>a</SUP></G> ‘I remove the 13ths’, i.e. I multiply up | |
2055 by the denominator 13, <I>ibid.</I> IV. 9). But the trouble was | |
2056 avoided by each of two other methods. | |
2057 <p>(1) The accented letters representing the denominator were | |
2058 written twice, along with the cardinal number for the | |
2059 numerator. This method is mostly found in the <I>Geometrica</I> | |
2060 and other works of Heron: cf. <G>e ig′ ig′</G>=5/13, <G>ta\ s z′z′</G>=6/7. | |
2061 The fractional signification is often emphasized by adding | |
2062 the word <G>lepta/</G> (‘fractions’ or ‘fractional parts’), e.g. in | |
2063 <G>lepta\ ig′ ig′ ib</G>=12/13 (<I>Geom</I>. 12. 5), and, where the expression | |
2064 contains units as well as fractions, the word ‘units’ (<G>mona/des</G>) | |
2065 is generally added, for clearness' sake, to indicate the integral | |
2066 number, e.g. <G>mona/des ib kai\ lepta\ ig′ ig′ ib</G>=12 12/13 (<I>Geom</I>. | |
2067 12. 5), <G>mona/des rmd lepta\ ig′ ig′ sO|q</G>=144 299/13 (<I>Geom</I>. 12. 6). | |
2068 Sometimes in Heron fractions are alternatively given in this | |
2069 notation and in that of submultiples, e.g. <G>b g′ ie′ h)/toi b kai\ | |
2070 b e′ e′</G>=‘2 1/3 1/15 or 2 2/5’ (<I>Geom</I>. 12. 48); <G>z ∢′ i′ ie′ oe′ h)/toi | |
2071 mona/des z e′ e′ g kai\ b e′ e′ tw=n e′ e′</G>=‘7 1/2 1/10 1/15 1/75 or 7 3/5+2/5X1/5’, | |
2072 i.e. 7 3/5+2/25 (<I>ibid.</I>); <G>h ∢′ i′ ke′ h)/toi mona/des h e′ e′ g kai\ e′ to\ e′</G>= | |
2073 ‘8 1/2 1/10 1/25 or 8 3/5+1/5X1/5’, i.e. 8 3/5+1/25 (<I>ibid.</I> 12. 46). (In | |
2074 Hultsch's edition of Heron single accents were used to de- | |
2075 note whole numbers and the numerators of fractions, while | |
2076 aliquot parts or denominators were represented by double | |
2077 accents; thus the last quoted expression was written | |
2078 <G>h′ <*> i″ ke″ h)/toi mona/des h′ e″ e″ g′ kai\ e″ to\ e″</G>.) | |
2079 <p>But (2) the most convenient notation of all is that which | |
2080 is regularly employed by Diophantus, and occasionally in the | |
2081 <I>Metrica</I> of Heron. In this system the numerator of any | |
2082 fraction is written in the line, with the denominator <I>above</I> it, | |
2083 <pb n=44><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2084 without accents or other marks (except where the numerator | |
2085 or denominator itself contains an accented fraction); the | |
2086 method is therefore simply the reverse of ours, but equally | |
2087 convenient. In Tannery's edition of Diophantus a line is | |
2088 put between the numerator below and the denominator above: | |
2089 thus <G>is</G>/<G>rka</G>=121/16. But it is better to omit the horizontal line | |
2090 (cf. <G>rkh</G>/<G>r</G>=100/128 in Kenyon's Papyri ii, No. cclxv. 40, and the | |
2091 fractions in Schöne's edition of Heron's <I>Metrica</I>). A few | |
2092 more instances from Diophantus may be given: <G>fib</G>/<G><SUB>'</SUB>buns</G>=2456/512 | |
2093 (IV. 28); <G>a.sa</G>/<G><SUB>'</SUB>etnh</G>=5358/10201 (V. 9); <G>rnb</G>/<G>tpq∢′</G>=(389 1/2)/152. The deno- | |
2094 minator is rarely found above the numerator, but to the | |
2095 right (like an exponent); e.g. <G>―ie<SUP>d</SUP></G>=15/4 (I. 39). Even in the | |
2096 case of a submultiple, where, as we have said, the orthodox | |
2097 method was to omit the numerator and simply write the | |
2098 denominator with an accent, Diophantus often follows the | |
2099 method applicable to other fractions, e.g. he writes <G>fib</G>/<G>a</G> for | |
2100 1/512 (IV. 28). Numbers partly integral and partly fractional, | |
2101 where the fraction is a submultiple or expressed as the sum | |
2102 of submultiples, are written much as we write them, the | |
2103 fractions simply following the integer, e.g. <G>a g</G><SUP>χ</SUP>=1 1/3; | |
2104 <G>b ∢′ s</G><SUP>χ</SUP>=2 1/2 1/6 (Lemma to V. 8); <G>to ∢′ is</G><SUP>χ</SUP>=370 1/2 1/16 (III. 11). | |
2105 Complicated fractions in which the numerator and denomi- | |
2106 nator are algebraical expressions or large numbers are often | |
2107 expressed by writing the numerator first and separating it | |
2108 by <G>mori/ou</G> or <G>e)n mori/w|</G> from the denominator; i.e. the fraction | |
2109 is expressed as the numerator <I>divided by</I> the denominator: | |
2110 thus <FIG><G>rn.<SUB>'</SUB>z<*>pd mori/ou ks.<SUB>'</SUB>brmd</G>=1507984/262144 (IV. 28). | |
2111 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Sexagesimal fractions</I>.</C> | |
2112 <p>Great interest attaches to the system of sexagesimal | |
2113 fractions (Babylonian in its origin, as we have seen) which | |
2114 was used by the Greeks in astronomical calculations, and | |
2115 <pb n=45><head>SEXAGESIMAL FRACTIONS</head> | |
2116 appears fully developed in the <I>Syntaxis</I> of Ptolemy. The | |
2117 circumference of a circle, and with it the four right angles | |
2118 subtended by it at the centre, were divided into 360 parts | |
2119 (<G>tmh/mata</G> or <G>moi=rai</G>), as we should say <I>degrees</I>, each <G>moi=ra</G> | |
2120 into 60 parts called (<G>prw=ta</G>) <G>e(xhkosta/</G>, (<I>first</I>) <I>sixtieths</I> or | |
2121 <I>minutes</I> (<G>lepta/</G>), each of these again into 60 <G>deu/tera e(xhkosta/</G>, | |
2122 <I>seconds</I>, and so on. In like manner, the diameter of the | |
2123 circle was divided into 120 <G>tmh/mata</G>, <I>segments</I>, and each of | |
2124 these segments was divided into sixtieths, each sixtieth | |
2125 again into sixty parts, and so on. Thus a convenient | |
2126 fractional system was available for arithmetical calculations | |
2127 in general; for the unit could be chosen at will, and any | |
2128 mixed number could be expressed as so many of those units | |
2129 <I>plus</I> so many of the fractions which we should represent | |
2130 by 1/60, so many of those which we should write (1/60)<SUP>2</SUP>, (1/60)<SUP>3</SUP>, | |
2131 and so on to any extent. The units, <G>tmh/mata</G> or <G>moi=rai</G> (the | |
2132 latter often denoted by the abbreviation <G>m</G>°), were written | |
2133 first, with the ordinary numeral representing the number | |
2134 of them; then came a simple numeral with one accent repre- | |
2135 senting that number of <I>first sixtieths</I>, or minutes, then a | |
2136 numeral with two accents representing that number of | |
2137 <I>second sixtieths</I>, or seconds, and so on. Thus <G>m° b</G>=2°, | |
2138 <G>moirw=n mz mb′ m″</G>=47° 42′ 40″. Similarly, <G>tmhma/twn xz | |
2139 d′ ne″</G>=67<I>p</I> 4′ 55″, where <I>p</I> denotes the <I>segment</I> (of the | |
2140 diameter). Where there was no unit, or no number of | |
2141 sixtieths, second sixtieths, &c., the symbol <G>*o</G>, signifying | |
2142 <G>ou)demi/a moi=ra, ou)de\n e(xhkosto/n</G>, and the like, was used; thus | |
2143 <G>moirw=n *o a′ b″ *o‴</G>=0°1′2″0‴. The system is parallel to | |
2144 our system of decimal fractions, with the difference that the | |
2145 submultiple is 1/60 instead of 1/10 nor is it much less easy to | |
2146 work with, while it furnishes a very speedy way of approxi- | |
2147 mating to the values of quantities not expressible in whole | |
2148 numbers. For example, in his Table of Chords, Ptolemy says | |
2149 that the chord subtending an angle of 120° at the centre is | |
2150 (<G>tmhma/twn</G>) <G>rg ne′ kg″</G> or 103<I>p</I> 55′ 23″; this is equivalent | |
2151 (since the radius of the circle is 60 <G>tmh/mata</G>) to saying that | |
2152 √3=1+43/60+55/60<SUP>2</SUP>+23/60<SUP>3</SUP>, and this works out to 1.7320509 ..., | |
2153 which is correct to the seventh decimal place, and exceeds | |
2154 the true value by 0.00000003 only. | |
2155 <pb n=46><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2156 <C>Practical calculation.</C> | |
2157 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>The abacus</I>.</C> | |
2158 <p>In practical calculation it was open to the Greeks to secure | |
2159 the advantages of a position-value system by using the | |
2160 abacus. The essence of the abacus was the arrangement of | |
2161 it in columns which might be vertical or horizontal, but were | |
2162 generally vertical, and pretty certainly so in Greece and | |
2163 Egypt; the columns were marked off by lines or in some | |
2164 other way and allocated to the successive denominations of | |
2165 the numerical system in use, i.e., in the case of the decimal | |
2166 system, the units, tens, hundreds, thousands, myriads, and so | |
2167 on. The number of units of each denomination was shown in | |
2168 each column by means of pebbles, pegs, or the like. When, | |
2169 in the process of addition or multiplication, the number of | |
2170 pebbles collected in one column becomes sufficient to make | |
2171 one or more units of the next higher denomination, the num- | |
2172 ber of pebbles representing the complete number of the higher | |
2173 units is withdrawn from the column in question and the | |
2174 proper number of the higher units added to the next higher | |
2175 column. Similarly, in subtraction, when a number of units of | |
2176 one denomination has to be subtracted and there are not | |
2177 enough pebbles in the particular column to subtract from, one | |
2178 pebble from the next higher column is withdrawn and actually | |
2179 or mentally resolved into the number of the lower units | |
2180 equivalent in value; the latter number of additional pebbles | |
2181 increases the number already in the column to a number from | |
2182 which the number to be subtracted can actually be withdrawn. | |
2183 The details of the columns of the Greek abacus have unfor- | |
2184 tunately to be inferred from the corresponding details of the | |
2185 Roman abacus, for the only abaci which have been preserved | |
2186 and can with certainty be identified as such are Roman. | |
2187 There were two kinds; in one of these the marks were | |
2188 buttons or knobs which could be moved up and down in each | |
2189 column, but could not be taken out of it, while in the other | |
2190 kind they were pebbles which could also be moved from one | |
2191 column to another. Each column was in two parts, a shorter | |
2192 portion at the top containing one button only, which itself | |
2193 represented half the number of units necessary to make up | |
2194 one of the next higher units, and a longer portion below | |
2195 <pb n=47><head>PRACTICAL CALCULATION</head> | |
2196 containing one less than half the same number. This arrange- | |
2197 ment of the columns in two parts enabled the total number of | |
2198 buttons to be economized. The columns represented, so far as | |
2199 integral numbers were concerned, units, tens, hundreds, thou- | |
2200 sands, &c., and in these cases the one button in the top | |
2201 portion of each column represented five units, and there were | |
2202 four buttons in the lower portion representing four units. | |
2203 But after the columns representing integers came columns | |
2204 representing fractions; the first contained buttons represent- | |
2205 ing <I>unciae</I>, of which there were 12 to the unit, i.e. fractions | |
2206 of 1/(12)th, and in this case the one button in the top portion | |
2207 represented 6 <I>unciae</I> or 6/(12)ths, while there were 5 buttons in | |
2208 the lower portion (instead of 4), the buttons in the column | |
2209 thus representing in all 11 <I>unciae</I> or 12ths. After this column | |
2210 there were (in one specimen) three other shorter ones along- | |
2211 side the lower portions only of the columns for integers, the | |
2212 first representing fractions of 1/(24)th (one button), the second | |
2213 fractions of 1/(48)th (one button), and the third fractions of 1/(72)nd | |
2214 (two buttons, which of course together made up 1/(36)th). | |
2215 <p>The mediaeval writer of the so-called geometry of Boëtius | |
2216 describes another method of indicating in the various columns | |
2217 the number of units of each denomination.<note>Boëtius, <I>De Inst. Ar.</I>, ed. Friedlein, pp. 396 sq.</note> According to him | |
2218 ‘abacus’ was a later name for what was previously called | |
2219 <I>mensa Pythagorea</I>, in honour of the Master who had taught | |
2220 its use. The method was to put in the columns, not the neces- | |
2221 sary number of pebbles or buttons, but the corresponding | |
2222 <I>numeral</I>, which might be written in sand spread over the | |
2223 surface (in the same way as Greek geometers are said to have | |
2224 drawn geometrical figures in sand strewn on boards similarly | |
2225 called <G>a)/bax</G> or <G>a)\ba/kion</G>). The figures put in the columns were | |
2226 called <I>apices</I>. The first variety of numerals mentioned by the | |
2227 writer are rough forms of the Indian figures (a fact which | |
2228 proves the late date of the composition); but other forms were | |
2229 (1) the first letters of the alphabet (which presumably mean | |
2230 the Greek alphabetic numerals) or (2) the ordinary Roman | |
2231 figures. | |
2232 <p>We should expect the arrangement of the Greek abacus to | |
2233 correspond to the Roman, but the actual evidence regarding its | |
2234 form and the extent to which it was used is so scanty that | |
2235 <pb n=48><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2236 we may well doubt whether any great use was made of it at | |
2237 all. But the use of pebbles to reckon with is attested by | |
2238 several writers. In Aristophanes (<I>Wasps</I>, 656-64) Bdelycleon | |
2239 tells his father to do an easy sum ‘not with pebbles but with | |
2240 fingers’, as much as to say, ‘There is no need to use pebbles | |
2241 for this sum; you can do it on your fingers.’ ‘The income | |
2242 of the state’, he says, ‘is 2000 talents; the yearly payment | |
2243 to the 6000 dicasts is only 150 talents.’ ‘Why’, answers the | |
2244 old man, ‘we don't get a tenth of the revenue.’ The calcula- | |
2245 tion in this case amounted to multiplying 150 by 10 to show | |
2246 that the product is less than 2000. But more to the purpose | |
2247 are the following allusions. Herodotus says that, in reckoning | |
2248 with pebbles, as in writing, the Greeks move their hand from | |
2249 left to right, the Egyptians from right to left<note>Herodotus, ii. c. 36.</note>; this indicates | |
2250 that the columns were vertical, facing the reckoner. Diogenes | |
2251 Laertius attributes to Solon a statement that those who had | |
2252 influence with tyrants were like the pebbles on a reckoning- | |
2253 board, because they sometimes stood for more and sometimes | |
2254 for less.<note>Diog. L. i. 59.</note> A character in a fourth-century comedy asks for an | |
2255 abacus and pebbles to do his accounts.<note>Alexis in Athenaeus, 117 c.</note> But most definite of | |
2256 all is a remark of Polybius that ‘These men are really like | |
2257 the pebbles on reckoning-boards. For the latter, according | |
2258 to the pleasure of the reckoner, have the value, now of a | |
2259 <G>xalkou=s</G> (1/8th of an obol or 1/(48)th of a drachma), and the next | |
2260 moment of a talent.’<note>Polybius, v. 26. 13.</note> The passages of Diogenes Laertius and | |
2261 Polybius both indicate that the pebbles were not fixed in the | |
2262 columns, but could be transferred from one to another, and | |
2263 the latter passage has some significance in relation to the | |
2264 Salaminian table presently to be mentioned, because the talent | |
2265 and the <G>xalkou=s</G> are actually the extreme denominations on | |
2266 one side of the table. | |
2267 <p>Two relics other than the Salaminian table may throw | |
2268 some light on the subject. First, the so-called Darius-vase | |
2269 found at Canosa (Canusium), south-west of Barletta, represents | |
2270 a collector of tribute of distressful countenance with a table in | |
2271 front of him having pebbles, or (as some maintain) coins, upon | |
2272 it and, on the right-hand edge, beginning on the side farthest | |
2273 away and written in the direction towards him, the letters | |
2274 <pb n=49><head>PRACTICAL CALCULATION</head> | |
2275 <G>*m*y*h<*><*>*o<*>*t</G>, while in his left hand he holds a sort of book in | |
2276 which, presumably, he has to enter the receipts. Now <G>*m</G>, <G>*y</G> | |
2277 (=<G>*x</G>), <G>*h</G>, and <G><*></G> are of course the initial letters of the words | |
2278 for 10000, 1000, 100, and 10 respectively. Here therefore we | |
2279 have a purely decimal system, without the halfway numbers | |
2280 represented by <G><*></G> (=<G>pe/nte</G>, 5) in combination with the other | |
2281 initial letters which we find in the ‘Attic’ system. The sign | |
2282 <G><*></G> after <G><*></G> seems to be wrongly written for <G><*></G>, the older sign | |
2283 for a drachma, <G>*o</G> stands for the obol, <G><*></G> for the 1/2-obol, and <G>*t</G> | |
2284 (<G>tetarthmo/rion</G>) for the 1/4-obol.<note>Keil in <I>Hermes</I>, 29, 1894, pp. 262-3.</note> Except that the fractions of | |
2285 the unit (here the drachma) are different from the fractions | |
2286 of the Roman unit, this scheme corresponds to the Roman, | |
2287 and so far might represent the abacus. Indeed, the decimal | |
2288 arrangement corresponds better to the abacus than does the | |
2289 Salaminian table with its intermediate ‘Herodianic’ signs for | |
2290 500, 50, and 5 drachmas. Prof. David Eugene Smith is, how- | |
2291 ever, clear that any one can see from a critical examination of | |
2292 the piece that what is represented is an ordinary money- | |
2293 changer or tax-receiver with coins on a table such as one | |
2294 might see anywhere in the East to-day, and that the table has | |
2295 no resemblance to an abacus.<note><I>Bibliotheca Mathematica</I>, ix<SUB>3</SUB>, p. 193.</note> On the other hand, it is to be | |
2296 observed that the open book held by the tax-receiver in his | |
2297 left hand has <G>*t*a*l*n</G> on one page and <G>*t<*>*i/*h</G> on the other, | |
2298 which would seem to indicate that he was entering totals in | |
2299 <I>talents</I> and must therefore presumably have been <I>adding</I> coins | |
2300 or pebbles on the table before him. | |
2301 <p>There is a second existing monument of the same sort, | |
2302 namely a so-called <G>sh/kwma</G> (or arrangement of measures) | |
2303 discovered about forty years ago<note>Dumont in <I>Revue archéologique</I>, xxvi (1873), p. 43.</note>; it is a stone tablet with | |
2304 fluid measures and has, on the right-hand side, the numerals | |
2305 <G>*x<*>*h<*><*><*><*>*t*i<*></G>. The signs are the ‘Herodianic’, and they | |
2306 include those for 500, 50, and 5 drachmas; <G><*></G> is the sign for | |
2307 a drachma, <G>*t</G> evidently stands for some number of obols | |
2308 making a fraction of the drachma, i.e. the <G>triw/bolon</G> or 3 | |
2309 obols, <G>*i</G> for an obol, and <G><*></G> for a 1/2-obol. | |
2310 <p>The famous Salaminian table was discovered by Rangabé, | |
2311 who gave a drawing and description of it immediately after- | |
2312 <pb n=50><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2313 wards (1846).<note><I>Revue archéologique</I>, iii. 1846.</note> The table, now broken into two unequal parts, | |
2314 is in the Epigraphical Museum at Athens. The facts with | |
2315 regard to it are stated, and a photograph of it is satisfactorily | |
2316 produced, by Wilhelm Kubitschek.<note><I>Wiener numismatische Zeitschrift</I>, xxxi. 1899, pp. 393-8, with | |
2317 Plate xxiv.</note> A representation of it is | |
2318 also given by Nagl<note><I>Abh. zur Gesch. d. Math.</I> ix. 1899, plate after p. 357.</note> based on Rangabé's description, and the | |
2319 sketch of it here appended follows Nagl's drawing. The size | |
2320 and material of the table (according to Rangabé's measure- | |
2321 ments it is 1.5 metres long and 0.75 metre broad) show that | |
2322 <FIG> | |
2323 it was no ordinary abacus; it may | |
2324 have been a fixture intended for | |
2325 quasi-public use, such as a banker's | |
2326 or money-changer's table, or again | |
2327 it may have been a scoring-table | |
2328 for some kind of game like <I>tric- | |
2329 trac</I> or backgammon. Opinion has | |
2330 from the first been divided between | |
2331 the two views; it has even been | |
2332 suggested that the table was in- | |
2333 tended for both purposes. But there | |
2334 can be no doubt that it was used | |
2335 for some kind of calculation and, | |
2336 if it was not actually an abacus, it | |
2337 may at least serve to give an idea | |
2338 of what the abacus was like. The | |
2339 difficulties connected with its in- | |
2340 terpretation are easily seen. The | |
2341 series of letters on the three sides are the same except | |
2342 that two of them go no higher than <G>*x</G> (1000 drachmae), | |
2343 but the third has <G><*></G> (5000 drachmae), and <G>*t</G> (the talent or | |
2344 6000 drachmae) in addition; <G><*></G> is the sign for a drachma, | |
2345 <G>*i</G> for an obol (1/6th of the drachma), <G><*></G> for 1/2-obol, <G>*t</G> for 1/4-obol | |
2346 (<G>tetarthmo/rion</G>, Boeckh's suggestion), not 1/3-obol (<G>trithmo/rion</G>, | |
2347 Vincent), and <G>*x</G> for 1/8-obol (<G>xalkou=s</G>). It seems to be | |
2348 agreed that the four spaces provided between the five shorter | |
2349 lines were intended for the fractions of the drachma; the first | |
2350 space would require 5 pebbles (one less than the 6 obols | |
2351 making up a drachma), the others one each. The longer | |
2352 <pb n=51><head>PRACTICAL CALCULATION</head> | |
2353 lines would provide the spaces for the drachmae and higher | |
2354 denominations. On the assumption that the cross line indi- | |
2355 cates the Roman method of having one pebble above it to | |
2356 represent 5, and four below it representing units, it is clear | |
2357 that, including denominations up to the talent (6000 drachmae), | |
2358 only five columns are necessary, namely one for the talent or | |
2359 6000 drachmae, and four for 1000, 100, 10 drachmae, and 1 | |
2360 drachma respectively. But there are actually ten spaces pro- | |
2361 vided by the eleven lines. On the theory of the game-board, | |
2362 five of the ten on one side (right or left) are supposed to | |
2363 belong to each of two players placed facing each other on the | |
2364 two longer sides of the table (but, if in playing they had to | |
2365 use the shorter columns for the fractions, it is not clear how | |
2366 they would make them suffice); the cross on the middle of the | |
2367 middle line might in that case serve to mark the separation | |
2368 between the lines belonging to the two players, or perhaps all | |
2369 the crosses may have the one object of helping the eye to dis- | |
2370 tinguish all the columns from one another. On the assump- | |
2371 tion that the table is an abacus, a possible explanation of the | |
2372 <I>eleven</I> lines is to suppose that they really supply <I>five</I> columns | |
2373 only, the odd lines marking the divisions between the columns, | |
2374 and the even lines, one in the middle of each column, | |
2375 marking where the pebbles should be placed in rows; in this | |
2376 case, if the crosses are intended to mark divisions between the | |
2377 four pebbles representing units and the one pebble represent- | |
2378 ing 5 in each column, the crosses are only required in the last | |
2379 three columns (for 100, 10, and 1), because, the highest de- | |
2380 nomination being 6000 drachmae, there was no need for a | |
2381 division of the 1000-column, which only required five unit- | |
2382 pebbles altogether. Nagl, a thorough-going supporter of the | |
2383 abacus-theory to the exclusion of the other, goes further and | |
2384 shows how the Salaminian table could have been used for the | |
2385 special purpose of carrying out a long multiplication; but this | |
2386 development seems far-fetched, and there is no evidence of | |
2387 such a use. | |
2388 <p>The Greeks in fact had little need of the abacus for calcu- | |
2389 lations. With their alphabetic numerals they could work out | |
2390 their additions, subtractions, multiplications, and divisions | |
2391 without the help of any marked columns, in a form little less | |
2392 convenient than ours: examples of long multiplications, which | |
2393 <pb n=52><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2394 include addition as the last step in each case, are found in | |
2395 Eutocius's commentary on Archimedes's <I>Measurement of | |
2396 a Circle</I>. We will take the four arithmetical operations | |
2397 separately. | |
2398 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>Addition and Subtraction</I>.</C> | |
2399 <p>There is no doubt that, in writing down numbers for the | |
2400 purpose of these operations, the Greeks would keep the several | |
2401 powers of 10 separate in a manner practically corresponding | |
2402 to our system of numerals, the hundreds, thousands, &c., being | |
2403 written in separate vertical rows. The following would be | |
2404 a typical example of a sum in addition: | |
2405 <table> | |
2406 <tr><td align=right><G><SUB>'</SUB>aukd</G></td><td>=</td><td align=right>1424</td></tr> | |
2407 <tr><td align=right><G>r g</G></td><td></td><td align=right>103</td></tr> | |
2408 <tr><td align=right><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>bspa</G></td><td></td><td align=right>12281</td></tr> | |
2409 <tr><td align=right><G><FIG> l</G></td><td></td><td align=right>30030</td></tr> | |
2410 <tr><td align=right><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>gwlh</G></td><td></td><td align=right>43838</td></tr> | |
2411 </table> | |
2412 and the mental part of the work would be the same for the | |
2413 Greek as for us. | |
2414 <p>Similarly a subtraction would be represented as follows: | |
2415 <table> | |
2416 <tr><td><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>gxls</G></td><td>=</td><td>93636</td></tr> | |
2417 <tr><td><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>gu q</G></td><td></td><td>23409</td></tr> | |
2418 <tr><td><G><FIG> skz</G></td><td></td><td>70227</td></tr> | |
2419 </table> | |
2420 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Multiplication</I>.</C> | |
2421 <C>(i) The Egyptian method.</C> | |
2422 <p>For carrying out multiplications two things were required. | |
2423 The first was a multiplication table. This the Greeks are | |
2424 certain to have had from very early times. The Egyptians, | |
2425 indeed, seem never to have had such a table. We know from | |
2426 the Papyrus Rhind that in order to multiply by any number | |
2427 the Egyptians began by successive doubling, thus obtaining | |
2428 twice, four times, eight times, sixteen times the multiplicand, | |
2429 and so on; they then added such sums of this series of multi- | |
2430 ples (including once the multiplicand) as were required. Thus, | |
2431 <pb n=53><head>MULTIPLICATION</head> | |
2432 to multiply by 13, they did not take 10 times and 3 times | |
2433 the multiplicand respectively and add them, but they found | |
2434 13 times the multiplicand by adding once and 4 times and 8 | |
2435 times it, which elements they had obtained by the doubling | |
2436 process; similarly they would find 25 times any number by | |
2437 adding once and 8 times and 16 times the number.<note>I have been told that there is a method in use to-day (some say in | |
2438 Russia, but I have not been able to verify this), which is certainly attractive | |
2439 and looks original, but which will immediately be seen to amount simply | |
2440 to an elegant practical method of carrying out the Egyptian procedure. | |
2441 Write out side by side in successive lines, so as to form two columns, | |
2442 (1) the multiplier and multiplicand, (2) half the multiplier (or the | |
2443 nearest integer below it if the multiplier is odd) and twice the multi- | |
2444 plicand, (3) half (or the nearest integer below the half) of the number | |
2445 in the first column of the preceding row and twice the number in the | |
2446 second column of the preceding row, and so on, until we have 1 in | |
2447 the first column. Then strike out all numbers in the second column | |
2448 which are opposite <I>even</I> numbers in the first column, and add all the | |
2449 numbers left in the second column. The sum will be the required | |
2450 product. Suppose e.g. that 157 is to be multiplied by 83. The rows | |
2451 and columns then are: | |
2452 <table> | |
2453 <tr><td align=right>83</td><td align=right>157</td><td></td></tr> | |
2454 <tr><td align=right>41</td><td align=right>314</td><td></td></tr> | |
2455 <tr><td align=right>20</td><td align=right><STRIKE>628</STRIKE></td><td></td></tr> | |
2456 <tr><td align=right>10</td><td align=right><STRIKE>1256</STRIKE></td><td></td></tr> | |
2457 <tr><td align=right>5</td><td align=right>2512</td><td></td></tr> | |
2458 <tr><td align=right>2</td><td align=right><STRIKE>5024</STRIKE></td><td></td></tr> | |
2459 <tr><td align=right>1</td><td align=right>10048</td><td></td></tr> | |
2460 <tr><td></td><td align=right>13031</td><td>= 83 x 157</td></tr> | |
2461 </table> | |
2462 The explanation is, of course, that, where we take half the preceding | |
2463 number in the first column <I>less one</I>, we omit once the figure in the right- | |
2464 hand column, so that it must be left in that column to be added in at | |
2465 the end; and where we take the exact half of an even number, we | |
2466 omit nothing in the right-hand column, but the new line is the <I>exact</I> | |
2467 equivalent of the preceding one, which can therefore be struck out.</note> Division | |
2468 was performed by the Egyptians in an even more rudimen- | |
2469 tary fashion, namely by a tentative back-multiplication begin- | |
2470 ning with the same doubling process. But, as we have seen | |
2471 (p. 14), the scholiast to the <I>Charmides</I> says that the branches | |
2472 of <G>logistikh/</G> include the ‘so-called Greek and Egyptian | |
2473 methods in multiplications and divisions’. | |
2474 <C>(ii) The Greek method.</C> | |
2475 <p>The Egyptian method being what we have just described, it | |
2476 seems clear that the Greek method, which was different, | |
2477 depended on the direct use of a multiplication table. A frag- | |
2478 ment of such a multiplication table is preserved on a two- | |
2479 leaved wax tablet in the British Museum (Add. MS. 34186). | |
2480 <pb n=54><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2481 It is believed to date from the second century A. D., and it | |
2482 probably came from Alexandria or the vicinity. But the | |
2483 form of the characters and the mingling of capitals and small | |
2484 letters both allow of an earlier date; e.g. there is in the | |
2485 Museum a Greek papyrus assigned to the third century B.C. | |
2486 in which the numerals are very similar to those on the tablet.<note>David Eugene Smith in <I>Bibliotheca Mathematica</I>, ix<SUB>3</SUB>, pp. 193-5.</note> | |
2487 <p>The second requirement is connected with the fact that the | |
2488 Greeks began their multiplications by taking the product of | |
2489 the highest constituents first, i.e. they proceeded as we should | |
2490 if we were to begin our long multiplications from the left | |
2491 instead of the right. The only difficulty would be to settle | |
2492 the denomination of the products of two high powers of ten. | |
2493 With such numbers as the Greeks usually had to multiply | |
2494 there would be no trouble; but if, say, the factors were un- | |
2495 usually large numbers, e.g. millions multiplied by millions or | |
2496 billions, care would be required, and even some rule for | |
2497 settling the denomination, or determining the particular | |
2498 power or powers of 10 which the product would contain. | |
2499 This exceptional necessity was dealt with in the two special | |
2500 treatises, by Archimedes and Apollonius respectively, already | |
2501 mentioned. The former, the <I>Sand-reckoner</I>, proves that, if | |
2502 there be a series of numbers, 1, 10, 10<SUP>2</SUP>, 10<SUP>3</SUP>... 10<SUP><I>m</I></SUP>... 10<SUP><I>n</I></SUP>..., | |
2503 then, if 10<SUP><I>m</I></SUP>, 10<SUP><I>n</I></SUP> be any two terms of the series, their product | |
2504 10<SUP><I>m</I></SUP>.10<SUP><I>n</I></SUP> will be a term in the same series and will be as many | |
2505 terms distant from 10<SUP><I>n</I></SUP> as the term 10<SUP><I>m</I></SUP> is distant from 1; | |
2506 also it will be distant from 1 by a number of terms less by | |
2507 one than the sum of the numbers of terms by which 10<SUP><I>m</I></SUP> and | |
2508 10<SUP><I>n</I></SUP> respectively are distant from 1. This is easily seen to be | |
2509 equivalent to the fact that, 10<SUP><I>m</I></SUP> being the (<I>m</I>+1)th term | |
2510 beginning with 1, and 10<SUP><I>n</I></SUP> the (<I>n</I>+1)th term beginning | |
2511 with 1, the product of the two terms is the (<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>+1)th | |
2512 term beginning with 1, and is 10<SUP><I>m</I>+<I>n</I></SUP>. | |
2513 <C>(iii) Apollonius's continued multiplications.</C> | |
2514 <p>The system of Apollonius deserves a short description.<note>Our authority here is the <I>Synagoge</I> of Pappus, Book ii, pp. 2-28, Hultsch.</note> Its | |
2515 object is to give a handy method of finding the continued | |
2516 product of any number of factors, each of which is represented | |
2517 by a single letter in the Greek numeral notation. It does not | |
2518 <pb n=55><head>MULTIPLICATION</head> | |
2519 therefore show how to multiply two large numbers each of | |
2520 which contains a number of digits (in our notation), that is, | |
2521 a certain number of units, a certain number of tens, a certain | |
2522 number of hundreds, &c.; it is confined to the multiplication | |
2523 of any number of factors each of which is one or other of the | |
2524 following: (<I>a</I>) a number of units as 1, 2, 3, ... 9, (<I>b</I>) a number | |
2525 of even tens as 10, 20, 30, ... 90, (<I>c</I>) a number of even hundreds | |
2526 as 100, 200, 300, ... 900. It does not deal with factors above | |
2527 hundreds, e.g. 1000 or 4000; this is because the Greek | |
2528 numeral alphabet only went up to 900, the notation begin- | |
2529 ning again after that with <G><SUB>'</SUB>a</G>, <G><SUB>'</SUB>b</G>, ... for 1000, 2000, &c. The | |
2530 essence of the method is the separate multiplication (1) of the | |
2531 <I>bases</I>, <G>puqme/nes</G>, of the several factors, (2) of the powers of ten | |
2532 contained in the factors, that is, what we represent by the | |
2533 ciphers in each factor. Given a multiple of ten, say 30, 3 is | |
2534 the <G>puqmh/n</G> or base, being the same number of units as the | |
2535 number contains tens; similarly in a multiple of 100, say 800, | |
2536 8 is the base. In multiplying three numbers such as 2, 30, | |
2537 800, therefore, Apollonius first multiplies the bases, 2, 3, and 8, | |
2538 then finds separately the product of the ten and the hundred, | |
2539 and lastly multiplies the two products. The final product has | |
2540 to be expressed as a certain number of units less than a | |
2541 myriad, then a certain number of myriads, a certain number | |
2542 of ‘double myriads’ (myriads squared), ‘triple myriads’ | |
2543 (myriads cubed), &c., in other words in the form | |
2544 <MATH><I>A</I><SUB>0</SUB>+<I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB><I>M</I>+<I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB><I>M</I><SUP>2</SUP>+...</MATH>, | |
2545 where <I>M</I> is a myriad or 10<SUP>4</SUP> and <I>A</I><SUB>0</SUB>, <I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB> ... respectively repre- | |
2546 sent some number not exceeding 9999. | |
2547 <p>No special directions are given for carrying out the multi- | |
2548 plication of the <I>bases</I> (digits), or for the multiplication of | |
2549 their product into the product of the tens, hundreds, &c., | |
2550 when separately found (directions for the latter multiplica- | |
2551 tion may have been contained in propositions missing from | |
2552 the mutilated fragment in Pappus). But the method of deal- | |
2553 ing with the tens and hundreds (the ciphers in our notation) | |
2554 is made the subject of a considerable number of separate | |
2555 propositions. Thus in two propositions the factors are all of | |
2556 one sort (tens or hundreds), in another we have factors of two | |
2557 sorts (a number of factors containing units only multiplied | |
2558 <pb n=56><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2559 by a number of multiples of ten, each less than 100, or by | |
2560 multiples of 100, each less than 1000), and so on. In the final | |
2561 proposition (25), with which the introductory lemmas close, | |
2562 the factors are of all three kinds, some containing units only, | |
2563 others being multiples of 10 (less than 100) and a third set | |
2564 being multiples of 100 (less than 1000 in each case). As | |
2565 Pappus frequently says, the proof is easy ‘in numbers’; | |
2566 Apollonius himself seems to have proved the propositions by | |
2567 means of lines or a diagram in some form. The method is the | |
2568 equivalent of taking the indices of all the separate powers of | |
2569 ten included in the factors (in which process ten =10<SUP>1</SUP> counts | |
2570 as 1, and 100=10<SUP>2</SUP> as 2), adding the indices together, and then | |
2571 dividing the sum by 4 to obtain the power of the myriad | |
2572 (10000) which the product contains. If the whole number in | |
2573 the quotient is <I>n</I>, the product contains (10000)<SUP><I>n</I></SUP> or the | |
2574 <I>n</I>-myriad in Apollonius's notation. There will in most cases | |
2575 be a remainder left after division by 4, namely 3, 2, or 1: the | |
2576 remainder then represents (in our notation) 3, 2, or 1 more | |
2577 ciphers, that is, the product is 1000, 100, or 10 times the | |
2578 <I>n</I>-myriad, or the 10000<SUP><I>n</I></SUP>, as the case may be. | |
2579 <p>We cannot do better than illustrate by the main problem | |
2580 which Apollonius sets himself, namely that of multiplying | |
2581 together all the numbers represented by the separate letters | |
2582 in the hexameter: | |
2583 <C><G>*)arte/midos klei=te kra/tos e)/xokon e)nne/a kou=rai</G>.</C> | |
2584 <p>The number of letters, and therefore of factors, is 38, of which | |
2585 10 are multiples of 100 less than 1000, namely <G>r</G>, <G>t</G>, <G>s</G>, <G>t</G>, <G>r</G>, <G>t</G>, | |
2586 <G>s</G>, <G>x</G>, <G>u</G>, <G>r</G> (=100, 300, 200, 300, 100, 300, 200, 600, 400, 100), | |
2587 17 are multiples of 10 less than 100, namely <G>m</G>, <G>i</G>, <G>o</G>, <G>k</G>, <G>l</G>, <G>i</G>, <G>k</G>, <G>o</G>, <G>x</G>, | |
2588 <G>o</G>, <G>o</G>, <G>n</G>, <G>n</G>, <G>n</G>, <G>k</G>, <G>o</G>, <G>i</G> (=40, 10, 70, 20, 30, 10, 20, 70, 60, 70, 70, 50, | |
2589 50, 50, 20, 70, 10), and 11 are numbers of units not exceeding | |
2590 9, namely <G>a</G>, <G>e</G>, <G>d</G>, <G>e</G>, <G>e</G>, <G>a</G>, <G>e</G>, <G>e</G>, <G>e</G>, <G>a</G>, <G>a</G> (=1, 5, 4, 5, 5, 1, 5, 5, 5, 1, 1). | |
2591 The sum of the indices of powers of ten contained in the | |
2592 factors is therefore <MATH>10.2+17.1=37</MATH>. This, when divided by | |
2593 4, gives 9 with 1 as remainder. Hence the product of all the | |
2594 tens and hundreds, excluding the <I>bases</I> in each, is 10.10000<SUP>9</SUP>. | |
2595 <p>We have now, as the second part of the operation, to mul- | |
2596 tiply the numbers containing units only by the <I>bases</I> of all the | |
2597 other factors, i.e. (beginning with the <I>bases</I>, first of the hun- | |
2598 dreds, then of the tens) to multiply together the numbers: | |
2599 <pb n=57><head>MULTIPLICATION</head> | |
2600 1, 3, 2, 3, 1, 3, 2, 6, 4, 1, | |
2601 4, 1, 7, 2, 3, 1, 2, 7, 6, 7, 7, 5, 5, 5, 2, 7, 1, | |
2602 and 1, 5, 4, 5, 5, 1, 5, 5, 5, 1, 1. | |
2603 <p>The product is at once given in the text as 19 ‘quadruple | |
2604 myriads’, 6036 ‘triple myriads’, and 8480 ‘double myriads’, or | |
2605 <MATH>19.10000<SUP>4</SUP>+6036.10000<SUP>3</SUP>+8480.10000<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
2606 (The detailed multiplication line by line, which is of course | |
2607 perfectly easy, is bracketed by Hultsch as interpolated.) | |
2608 <p>Lastly, says Pappus, this product multiplied by the other | |
2609 (the product of the tens and hundreds without the <I>bases</I>), | |
2610 namely 10.10000<SUP>9</SUP>, as above, gives | |
2611 <MATH>196.10000<SUP>13</SUP>+368.10000<SUP>12</SUP>+4800.10000<SUP>11</SUP></MATH>. | |
2612 <C>(iv) Examples of ordinary multiplications.</C> | |
2613 <p>I shall now illustrate, by examples taken from Eutocius, the | |
2614 Greek method of performing long multiplications. It will be | |
2615 seen that, as in the case of addition and subtraction, the | |
2616 working is essentially the same as ours. The multiplicand is | |
2617 written first, and below it is placed the multiplier preceded by | |
2618 <G>e)pi/</G> (=‘by’ or ‘into’). Then the term containing the highest | |
2619 power of 10 in the multiplier is taken and multiplied into all | |
2620 the terms in the multiplicand, one after the other, first into that | |
2621 containing the highest power of 10, then into that containing | |
2622 the next highest power of 10, and so on in descending order; | |
2623 after which the term containing the next highest power of 10 | |
2624 in the multiplier is multiplied into all the terms of the multi- | |
2625 plicand in the same order; and so on. The same procedure | |
2626 is followed where either or both of the numbers to be multi- | |
2627 plied contain fractions. Two examples from Eutocius will | |
2628 make the whole operation clear. | |
2629 <p>(1) | |
2630 <table> | |
2631 <tr><td></td><td><G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G></td><td align=right>1351</td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2632 <tr><td align=right><G>e)pi/</G></td><td><G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G></td><td align=right>X 1351</td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2633 <tr><td></td><td><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>a</G></td><td align=right>1000000</td><td align=right>300000</td><td align=right>50000</td><td align=right>1000</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2634 <tr><td></td><td><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>et</G></td><td align=right>300000</td><td align=right>90000</td><td align=right>15000</td><td align=right>300</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2635 <tr><td></td><td><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>e<SUB>'</SUB>bfn</G></td><td></td><td align=right>50000</td><td align=right>15000</td><td align=right>2500</td><td>50</td><td></td></tr> | |
2636 <tr><td></td><td align=right><G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G></td><td></td><td></td><td align=right>1000</td><td align=right>300</td><td>50</td><td>1</td></tr> | |
2637 <tr><td align=right><G>o(mou=</G></td><td><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>esa</G></td><td align=right><I>together</I></td><td align=right>1825201.</td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2638 </table> | |
2639 <pb n=58><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2640 <p>(2) | |
2641 <table> | |
2642 <tr><td></td><td><G><SUB>'</SUB>gig∢d′</G></td><td align=right>3013 1/2 1/4</td><td colspan=2>[=3013 3/4]</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2643 <tr><td align=right><G>e)pi\</G></td><td><G><SUB>'</SUB>gig∢d′</G></td><td align=right>X 3013 1/2 1/4</td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2644 <tr><td></td><td><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>q<SUB>'</SUB>afyn</G></td><td align=right>9000000</td><td align=right>30000</td><td align=right>9000</td><td align=right>1500</td><td align=right>750</td></tr> | |
2645 <tr><td></td><td><G><FIG>rleb∢</G></td><td align=right>30000</td><td align=right>100</td><td align=right>30</td><td align=right>5</td><td align=right>2 1/2</td></tr> | |
2646 <tr><td></td><td><G><SUB>'</SUB>qlqa∢∢d′</G></td><td align=right>9000</td><td align=right>30</td><td align=right>9</td><td align=right>1 1/2</td><td align=right>1/2 1/4</td></tr> | |
2647 <tr><td></td><td><G><SUB>'</SUB>afea∢d′h′</G></td><td align=right>1500</td><td align=right>5</td><td align=right>1 1/2</td><td align=right>1/4</td><td align=right>1/8</td></tr> | |
2648 <tr><td></td><td><G>ynb∢∢d′h′is′</G></td><td align=right>750</td><td align=right>2 1/2</td><td align=right>1/2 1/4</td><td align=right>1/8</td><td align=right>1/(16)</td></tr> | |
2649 <tr><td align=right><G>o(mou=</G></td><td><G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>bxpqis′</G></td><td colspan=4 align=center><I>together</I> 9082689 1/(16).</td><td></td></tr> | |
2650 </table> | |
2651 <p>The following is one among many instances in which Heron | |
2652 works out a multiplication of two numbers involving fractions. | |
2653 He has to multiply 4 (33)/(64) by 7 (62)/(64), which he effects as follows | |
2654 (<I>Geom</I>. 12. 68): | |
2655 <MATH>4.7 = 28, | |
2656 4.(62)/(64) = (248)/(64), | |
2657 (33)/(64).7 = (231)/(64) | |
2658 (33)/(64).(62)/(64) = (2046)/(64).1/(64) = (31)/(64)+(62)/(64).1/(64)</MATH>; | |
2659 the result is therefore | |
2660 <MATH>28 (510)/(64)+(62)/(64).1/(64) = 28+7 (62)/(64)+(62)/(64).1/(64) | |
2661 = 35 (62)/(64)+(62)/(64).1/(64)</MATH>. | |
2662 <p>The multiplication of 37°4′55″ (in the sexagesimal system) | |
2663 by itself is performed by Theon of Alexandria in his com- | |
2664 mentary on Ptolemy's <I>Syntaxis</I> in an exactly similar manner. | |
2665 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>Division</I>.</C> | |
2666 <p>The operation of division depends on those of multiplication | |
2667 and subtraction, and was performed by the Greeks, <I>mutatis | |
2668 mutandis</I>, in the same way as we perform it to-day. Suppose, | |
2669 for example, that the process in the first of the above multi- | |
2670 plications had to be reversed and <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>esa</G> (1825201) had to be | |
2671 divided by <G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G> (1351). The terms involving the successive | |
2672 powers of 10 would be mentally kept separate, as in addition | |
2673 and subtraction, and the first question would be, how many | |
2674 times does one thousand go into one million, allowing for the | |
2675 fact that the one thousand has 351 behind it, while the one | |
2676 million has 825 thousands behind it. The answer is one | |
2677 thousand or <G><SUB>'</SUB>a</G>, and this multiplied by the divisor <G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G> gives | |
2678 <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>a</G> which, subtracted from <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>esa</G>, leaves <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>dsa</G>. This | |
2679 <pb n=59><head>DIVISION</head> | |
2680 remainder (=474201) has now to be divided by <G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G> (1351), | |
2681 and it would be seen that the latter would go into the former | |
2682 <G>t</G> (300) times, but not <G>u</G> (400) times. Multiplying <G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G> by <G>t</G>, | |
2683 we obtain <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>et</G> (405300), which, when subtracted from <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>dsa</G> | |
2684 (474201), leaves <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>h<*>a</G> (68901). This has again to be divided | |
2685 by <G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G> and goes <G>n</G> (50) times; multiplying <G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G> by <G>n</G>, we | |
2686 have <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>zfn</G> (67550), which, subtracted from <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>h<*>a</G> (68901), | |
2687 leaves <G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G> (1351). The last quotient is therefore <G>a</G> (1), and | |
2688 the whole quotient is <G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G> (1351). | |
2689 <p>An actual case of long division where both dividend and | |
2690 divisor contain sexagesimal fractions is described by Theon. | |
2691 The problem is to divide 1515 20′15″ by 25 12′ 10″, and | |
2692 Theon's account of the process amounts to the following: | |
2693 <table> | |
2694 <tr align=center><td>Divisor.</td><td></td><td colspan=2>Dividend.</td><td></td><td>Quotient.</td></tr> | |
2695 <tr><td>25 12′ 10″</td><td></td><td>1515</td><td>20′</td><td>15″</td><td>First term 60</td></tr> | |
2696 <tr><td></td><td>25.60</td><td>= 1500</td><td></td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2697 <tr><td></td><td colspan=2>Remainder 15=</td><td>900′</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2698 <tr><td></td><td>Sum</td><td></td><td>920′</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2699 <tr><td></td><td>12′.60</td><td>=</td><td>720′</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2700 <tr><td></td><td colspan=2 align=center>Remainder</td><td>200′</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2701 <tr><td></td><td>10″.60</td><td>=</td><td>10′</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2702 <tr><td></td><td colspan=2 align=center>Remainder</td><td>190′</td><td></td><td>Second term 7′</td></tr> | |
2703 <tr><td></td><td>25.7′</td><td>=</td><td>175′</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
2704 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td>15′ =</td><td>900″</td><td></td></tr> | |
2705 <tr><td></td><td></td><td>Sum</td><td></td><td>915″</td><td></td></tr> | |
2706 <tr><td></td><td></td><td>12′.7′ =</td><td></td><td>84″</td><td></td></tr> | |
2707 <tr><td></td><td></td><td colspan=2 align=center>Remainder</td><td>831″</td><td></td></tr> | |
2708 <tr><td></td><td></td><td>10″.7′ =</td><td></td><td>1″ 10‴</td><td></td></tr> | |
2709 <tr><td></td><td></td><td colspan=2 align=center>Remainder</td><td>829″ 50‴</td><td>Third</td></tr> | |
2710 <tr><td></td><td></td><td>25.33″ =</td><td></td><td>825″</td><td>term 33‴</td></tr> | |
2711 <tr><td></td><td></td><td colspan=2 align=center>Remainder</td><td>4″ 50‴ =</td><td>290‴</td></tr> | |
2712 <tr><td></td><td></td><td>12′.33″ =</td><td></td><td></td><td>396‴</td></tr> | |
2713 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td colspan=2 align=center>(<I>too great by</I>)</td><td>106″</td></tr> | |
2714 </table> | |
2715 Thus the quotient is something less than 60 7′33″. It will | |
2716 be observed that the difference between this operation of | |
2717 <pb n=60><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2718 Theon's and that of dividing <G><FIG><SUB>'</SUB>esa</G> by <G><SUB>'</SUB>atna</G> as above is that | |
2719 Theon makes <I>three</I> subtractions for one term of the quotient, | |
2720 whereas the remainder was arrived at in the other case after | |
2721 <I>one</I> subtraction. The result is that, though Theon's method | |
2722 is quite clear, it is longer, and moreover makes it less easy to | |
2723 foresee what will be the proper figure to try in the quotient, | |
2724 so that more time would probably be lost in making un- | |
2725 successful trials. | |
2726 <C>(<G>e</G>) <I>Extraction of the square root</I>.</C> | |
2727 <p>We are now in a position to see how the problem of extract- | |
2728 ing the square root of a number would be attacked. First, as | |
2729 in the case of division, the given whole number would be | |
2730 separated into terms containing respectively such and such | |
2731 a number of units and of the separate powers of 10. Thus | |
2732 there would be so many units, so many tens, so many hun- | |
2733 dreds, &c., and it would have to be borne in mind that the | |
2734 squares of numbers from 1 to 9 lie between 1 and 99, the | |
2735 squares of numbers from 10 to 90 between 100 and 9900, and | |
2736 so on. Then the first term of the square root would be some | |
2737 number of tens or hundreds or thousands, and so on, and | |
2738 would have to be found in much the same way as the first | |
2739 term of a quotient in a long division, by trial if necessary. | |
2740 If <I>A</I> is the number the square root of which is required, while | |
2741 <I>a</I> represents the first term or denomination of the square root, | |
2742 and <I>x</I> the next term or denomination to be found, it would be | |
2743 necessary to use the identity <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>=<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>+2<I>ax</I>+<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> and to | |
2744 find <I>x</I> so that 2<I>ax</I>+<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP> might be somewhat less than the | |
2745 remainder <I>A-a</I><SUP>2</SUP>, i.e. we have to divide <I>A-a</I><SUP>2</SUP> by 2<I>a</I>, allowing | |
2746 for the fact that not only must 2<I>ax</I> (where <I>x</I> is the quotient) | |
2747 but also (2<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>)<I>x</I> be less than <I>A-a</I><SUP>2</SUP>. Thus, by trial, the | |
2748 highest possible value of <I>x</I> satisfying the condition would be | |
2749 easily found. If that value were <I>b</I>, the further quantity | |
2750 2<I>ab</I>+<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> would have to be subtracted from the first remainder | |
2751 <I>A-a</I><SUP>2</SUP>, and from the second remainder thus left a third term | |
2752 or denomination of the square root would have to be found in | |
2753 like manner; and so on. That this was the actual procedure | |
2754 followed is clear from a simple case given by Theon of Alex- | |
2755 andria in his commentary on the <I>Syntaxis</I>. Here the square | |
2756 root of 144 is in question, and it is obtained by means of | |
2757 <pb n=61><head>EXTRACTION OF THE SQUARE ROOT</head> | |
2758 Eucl. II. 4. The highest possible denomination (i.e. power | |
2759 of 10) in the square root is 10; 10<SUP>2</SUP> subtracted from 144 leaves | |
2760 44, and this must contain, not only twice the product of 10 | |
2761 and the next term of the square root, but also the square of | |
2762 the next term itself. Now twice 1.10 itself produces 20, and | |
2763 the division of 44 by 20 suggests 2 as the next term of the | |
2764 square root; this turns out to be the exact figure required, since | |
2765 <MATH>2.20+2<SUP>2</SUP>=44</MATH>. | |
2766 <p>The same procedure is illustrated by Theon's explanation | |
2767 of Ptolemy's method of extracting square roots according to | |
2768 the sexagesimal system of fractions. The problem is to find | |
2769 approximately the square root of 4500 <G>moi=rai</G> or <I>degrees</I>, and | |
2770 <FIG> | |
2771 a geometrical figure is used which proves beyond doubt the | |
2772 essentially Euclidean basis of the whole method. The follow- | |
2773 ing arithmetical representation of the purport of the passage, | |
2774 when looked at in the light of the figure, will make the | |
2775 matter clear. Ptolemy has first found the integral part of | |
2776 √(4500) to be 67. Now 67<SUP>2</SUP>=4489, so that the remainder is | |
2777 11. Suppose now that the rest of the square root is expressed | |
2778 by means of sexagesimal fractions, and that we may therefore | |
2779 write | |
2780 <MATH>√(4500)=67+<I>x</I>/(60)+<I>y</I>/(60)<SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>, | |
2781 where <I>x, y</I> are yet to be found. Thus <I>x</I> must be such that | |
2782 2.67<I>x</I>/60 is somewhat less than 11, or <I>x</I> must be somewhat | |
2783 <pb n=62><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2784 less than (11.60)/(2.67) or (330)/(67), which is at the same time greater than | |
2785 4. On trial it turns out that 4 will satisfy the conditions of | |
2786 the problem, namely that <MATH>(67+4/(60))<SUP>2</SUP></MATH> must be less than 4500, | |
2787 so that a remainder will be left by means of which <I>y</I> can be | |
2788 found. | |
2789 <p>Now this remainder is <MATH>11-(2.67.4)/(60)-(4/(60))<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, and this is | |
2790 equal to <MATH>(11.60<SUP>2</SUP>-2.67.4.60-16)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> or (7424)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>). | |
2791 <p>Thus we must suppose that <MATH>2(67+4/(60))<I>y</I>/(60<SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> approximates to | |
2792 (7424)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>), or that 8048<I>y</I> is approximately equal to 7424.60. | |
2793 Therefore <I>y</I> is approximately equal to 55. | |
2794 <p>We have then to subtract <MATH>2(67+4/(60))(55)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>)+((55)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, or | |
2795 <MATH>(442640)/(60<SUP>3</SUP>)+(3025)/(60<SUP>4</SUP>)</MATH>, from the remainder (7424)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>) above found. | |
2796 <p>The subtraction of (442640)/(60<SUP>3</SUP>) from (7424)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>) gives (2800)/(60<SUP>3</SUP>) or <MATH>(46)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>)+(40)/(60<SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>; | |
2797 but Theon does not go further and subtract the remaining | |
2798 (3025)/(60<SUP>4</SUP>); he merely remarks that the square of (55)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>) approximates | |
2799 to <MATH>(46)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>)+(40)/(60<SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>. As a matter of fact, if we deduct the (3025)/(60<SUP>4</SUP>) from | |
2800 (2800)/(60<SUP>3</SUP>), so as to obtain the correct remainder, it is found | |
2801 to be (164975)/(60<SUP>4</SUP>). | |
2802 <p>Theon's plan does not work conveniently, so far as the | |
2803 determination of the first fractional term (the <I>first-sixtieths</I>) | |
2804 is concerned, unless the integral term in the square root is | |
2805 large relatively to <I>x</I>/(60); if this is not the case, the term (<I>x</I>/(60))<SUP>2</SUP> is | |
2806 not comparatively negligible, and the tentative ascertainment | |
2807 of <I>x</I> is more difficult. Take the case of √3, the value of which, | |
2808 in Ptolemy's Table of Chords, is equal to <MATH>1+(43)/(60)+(55)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>)+(23)/(60<SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>. | |
2809 <pb n=63><head>EXTRACTION OF THE SQUARE ROOT</head> | |
2810 If we first found the unit 1 and then tried to find the next | |
2811 term by trial, it would probably involve a troublesome amount | |
2812 of trials. An alternative method in such a case was to | |
2813 multiply the number by 60<SUP>2</SUP>, thus reducing it to second- | |
2814 sixtieths, and then, taking the square root, to ascertain the | |
2815 number of first-sixtieths in it. Now 3.60<SUP>2</SUP>=10800, and, as | |
2816 103<SUP>2</SUP>=10609, the first element in the square root of 3 is | |
2817 found in this way to be <MATH>(103)/(60)(=1+(43)/(60))</MATH>. That this was the | |
2818 method in such cases is indicated by the fact that, in the Table | |
2819 of Chords, each chord is expressed as a certain number of | |
2820 first-sixtieths, followed by the second-sixtieths, &c., √3 being | |
2821 expressed as <MATH>(103)/(60)+(55)/(60<SUP>2</SUP>)+(23)/(60<SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>. The same thing is indicated by | |
2822 the scholiast to Eucl., Book X, who begins the operation of | |
2823 finding the square root of 31 10′36″ by reducing this to | |
2824 second-sixtieths; the number of second-sixtieths is 112236, | |
2825 which gives, as the number of first-sixtieths in the square | |
2826 root, 335, while <MATH>(335)/(60)=5 35′</MATH>. The second-sixtieths in the | |
2827 square root can then be found in the same way as in Theon's | |
2828 example. Or, as the scholiast says, we can obtain the square | |
2829 root as far as the second-sixtieths by reducing the original | |
2830 number to fourth-sixtieths, and so on. This would no doubt | |
2831 be the way in which the approximate value 2 49′42″20‴10′′′′ | |
2832 given by the scholiast for √8 was obtained, and similarly | |
2833 with other approximations of his, such as <MATH>√2=1 24′51″</MATH> and | |
2834 <MATH>√(27)=5 11′ 46″ 50‴</MATH> (the 50‴ should be 10‴). | |
2835 <C>(<G>z</G>) <I>Extraction of the cube root</I></C> | |
2836 <p>Our method of extracting the cube root of a number depends | |
2837 upon the formula <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>)<SUP>3</SUP>=<I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>+3<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>x</I>+3<I>ax</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>x</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH>, just as the | |
2838 extraction of the square root depends on the formula | |
2839 <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>=<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>+2<I>ax</I>+<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. As we have seen, the Greek method | |
2840 of extracting the square root was to use the latter (Euclidean) | |
2841 formula just as we do; but in no extant Greek writer do we | |
2842 find any description of the operation of extracting the cube | |
2843 root. It is possible that the Greeks had not much occasion | |
2844 for extracting cube roots, or that a table of cubes would | |
2845 suffice for most of their purposes. But that they had some | |
2846 <pb n=64><head>GREEK NUMERICAL NOTATION</head> | |
2847 method is clear from a passage of Heron, where he gives 4 9/(14) | |
2848 as an approximation to √<SUP>3</SUP>(100), and shows how he obtains it.<note>Heron, <I>Metrica</I>, iii. c. 20.</note> | |
2849 Heron merely gives the working dogmatically, in concrete | |
2850 numbers, without explaining its theoretical basis, and we | |
2851 cannot be quite certain as to the precise formula underlying | |
2852 the operation. The best suggestion which has been made on | |
2853 the subject will be given in its proper place, the chapter | |
2854 on Heron. | |
2855 <pb><C>III</C> | |
2856 <C>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</C> | |
2857 <p>THERE is very little early evidence regarding Pythagoras's | |
2858 own achievements, and what there is does not touch his mathe- | |
2859 matics. The earliest philosophers and historians who refer | |
2860 to him would not be interested in this part of his work. | |
2861 Heraclitus speaks of his wide knowledge, but with disparage- | |
2862 ment: ‘much learning does not teach wisdom; otherwise | |
2863 it would have taught Hesiod and Pythagoras, and again | |
2864 Xenophanes and Hecataeus’.<note>Diog. L. ix. 1 (Fr. 40 in <I>Vorsokratiker,</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 86. 1-3).</note> Herodotus alludes to Pytha- | |
2865 goras and the Pythagoreans several times; he calls Pythagoras | |
2866 ‘the most able philosopher among the Greeks’ (<G>*(ellh/nwn on) | |
2867 tw=| a)sqenesta/tw| sofisth=| *puqago/rh|</G>).<note>Herodotus, iv. 95.</note> In Empedocles he had | |
2868 an enthusiastic admirer: ‘But there was among them a man | |
2869 of prodigious knowledge who acquired the profoundest wealth | |
2870 of understanding and was the greatest master of skilled arts | |
2871 of every kind; for, whenever he willed with his whole heart, | |
2872 he could with ease discern each and every truth in his ten— | |
2873 nay, twenty—men's lives.’<note>Diog. L. viii. 54 and Porph. <I>V. Pyth.</I> 30 (Fr. 129 in <I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 272. 15-20).</note> | |
2874 <p>Pythagoras himself left no written exposition of his | |
2875 doctrines, nor did any of his immediate successors, not even | |
2876 Hippasus, about whom the different stories ran (1) that he | |
2877 was expelled from the school because he published doctrines | |
2878 of Pythagoras, and (2) that he was drowned at sea for | |
2879 revealing the construction of the dodecahedron in the sphere | |
2880 and claiming it as his own, or (as others have it) for making | |
2881 known the discovery of the irrational or incommensurable. | |
2882 Nor is the absence of any written record of Pythagorean | |
2883 <pb n=66><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
2884 doctrines down to the time of Philolaus to be attributed | |
2885 to a pledge of secrecy binding the school; at all events, it | |
2886 did not apply to their mathematics or their physics; the | |
2887 supposed secrecy may even have been invented to explain | |
2888 the absence of documents. The fact appears to be that oral | |
2889 communication was the tradition of the school, while their | |
2890 doctrine would in the main be too abstruse to be understood | |
2891 by the generality of people outside. | |
2892 <p>In these circumstances it is difficult to disentangle the | |
2893 portions of the Pythagorean philosophy which can safely | |
2894 be attributed to the founder of the school. Aristotle evi- | |
2895 dently felt this difficulty; it is clear that he knew nothing | |
2896 for certain of any ethical or physical doctrines going back | |
2897 to Pythagoras himself; and when he speaks of the Pytha- | |
2898 gorean system, he always refers it to ‘the Pythagoreans’, | |
2899 sometimes even to ‘the so-called Pythagoreans’. | |
2900 <p>The earliest direct testimony to the eminence of Pythagoras | |
2901 in mathematical studies seems to be that of Aristotle, who in | |
2902 his separate book <I>On the Pythagoreans</I>, now lost, wrote that | |
2903 <p>‘Pythagoras, the son of Mnesarchus, first worked at mathe- | |
2904 matics and arithmetic, and afterwards, at one time, condescended | |
2905 to the wonder-working practised by Pherecydes.’<note>Apollonius, <I>Hist. mirabil.</I> 6 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 29. 5).</note> | |
2906 <p>In the <I>Metaphysics</I> he speaks in similar terms of the | |
2907 Pythagoreans: | |
2908 <p>‘In the time of these philosophers (Leucippus and | |
2909 Democritus) and before them the so-called Pythagoreans | |
2910 applied themselves to the study of mathematics, and were | |
2911 the first to advance that science; insomuch that, having been | |
2912 brought up in it, they thought that its principles must be | |
2913 the principles of all existing things.’<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> A. 5, 985 b 23.</note> | |
2914 <p>It is certain that the Theory of Numbers originated in | |
2915 the school of Pythagoras; and, with regard to Pythagoras | |
2916 himself, we are told by Aristoxenus that he ‘seems to have | |
2917 attached supreme importance to the study of arithmetic, | |
2918 which he advanced and took out of the region of commercial | |
2919 utility’.<note>Stobaeus, <I>Ecl.</I> i. proem. 6 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 346. 12).</note> | |
2920 <pb n=67><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
2921 <C>Numbers and the universe.</C> | |
2922 <p>We know that Thales (about 624-547 B.C.) and Anaximander | |
2923 (born probably in 611/10 B.C.) occupied themselves with | |
2924 astronomical phenomena, and, even before their time, the | |
2925 principal constellations had been distinguished. Pythagoras | |
2926 (about 572-497 B.C. or a little later) seems to have been | |
2927 the first Greek to discover that the planets have an inde- | |
2928 pendent movement of their own from west to east, i.e. in | |
2929 a direction contrary to the daily rotation of the fixed stars; | |
2930 or he may have learnt what he knew of the planets from the | |
2931 Babylonians. Now any one who was in the habit of intently | |
2932 studying the heavens would naturally observe that each | |
2933 constellation has two characteristics, the number of the stars | |
2934 which compose it and the geometrical figure which they | |
2935 form. Here, as a recent writer has remarked,<note>L. Brunschvicg, <I>Les étapes de la philosophie mathématique</I>, 1912, p. 33.</note> we find, if not | |
2936 the origin, a striking illustration of the Pythagorean doctrine. | |
2937 And, just as the constellations have a number characteristic | |
2938 of them respectively, so all known objects have a number; | |
2939 as the formula of Philolaus states, ‘all things which can | |
2940 be known have number; for it is not possible that without | |
2941 number anything can either be conceived or known’.<note>Stob. <I>Ecl.</I> i. 21, 7<SUP>b</SUP> (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 310. 8-10).</note> | |
2942 <p>This formula, however, does not yet express all the content | |
2943 of the Pythagorean doctrine. Not only do all things possess | |
2944 numbers; but, in addition, all things <I>are</I> numbers; ‘these | |
2945 thinkers’, says Aristotle, ‘seem to consider that number is | |
2946 the principle both as matter for things and as constituting | |
2947 their attributes and permanent states’.<note>Aristotle, <I>Metaph.</I> A. 5, 986 a 16.</note> True, Aristotle | |
2948 seems to regard the theory as originally based on the analogy | |
2949 between the properties of things and of numbers. | |
2950 <p>‘They thought they found in numbers, more than in fire, | |
2951 earth, or water, many resemblances to things which are and | |
2952 become; thus such and such an attribute of numbers is jus- | |
2953 tice, another is soul and mind, another is opportunity, and so | |
2954 on; and again they saw in numbers the attributes and ratios | |
2955 of the musical scales. Since, then, all other things seemed | |
2956 in their whole nature to be assimilated to numbers, while | |
2957 numbers seemed to be the first things in the whole of nature, | |
2958 <pb n=68><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
2959 they supposed the elements of numbers to be the elements | |
2960 of all things, and the whole heaven to be a musical scale and | |
2961 a number.’<note><I>Metaph.</I> A. 5, 985 b 27-986 a 2.</note> | |
2962 <p>This passage, with its assertion of ‘resemblances’ and | |
2963 ‘assimilation’, suggests numbers as affections, states, or rela- | |
2964 tions rather than as substances, and the same is implied by | |
2965 the remark that existing things exist by virtue of their | |
2966 <I>imitation</I> of numbers.<note><I>Ib.</I> A. 5, 987 b 11.</note> But again we are told that the | |
2967 numbers are not separable from the things, but that existing | |
2968 things, even perceptible substances, are made up of numbers; | |
2969 that the substance of all things is number, that things are | |
2970 numbers, that numbers are made up from the unit, and that the | |
2971 whole heaven is numbers.<note><I>Ib.</I> N. 3, 1090 a 22-23; M. 7, 1080 b 17; A. 5, 987 a 19, 987 b 27, 986 a 20.</note> Still more definite is the statement | |
2972 that the Pythagoreans ‘construct the whole heaven out of | |
2973 numbers, but not of <I>monadic</I> numbers, since they suppose the | |
2974 units to have magnitude’, and that, ‘as we have said before, | |
2975 the Pythagoreans assume the numbers to have magnitude’.<note><I>Ib.</I> M. 7, 1080 b 18, 32.</note> | |
2976 Aristotle points out certain obvious difficulties. On the one | |
2977 hand the Pythagoreans speak of ‘this number of which the | |
2978 heaven is composed’; on the other hand they speak of ‘attri- | |
2979 butes of numbers’ and of numbers as ‘the <I>causes</I> of the things | |
2980 which exist and take place in the heaven both from the begin- | |
2981 ning and now’. Again, according to them, abstractions and | |
2982 immaterial things are also numbers, and they place them in | |
2983 different regions; for example, in one region they place | |
2984 opinion and opportunity, and in another, a little higher up or | |
2985 lower down, such things as injustice, sifting, or mixing. | |
2986 Is it this same ‘number in the heaven’ which we must | |
2987 assume each of these things to be, or a number other than | |
2988 this number?<note><I>Ib.</I> A. 8, 990 a 18-29.</note> | |
2989 <p>May we not infer from these scattered remarks of Aristotle | |
2990 about the Pythagorean doctrine that ‘the number in the | |
2991 heaven’ is the number of the visible stars, made up of | |
2992 units which are material points? And may this not be | |
2993 the origin of the theory that all things are numbers, a | |
2994 theory which of course would be confirmed when the further | |
2995 <pb n=69><head>NUMBERS AND THE UNIVERSE</head> | |
2996 capital discovery was made that musical harmonies depend | |
2997 on numerical ratios, the octave representing the ratio 2:1 | |
2998 in length of string, the fifth 3:2 and the fourth 4:3? | |
2999 <p>The use by the Pythagoreans of visible points to represent | |
3000 the units of a number of a particular form is illustrated by | |
3001 the remark of Aristotle that | |
3002 <p>‘Eurytus settled what is the number of what object (e.g. | |
3003 this is the number of a man, that of a horse) and imitated | |
3004 the shapes of living things by pebbles <I>after the manner of | |
3005 those who bring numbers into the forms of triangle or | |
3006 square</I>’.<note><I>Metaph.</I> N. 5, 1092 b 10.</note> | |
3007 <p>They treated the unit, which is a point without position | |
3008 (<G>stigmh\ a)/qetos</G>), as a point, and a point as a unit having | |
3009 position (<G>mona\s qe/sin e)/xousa</G>).<note><I>Ib.</I> M. 8, 1084 b 25; <I>De an.</I> i. 4, 409 a 6; Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 95. 21.</note> | |
3010 <C>Definitions of the unit and of number.</C> | |
3011 <p>Aristotle observes that the One is reasonably regarded as | |
3012 not being itself a number, because a measure is not the things | |
3013 measured, but the measure or the One is the beginning (or | |
3014 principle) of number.<note><I>Metaph.</I> N. 1, 1088 a 6.</note> This doctrine may be of Pythagorean | |
3015 origin; Nicomachus has it<note>Nicom. <I>Introd. arithm.</I> ii. 6. 3, 7. 3.</note>; Euclid implies it when he says | |
3016 that a unit is that by virtue of which each of existing things | |
3017 is called one, while a number is ‘the multitude made up of | |
3018 units’<note>Eucl. VII, Defs. 1, 2.</note>; and the statement was generally accepted. According | |
3019 to Iamblichus,<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom. ar. introd.</I>, p. 11. 2-10.</note> Thymaridas (an ancient Pythagorean, probably | |
3020 not later than Plato's time) defined a unit as ‘limiting quan- | |
3021 tity’ (<G>perai/nousa poso/ths</G>) or, as we might say, ‘limit of few- | |
3022 ness’, while some Pythagoreans called it ‘the confine between | |
3023 number and parts’, i.e. that which separates multiples | |
3024 and submultiples. Chrysippus (third century B.C.) called it | |
3025 ‘multitude one’ (<G>plh=qos e(/n</G>), a definition objected to by | |
3026 Iamblichus as a contradiction in terms, but important as an | |
3027 attempt to bring 1 into the conception of number. | |
3028 <p>The first definition of number is attributed to Thales, who | |
3029 defined it as a collection of units (<G>mona/dwn su/sthma</G>), ‘follow- | |
3030 <pb n=70><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3031 ing the Egyptian view’.<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom. ar. introd.</I>, p. 10. 8-10.</note> The Pythagoreans ‘made number | |
3032 out of one’<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> A. 5, 986 a 20.</note> some of them called it ‘a progression of multi- | |
3033 tude beginning from a unit and a regression ending in it’.<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 18. 3-5.</note> | |
3034 (Stobaeus credits Moderatus, a Neo-Pythagorean of the time | |
3035 of Nero, with this definition.<note>Stob. <I>Ecl.</I> i. pr. 8.</note>) Eudoxus defined number as | |
3036 a ‘determinate multitude’ (<G>plh=qos w(risme/non</G>).<note>Iambl. <I>op. cit.</I>, p. 10. 17.</note> Nicoma- | |
3037 chus has yet another definition, ‘a flow of quantity made up | |
3038 of units’<note>Nicom. i. 7. 1.</note> (<G>poso/thtos xu/ma e)k mona/dwn sugkei/menon</G>). Aris- | |
3039 totle gives a number of definitions equivalent to one or other | |
3040 of those just mentioned, ‘limited multitude’,<note><I>Metaph.</I> ▵. 13, 1020 a 13.</note> ‘multitude (or | |
3041 ‘combination’) of units’,<note><I>Ib.</I> I. 1, 1053 a 30; Z. 13, 1039 a 12.</note> ‘multitude of indivisibles’,<note><I>Ib.</I> M. 9, 1085 b 22.</note> ‘several | |
3042 ones’ (<G>e(/na plei/w</G>),<note><I>Phys.</I> iii. 7, 207 b 7.</note> ‘multitude measurable by one’,<note><I>Metaph.</I> I. 6, 1057 a 3.</note> ‘multi- | |
3043 tude measured’, and ‘multitude of measures’<note><I>Ib.</I> N. 1, 1088 a 5.</note> (the measure | |
3044 being the unit). | |
3045 <C>Classification of numbers.</C> | |
3046 <p>The distinction between <I>odd</I> (<G>perisso/s</G>) and <I>even</I> (<G>a)/rtios</G>) | |
3047 doubtless goes back to Pythagoras. A Philolaus fragment | |
3048 says that ‘number is of two special kinds, odd and even, with | |
3049 a third, even-odd, arising from a mixture of the two; and of | |
3050 each kind there are many forms’.<note>Stob. <I>Ecl.</I> i. 21. 7<SUP>c</SUP> (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 310. 11-14).</note> According to Nicomachus, | |
3051 the Pythagorean definitions of odd and even were these: | |
3052 <p>‘An <I>even</I> number is that which admits of being divided, by | |
3053 one and the same operation, into the greatest and the least | |
3054 parts, greatest in size but least in number (i. e. into <I>two halves</I>) | |
3055 ..., while an <I>odd</I> number is that which cannot be so divided | |
3056 but is only divisible into two unequal parts.’<note>Nicom. i. 7. 3.</note> | |
3057 <p>Nicomachus gives another ancient definition to the effect | |
3058 that | |
3059 ‘an <I>even</I> number is that which can be divided both into two | |
3060 equal parts and into two unequal parts (except the funda- | |
3061 mental dyad which can only be divided into two equal parts), | |
3062 but, however it is divided, must have its two parts <I>of the same | |
3063 kind</I> without part in the other kind (i. e. the two parts are | |
3064 <pb n=71><head>CLASSIFICATION OF NUMBERS</head> | |
3065 both odd or both even); while an <I>odd</I> number is that which, | |
3066 however divided, must in any case fall into two unequal parts, | |
3067 and those parts always belonging to the two <I>different</I> kinds | |
3068 respectively (i.e. one being odd and one even).’<note>Nicom. i. 7. 4.</note> | |
3069 <p>In the latter definition we have a trace of the original | |
3070 conception of 2 (the dyad) as being, not a number at all, but | |
3071 the principle or beginning of the even, just as one was not a | |
3072 number but the principle or beginning of number; the defini- | |
3073 tion implies that 2 was not originally regarded as an even | |
3074 number, the qualification made by Nicomachus with reference | |
3075 to the dyad being evidently a later addition to the original | |
3076 definition (Plato already speaks of two as even).<note>Plato, <I>Parmenides</I>, 143 D.</note> | |
3077 <p>With regard to the term ‘odd-even’, it is to be noted that, | |
3078 according to Aristotle, the Pythagoreans held that ‘the One | |
3079 arises from both kinds (the odd and the even), for it is both | |
3080 even and odd’.<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> A. 5, 986 a 19.</note> The explanation of this strange view might | |
3081 apparently be that the unit, being the principle of all number, | |
3082 even as well as odd, cannot itself be odd and must therefore | |
3083 be called even-odd. There is, however, another explanation, | |
3084 attributed by Theon of Smyrna to Aristotle, to the effect that the | |
3085 unit when added to an even number makes an odd number, but | |
3086 when added to an odd number makes an even number: which | |
3087 could not be the case if it did not partake of both species; | |
3088 Theon also mentions Archytas as being in agreement with this | |
3089 view.<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 22. 5-10.</note> But, inasmuch as the fragment of Philolaus speaks of | |
3090 ‘many forms’ of the species odd and even, and ‘a third’ | |
3091 (even-odd) obtained from a combination of them, it seems | |
3092 more natural to take ‘even-odd’ as there meaning, not the | |
3093 unit, but the product of an odd and an even number, while, if | |
3094 ‘even’ in the same passage excludes such a number, ‘even’ | |
3095 would appear to be confined to powers of 2, or 2<SUP><I>n</I></SUP>. | |
3096 <p>We do not know how far the Pythagoreans advanced | |
3097 towards the later elaborate classification of the varieties of | |
3098 odd and even numbers. But they presumably had not got | |
3099 beyond the point of view of Plato and Euclid. In Plato we | |
3100 have the terms ‘even-times even’ (<G>a)/rtia a)rtia/kis</G>), ‘odd- | |
3101 times odd’ (<G>peritta\ peritta/kis</G>), ‘odd-times even’ (<G>a)/rtia</G> | |
3102 <pb n=72><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3103 <G>peritta/kis</G>) and ‘even-times odd’ (<G>peritta\ a)rtia/kis</G>), which | |
3104 are evidently used in the simple sense of the products of even | |
3105 and even, odd and odd, odd and even, and even and odd | |
3106 factors respectively.<note>Plato, <I>Parmenides</I>, 143 E.</note> Euclid's classification does not go much | |
3107 beyond this; he does not attempt to make the four defini- | |
3108 tions mutually exclusive.<note>See Eucl. VII. Defs. 8-10.</note> An ‘odd-times odd’ number is of | |
3109 course any odd number which is not prime; but ‘even-times | |
3110 even’ (‘a number measured by an even number according to | |
3111 an even number’) does not exclude ‘even-times odd’ (‘a | |
3112 number measured by an even number according to an odd | |
3113 number’); e.g. 24, which is 6 times 4, or 4 times 6, is also | |
3114 8 times 3. Euclid did not apparently distinguish, any more | |
3115 than Plato, between ‘even-times odd’ and ‘odd-times even’ | |
3116 (the definition of the latter in the texts of Euclid was pro- | |
3117 bably interpolated). The Neo-Pythagoreans improved the | |
3118 classification thus. With them the ‘even-times even’ number | |
3119 is that which has its halves even, the halves of the halves | |
3120 even, and so on till unity is reached’<note>Nicom. i. 8. 4.</note>; in short, it is a number | |
3121 of the form 2<SUP><I>n</I></SUP>. The ‘even-odd’ number (<G>a)rtiope/rittos</G> in one | |
3122 word) is such a number as, when once halved, leaves as quo- | |
3123 tient an odd number,<note><I>Ib.</I> i. 9. 1.</note> i.e. a number of the form 2 (2<I>m</I>+1). | |
3124 The ‘odd-even’ number (<G>perissa/rtios</G>) is a number such that | |
3125 it can be halved twice or more times successively, but the | |
3126 quotient left when it can no longer be halved is an odd num- | |
3127 ber not unity,<note><I>Ib.</I> i. 10. 1.</note> i.e. it is a number of the form 2<SUP><I>n</I>+1</SUP> (2<I>m</I>+1). | |
3128 The ‘odd-times odd’ number is not defined as such by | |
3129 Nicomachus and Iamblichus, but Theon of Smyrna quotes | |
3130 a curious use of the term; he says that it was one of the | |
3131 names applied to prime numbers (excluding of course 2), for | |
3132 these have two odd factors, namely 1 and the number itself.<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 23. 14-23.</note> | |
3133 <p><I>Prime</I> or <I>incomposite</I> numbers (<G>prw=tos kai\ a)su/nqetos</G>) and | |
3134 <I>secondary</I> or <I>composite</I> numbers (<G>deu/teros kai\ su/nqetos</G>) are | |
3135 distinguished in a fragment of Speusippus based upon works | |
3136 of Philolaus.<note><I>Theol. Ar.</I> (Ast), p. 62 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 304. 5).</note> We are told<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 27. 4.</note> that Thymaridas called a prime | |
3137 number <I>rectilinear</I> (<G>eu)qugrammiko/s</G>), the ground being that it | |
3138 can only be set out in one dimension<note>Cf. Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> ▵. 13, 1020 b 3<SUP>'</SUP>, 4.</note> (since the only measure | |
3139 <pb n=73><head>CLASSIFICATION OF NUMBERS</head> | |
3140 of it, excluding the number itself, is 1); Theon of Smyrna | |
3141 gives <I>euthymetric</I> and <I>linear</I> as alternative terms,<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 23. 12.</note> and the | |
3142 latter (<G>grammiko/s</G>) also occurs in the fragment of Speusippus. | |
3143 Strictly speaking, the prime number should have been called | |
3144 that which is rectilinear or linear <I>only.</I> As we have seen, | |
3145 2 was not originally regarded as a prime number, or even as | |
3146 a number at all. But Aristotle speaks of the dyad as ‘the | |
3147 only even number which is prime,’<note>Arist. <I>Topics</I>, q. 2, 157 a 39.</note> showing that this diver- | |
3148 gence from early Pythagorean doctrine took place before | |
3149 Euclid's time. Euclid defined a prime number as ‘that which | |
3150 is measured by a unit alone’,<note>Eucl. VII. Def. 11.</note> a composite number as ‘that | |
3151 which is measured by some number’,<note><I>Ib.</I> Def. 13.</note> while he adds defini- | |
3152 tions of numbers ‘prime to one another’ (‘those which are | |
3153 measured by a unit alone as a common measure’) and of | |
3154 numbers ‘composite to one another’ (‘those which are mea- | |
3155 sured by some number as a common measure’).<note><I>Ib.</I> Defs. 12, 14.</note> Euclid then, | |
3156 as well as Aristotle, includes 2 among prime numbers. Theon | |
3157 of Smyrna says that even numbers are not measured by the | |
3158 unit alone, except 2, which therefore is odd-<I>like</I> without being | |
3159 prime.<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 24. 7.</note> The Neo-Pythagoreans, Nicomachus and Iamblichus, | |
3160 not only exclude 2 from prime numbers, but define composite | |
3161 numbers, numbers prime to one another, and numbers com- | |
3162 posite to one another as excluding all even numbers; they | |
3163 make all these categories subdivisions of <I>odd.</I><note>Nicom. i, cc. 11-13; Iambl. <I>in N<SUP>^</SUP>icom.</I>, pp. 26-8.</note> Their object | |
3164 is to divide odd into three classes parallel to the three subdivi- | |
3165 sions of even, namely even-even = 2<SUP><I>n</I></SUP>, even-odd = 2 (2<I>m</I>+1) | |
3166 and the quasi-intermediate odd-even = 2<SUP><I>n</I>+1</SUP> (2<I>m</I>+1); accord- | |
3167 ingly they divide odd numbers into (<I>a</I>) the prime and | |
3168 incomposite, which are Euclid's primes excluding 2, (<I>b</I>) the | |
3169 secondary and composite, the factors of which must all be not | |
3170 only odd but prime numbers, (<I>c</I>) those which are ‘secondary and | |
3171 composite in themselves but prime and incomposite to another | |
3172 number,’ e.g. 9 and 25, which are both secondary and com- | |
3173 posite but have no common measure except 1. The incon- | |
3174 venience of the restriction in (<I>b</I>) is obvious, and there is the | |
3175 <pb n=74><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3176 further objection that (<I>b</I>) and (<I>c</I>) overlap, in fact (<I>b</I>) includes | |
3177 the whole of (<I>c</I>). | |
3178 <C>‘Perfect’ and ‘Friendly’ numbers.</C> | |
3179 <p>There is no trace in the fragments of Philolaus, in Plato or | |
3180 Aristotle, or anywhere before Euclid, of the <I>perfect</I> number | |
3181 (<G>te/leios</G>) in the well-known sense of Euclid's definition | |
3182 (VII. Def. 22), a number, namely, which is ‘equal to (the | |
3183 sum of) its own parts’ (i.e. all its factors including 1), | |
3184 e.g. | |
3185 <MATH>6=1+2+3; 28=1+2+4+7+14; | |
3186 496=1+2+4+8+16+31+62+124+248</MATH>. | |
3187 The law of the formation of these numbers is proved in | |
3188 Eucl. IX. 36, which is to the effect that, if the sum of any | |
3189 number of terms of the series 1, 2, 2<SUP>2</SUP>, 2<SUP>3</SUP> .... 2<SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP>(=<I>S<SUB>n</SUB></I>) is prime, | |
3190 then <I>S<SUB>n</SUB></I>.2<SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP> is a ‘perfect’ number. Theon of Smyrna<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 45.</note> and | |
3191 Nicomachus<note>Nicom. i. 16, 1-4.</note> both define a ‘perfect’ number and explain the | |
3192 law of its formation; they further distinguish from it two | |
3193 other kinds of numbers, (1) <I>over-perfect</I> (<G>u(pertelh/s</G> or <G>u(perte/- | |
3194 leios</G>), so called because the sum of all its aliquot parts is | |
3195 greater than the number itself, e.g. 12, which is less than | |
3196 1+2+3+4+6, (2) <I>defective</I> (<G>e)lliph/s</G>), so called because the | |
3197 sum of all its aliquot parts is less than the number itself, | |
3198 e.g. 8, which is greater than 1+2+4. Of perfect numbers | |
3199 Nicomachus knew four (namely 6, 28, 496, 8128) but no more. | |
3200 He says they are formed in ‘ordered’ fashion, there being one | |
3201 among the units (i. e. less than 10), one among the tens (less | |
3202 than 100), one among the hundreds (less than 1000), and one | |
3203 among the thousands (less than a myriad); he adds that they | |
3204 terminate alternately in 6 or 8. They do all terminate in 6 or | |
3205 8 (as we can easily prove by means of the formula (2<SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP>) 2<SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP>), | |
3206 but not alternately, for the fifth and sixth perfect numbers | |
3207 both end in 6, and the seventh and eighth both end in 8. | |
3208 Iamblichus adds a tentative suggestion that there may (<G>ei) | |
3209 tu/xoi</G>) in like manner be one perfect number among the first | |
3210 myriads (less than 10000<SUP>2</SUP>), one among the second myriads | |
3211 (less than 10000<SUP>3</SUP>), and so on <I>ad infinitum.</I><note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 33. 20-23.</note> This is incorrect, | |
3212 for the next perfect numbers are as follows:<note>The fifth perfect number may have been known to Iamblichus, | |
3213 though he does not give it; it was, however, known, with all its factors, | |
3214 in the fifteenth century, as appears from a tract written in German | |
3215 which was discovered by Curtze (Cod. lat. Monac. 14908). The first | |
3216 eight ‘perfect’ numbers were calculated by Jean Prestet (d. 1670); | |
3217 Fermat (1601-65) had stated, and Euler proved, that 2<SUP>31</SUP>-1 is prime. | |
3218 The ninth perfect number was found by P. Seelhoff, <I>Zeitschr. f. Math. u. | |
3219 Physik</I>, 1886, pp. 174 sq.) and verified by E. Lucas (<I>Mathésis</I>, vii, 1887, | |
3220 pp. 44-6). The tenth was found by R. E. Powers (<I>Bull. Amer. Math. | |
3221 Soc.</I>, 1912, p. 162).</note> | |
3222 <pb n=75><head>‘PERFECT’, AND ‘FRIENDLY’ NUMBERS</head> | |
3223 fifth, <MATH>2<SUP>12</SUP> (2<SUP>13</SUP>-1)=33 550 336</MATH> | |
3224 sixth, <MATH>2<SUP>16</SUP> (2<SUP>17</SUP>-1)=8 589 869 056</MATH> | |
3225 seventh, <MATH>2<SUP>18</SUP> (2<SUP>19</SUP>-1)=137 438 691 328</MATH> | |
3226 eighth, <MATH>2<SUP>30</SUP> (2<SUP>31</SUP>-1)=2 305 843 008 139 952 128</MATH> | |
3227 ninth, <MATH>2<SUP>60</SUP> (2<SUP>61</SUP>-1)=2 658 455 991 569 831 744 654 692 | |
3228 615 953 842 176</MATH> | |
3229 tenth, <MATH>2<SUP>88</SUP> (2<SUP>89</SUP>-1)</MATH>. | |
3230 With these ‘perfect’ numbers should be compared the so- | |
3231 called ‘friendly numbers’. Two numbers are ‘friendly’ when | |
3232 each is the sum of all the aliquot parts of the other, e.g. 284 and | |
3233 220 (for <MATH>284=1+2+4+5+10+11+20+22+44+55+110</MATH>, | |
3234 while <MATH>220=1+2+4+71+142</MATH>). Iamblichus attributes the | |
3235 discovery of such numbers to Pythagoras himself, who, being | |
3236 asked ‘what is a friend?’ said ‘<I>Alter ego</I>’, and on this analogy | |
3237 applied the term ‘friendly’ to two numbers the aliquot parts | |
3238 of either of which make up the other.<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 35. 1-7. The subject of ‘friendly’ numbers | |
3239 was taken up by Euler, who discovered no less than sixty-one pairs of | |
3240 such numbers. Descartes and van Schooten had previously found three | |
3241 pairs but no more.</note> | |
3242 <p>While for Euclid, Theon of Smyrna, and the Neo-Pytha- | |
3243 goreans the ‘perfect’ number was the kind of number above | |
3244 described, we are told that the Pythagoreans made 10 the | |
3245 perfect number. Aristotle says that this was because they | |
3246 found within it such things as the void, proportion, oddness, | |
3247 and so on.<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> M. 8, 1084 a 32-4.</note> The reason is explained more in detail by Theon | |
3248 of Smyrna<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 93. 17-94. 9 (<I>Vorsokratiker</I>, i<SUP>3</SUP>, pp. 303-4).</note> and in the fragment of Speusippus. 10 is the | |
3249 sum of the numbers 1, 2, 3, 4 forming the <G>tetraktu/s</G> (‘their | |
3250 greatest oath’, alternatively called the ‘principle of health’<note>Lucian, <I>De lapsu in salutando</I>, 5.</note>). | |
3251 These numbers include the ratios corresponding to the musical | |
3252 intervals discovered by Pythagoras, namely 4:3 (the fourth), | |
3253 <pb n=76><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3254 3:2 (the fifth), and 2:1 (the octave). Speusippus observes | |
3255 further that 10 contains in it the ‘linear’, ‘plane’ and ‘solid’ | |
3256 varieties of number; for 1 is a point, 2 is a line,<note>Cf. Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> Z. 10, 1036 b 12.</note> 3 a triangle, | |
3257 and 4 a pyramid.<note><I>Theol. Ar.</I> (Ast), p. 62. 17-22.</note> | |
3258 <C>Figured numbers.</C> | |
3259 <p>This brings us once more to the theory of figured numbers, | |
3260 which seems to go back to Pythagoras himself. A point or | |
3261 dot is used to represent 1; two dots placed apart represent | |
3262 2, and at the same time define the straight line joining the | |
3263 two dots; three dots, representing 3, mark out the first | |
3264 rectilinear plane figure, a triangle; four dots, one of which is | |
3265 outside the plane containing the other three, represent 4 and | |
3266 also define the first rectilineal solid figure. It seems clear | |
3267 that the oldest Pythagoreans were acquainted with the forma- | |
3268 tion of triangular and square numbers by means of pebbles or | |
3269 dots<note>Cf. Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> N. 5, 1092 b 12.</note>; and we judge from the account of Speusippus's book, | |
3270 <I>On the Pythagorean Numbers</I>, which was based on works of | |
3271 Philolaus, that the latter dealt with linear numbers, polygonal | |
3272 numbers, and plane and solid numbers of all sorts, as well as | |
3273 with the five regular solid figures.<note><I>Theol. Ar.</I> (Ast), p. 61.</note> The varieties of plane | |
3274 numbers (triangular, square, oblong, pentagonal, hexagonal, | |
3275 and so on), solid numbers (cube, pyramidal, &c.) are all dis- | |
3276 cussed, with the methods of their formation, by Nicomachus<note>Nicom. i. 7-11, 13-16, 17.</note> | |
3277 and Theon of Smyrna.<note>Theon of Smyrna, pp. 26-42.</note> | |
3278 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Triangular numbers.</I></C> | |
3279 <p>To begin with <I>triangular</I> numbers. It was probably | |
3280 Pythagoras who discovered that the sum of any number of | |
3281 successive terms of the series of natural numbers 1, 2, 3 ... | |
3282 beginning from 1 makes a triangular number. This is obvious | |
3283 enough from the following arrangements of rows of points; | |
3284 <FIG> | |
3285 Thus <MATH>1+2+3+...+<I>n</I>=1/2<I>n</I> (<I>n</I>+1)</MATH> is a triangular number | |
3286 <pb n=77><head>FIGURED NUMBERS</head> | |
3287 of side <I>n.</I> The particular triangle which has 4 for its side is | |
3288 mentioned in a story of Pythagoras by Lucian. Pythagoras | |
3289 told some one to count. He said 1, 2, 3, 4, whereon Pytha- | |
3290 goras interrupted, ‘Do you see? What you take for 4 is 10, | |
3291 a perfect triangle and our oath’.<note>Lucian, <G>*bi/wv pra=sis,</G> 4.</note> This connects the know- | |
3292 ledge of triangular numbers with true Pythagorean ideas. | |
3293 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>Square numbers and gnomons.</I></C> | |
3294 <p>We come now to <I>square</I> numbers. It is easy to see that, if | |
3295 we have a number of dots forming and filling | |
3296 up a square as in the accompanying figure repre- | |
3297 <FIG> | |
3298 senting 16, the square of 4, the next higher | |
3299 square, the square of 5, can be formed by adding | |
3300 a row of dots round two sides of the original | |
3301 square, as shown; the number of these dots is | |
3302 2.4+1, or 9. This process of forming successive squares can | |
3303 be applied throughout, beginning from the first square | |
3304 number 1. The successive additions are shown in the annexed | |
3305 figure between the successive pairs of straight | |
3306 <FIG> | |
3307 lines forming right angles; and the successive | |
3308 numbers added to the 1 are | |
3309 <MATH>3, 5, 7 ... (2<I>n</I>+1)</MATH>, | |
3310 that is to say, the successive odd numbers. | |
3311 This method of formation shows that the | |
3312 sum of any number of successive terms | |
3313 of the series of odd numbers 1, 3, 5, 7 ... starting from | |
3314 1 is a square number, that, if <I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP> is any square number, the | |
3315 addition of the odd number 2<I>n</I>+1 makes it into the next | |
3316 square, (<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP>, and that the sum of the series of odd num- | |
3317 bers <MATH>1+3+5+7+...+(2<I>n</I>+1)=(<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, while | |
3318 <MATH>1+3+5+7+...+(2<I>n</I>-1)=<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
3319 All this was known to Pythagoras. The odd numbers succes- | |
3320 sively added were called <I>gnomons</I>; this is clear from Aristotle's | |
3321 allusion to gnomons placed round 1 which now produce different | |
3322 figures every time (oblong figures, each dissimilar to the pre- | |
3323 ceding one), now preserve one and the same figure (squares)<note>Arist. <I>Phys.</I> iii. 4, 203 a 13-15.</note>; | |
3324 the latter is the case with the gnomons now in question. | |
3325 <pb n=78><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3326 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>History of the term ‘gnomon’.</I></C> | |
3327 <p>It will be noticed that the gnomons shown in the above | |
3328 figure correspond in shape to the geometrical gnomons with | |
3329 which Euclid, Book II, has made us familiar. The history of | |
3330 the word ‘gnomon’ is interesting. (1) It was originally an | |
3331 astronomical instrument for the measuring of time, and con- | |
3332 sisted of an upright stick which cast shadows on a plane or | |
3333 hemispherical surface. This instrument is said to have been | |
3334 introduced into Greece by Anaximander<note>Suidas, <I>s. v.</I></note> and to have come | |
3335 from Babylon.<note>Herodotus, ii. 109.</note> Following on this application of the word | |
3336 ‘gnomon’ (a ‘marker’ or ‘pointer’, a means of reading off and | |
3337 knowing something), we find Oenopides calling a perpendicular | |
3338 let fall on a straight line from an external point a straight line | |
3339 drawn ‘<I>gnomon-wise</I>’ (<G>kata\ gnw/mona</G>).<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 283. 9.</note> Next (2) we find the | |
3340 term used of an instrument for drawing right angles, which | |
3341 took the form shown in the annexed figure. This seems to | |
3342 <FIG> | |
3343 be the meaning in Theognis 805, where it is said | |
3344 that the envoy sent to consult the oracle at Delphi | |
3345 should be ‘straighter than the <G>to/pvos</G> (an instru- | |
3346 ment with a stretched string for drawing a circle), | |
3347 the <G>sta/qmh</G> (a plumb-line), and the <I>gnomon</I>’. | |
3348 It was natural that, owing to its shape, the gnomon should | |
3349 then be used to describe (3) the figure which remained of | |
3350 a square when a smaller square was cut out of it (or the figure | |
3351 which, as Aristotle says, when added to a square, preserves | |
3352 the shape and makes up a larger square). The term is used | |
3353 in a fragment of Philolaus where he says that ‘number makes | |
3354 all things knowable and mutually agreeing in the way charac- | |
3355 teristic of the <I>gnomon</I>’.<note>Boeckh, <I>Philolaos des Pythagoreers Lehren</I>, p. 141; <I>ib.</I>, p. 144; <I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 313. 15.</note> Presumably, as Boeckh says, the | |
3356 connexion between the gnomon and the square to which it is | |
3357 added was regarded as symbolical of union and agreement, | |
3358 and Philolaus used the idea to explain the knowledge of | |
3359 things, making the <I>knowing</I> embrace the <I>known</I> as the | |
3360 gnomon does the square.<note>Cf. Scholium No. 11 to Book II in Euclid, ed. Heib., vol. v, p. 225.</note> (4) In Euclid the geometrical | |
3361 meaning of the word is further extended (II. Def. 2) to cover | |
3362 <pb n=79><head>HISTORY OF THE TERM ‘GNOMON’</head> | |
3363 the figure similarly related to any parallelogram, instead of | |
3364 <FIG> | |
3365 a square; it is defined as made up of ‘any | |
3366 one whatever of the parallelograms about | |
3367 the diameter (diagonal) with the two com- | |
3368 plements’. Later still (5) Heron of Alex- | |
3369 andria defines a <I>gnomon</I> in general as that | |
3370 which, when added to anything, number or figure, makes the | |
3371 whole similar to that to which it is added.<note>Heron, Def. 58 (Heron, vol. iv, Heib., p. 225).</note> | |
3372 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>Gnomons of the polygonal numbers.</I></C> | |
3373 <p>Theon of Smyrna uses the term in this general sense with | |
3374 reference to numbers: ‘All the successive numbers which [by | |
3375 being successively added] produce triangles or squares <I>or | |
3376 polygons</I> are called gnomons.’<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 37. 11-13.</note> From the accompanying | |
3377 figures showing successive pentagonal and hexagonal numbers | |
3378 it will be seen that the outside rows or gnomons to be succes- | |
3379 <FIG> | |
3380 sively added after 1 (which is the first pentagon, hexagon, &c.) | |
3381 are in the case of the pentagon 4, 7, 10, .. or the terms of an | |
3382 arithmetical progression beginning from 1 with common differ- | |
3383 ence 3, and in the case of the hexagon 5, 9, 13 .... or the | |
3384 terms of an arithmetical progression beginning from 1 with | |
3385 common difference 4. In general the successive <I>gnomonic</I> | |
3386 numbers for any polygonal number, say of <I>n</I> sides, have | |
3387 (<I>n</I>-2) for their common difference.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 34. 13-15.</note> | |
3388 <C>(<G>e</G>) <I>Right-angled triangles with sides in rational numbers.</I></C> | |
3389 <p>To return to Pythagoras. Whether he learnt the fact from | |
3390 Egypt or not, Pythagoras was certainly aware that, while | |
3391 <MATH>3<SUP>2</SUP>+4<SUP>2</SUP>=5<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, any triangle with its sides in the ratio of the | |
3392 <pb n=80><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3393 numbers 3, 4, 5 is right angled. This fact could not but add | |
3394 strength to his conviction that all things were numbers, for it | |
3395 established a connexion between numbers and the <I>angles</I> of | |
3396 geometrical figures. It would also inevitably lead to an | |
3397 attempt to find other square numbers besides 5<SUP>2</SUP> which are | |
3398 the sum of two squares, or, in other words, to find other sets | |
3399 of three integral numbers which can be made the sides of | |
3400 right-angled triangles; and herein we have the beginning of | |
3401 the <I>indeterminate analysis</I> which reached so high a stage of | |
3402 development in Diophantus. In view of the fact that the | |
3403 sum of any number of successive terms of the series of odd | |
3404 numbers 1, 3, 5, 7 ... beginning from 1 is a square, it was | |
3405 only necessary to pick out of this series the odd numbers | |
3406 which are themselves squares; for if we take one of these, | |
3407 say 9, the addition of this square to the square which is the sum | |
3408 of all the preceding odd numbers makes the square number | |
3409 which is the sum of the odd numbers up to the number (9) that | |
3410 we have taken. But it would be natural to seek a formula | |
3411 which should enable all the three numbers of a set to be imme- | |
3412 diately written down, and such a formula is actually attributed | |
3413 to Pythagoras.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 487. 7-21.</note> This formula amounts to the statement that, | |
3414 if <I>m</I> be any odd number, | |
3415 <MATH><I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1/2)<SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>+1/2)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
3416 Pythagoras would presumably arrive at this method of forma- | |
3417 tion in the following way. Observing that the gnomon put | |
3418 round <I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP> is 2<I>n</I>+1, he would only have to make 2<I>n</I>+1 a | |
3419 square. | |
3420 <p>If we suppose that <MATH>2<I>n</I>+1=<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
3421 we obtain <MATH><I>n</I>=1/2(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)</MATH>, | |
3422 and therefore <MATH><I>n</I>+1=1/2(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>+1)</MATH>. | |
3423 <p>It follows that | |
3424 <MATH><I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1/2)<SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>+1/2)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
3425 <pb n=81><head>RATIONAL RIGHT-ANGLED TRIANGLES</head> | |
3426 <p>Another formula, devised for the same purpose, is attributed | |
3427 to Plato,<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, pp. 428. 21-429. 8.</note> namely | |
3428 <MATH>(2<I>m</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)<SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>+1)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
3429 We could obtain this formula from that of Pythagoras by | |
3430 doubling the sides of each square in the latter; but it would | |
3431 be incomplete if so obtained, for in Pythagoras's formula <I>m</I> is | |
3432 necessarily odd, whereas in Plato's it need not be. As Pytha- | |
3433 goras's formula was most probably obtained from the gnomons | |
3434 of dots, it is tempting to suppose that Plato's was similarly | |
3435 <FIG> | |
3436 evolved. Consider the square with <I>n</I> dots in its | |
3437 side in relation to the next smaller square (<I>n</I>-1)<SUP>2</SUP> | |
3438 and the next larger (<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP>. Then <I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP> exceeds | |
3439 (<I>n</I>-1)<SUP>2</SUP> by the gnomon 2<I>n</I>-1, but falls short of | |
3440 (<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP> by the gnomon 2<I>n</I>+1. Therefore the | |
3441 square (<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP> exceeds the square (<I>n</I>-1)<SUP>2</SUP> by | |
3442 the sum of the two gnomons 2<I>n</I>-1 and 2<I>n</I>+1, which | |
3443 is 4<I>n.</I> | |
3444 <p>That is, <MATH>4<I>n</I>+(<I>n</I>-1)<SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
3445 and, substituting <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP> for <I>n</I> in order to make 4<I>n</I> a square, we | |
3446 obtain the Platonic formula | |
3447 <MATH>(2<I>m</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)<SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>+1)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
3448 <p>The formulae of Pythagoras and Plato supplement each | |
3449 other. Euclid's solution (X, Lemma following Prop. 28) is | |
3450 more general, amounting to the following. | |
3451 <p>If <I>AB</I> be a straight line bisected at <I>C</I> and produced to <I>D</I>, | |
3452 then (Eucl. II. 6) | |
3453 <MATH><I>AD.DB</I>+<I>CB</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>CD</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
3454 which we may write thus: | |
3455 <MATH><I>uv</I>=<I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
3456 where <MATH><I>u</I>=<I>c</I>+<I>b</I>, <I>v</I>=<I>c</I>-<I>b</I></MATH>, | |
3457 and consequently | |
3458 <MATH><I>c</I>=1/2(<I>u</I>+<I>v</I>), <I>b</I>=1/2(<I>u</I>-<I>v</I>)</MATH>. | |
3459 <p>In order that <I>uv</I> may be a square, says Euclid, <I>u</I> and <I>v</I> | |
3460 must, if they are not actually squares, be ‘similar plane num- | |
3461 bers’, and further they must be either both odd or both even | |
3462 <pb n=82><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3463 in order that <I>b</I> (and <I>c</I> also) may be a whole number. ‘Similar | |
3464 plane’ numbers are of course numbers which are the product | |
3465 of two factors proportional in pairs, as <I>mp.np</I> and <I>mq.nq</I>, or | |
3466 <I>mnp</I><SUP>2</SUP> and <I>mnq</I><SUP>2</SUP>. Provided, then, that these numbers are both | |
3467 even or both odd, | |
3468 <MATH><I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>p</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>q</I><SUP>2</SUP>+((<I>mnp</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>mnq</I><SUP>2</SUP>)/2)<SUP>2</SUP>=((<I>mnp</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>mnq</I><SUP>2</SUP>)/2)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH> | |
3469 is the solution, which includes both the Pythagorean and the | |
3470 Platonic formulae. | |
3471 <C>(<G>z</G>) <I>Oblong numbers.</I></C> | |
3472 <p>Pythagoras, or the earliest Pythagoreans, having discovered | |
3473 that, by adding any number of successive terms (beginning | |
3474 from 1) of the series <MATH>1+2+3+...+<I>n</I>=1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)</MATH>, we obtain | |
3475 triangular numbers, and that by adding the successive odd | |
3476 numbers <MATH>1+3+5+...+(2<I>n</I>-1)=<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> we obtain squares, it | |
3477 cannot be doubted that in like manner they summed the | |
3478 series of even numbers <MATH>2+4+6+...+2<I>n</I>=<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)</MATH> and | |
3479 discovered accordingly that the sum of any number of succes- | |
3480 sive terms of the series beginning with 2 was an ‘oblong’ | |
3481 number (<G>e(teromh/khs</G>), with ‘sides’ or factors differing by 1. | |
3482 They would also see that the oblong number is double of | |
3483 a triangular number. These facts would be brought out by | |
3484 taking two dots representing 2 and then placing round them, | |
3485 gnomon-wise and successively, the even numbers 4, 6, &c., | |
3486 thus: | |
3487 <FIG> | |
3488 The successive oblong numbers are | |
3489 <MATH>2.3=6, 3.4=12, 4.5=20..., <I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)...</MATH>, | |
3490 and it is clear that no two of these numbers are similar, for | |
3491 the ratio <I>n</I>:(<I>n</I>+1) is different for all different values of <I>n.</I> | |
3492 We may have here an explanation of the Pythagorean identi- | |
3493 fication of ‘odd’ with ‘limit’ or ‘limited’ and of ‘even’ with | |
3494 <pb n=83><head>OBLONG NUMBERS</head> | |
3495 ‘unlimited’<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> A. 5, 986 a 17.</note> (cf. the Pythagorean scheme of ten pairs of | |
3496 opposites, where odd, limit and square in one set are opposed | |
3497 to even, unlimited and oblong respectively in the other).<note><I>Ib.</I> A. 5, 986 a 23-26.</note> For, | |
3498 while the adding of the successive odd numbers as gnomons | |
3499 round 1 gives only one form, the square, the addition of the | |
3500 successive even numbers to 2 gives a succession of ‘oblong’ | |
3501 numbers all dissimilar in form, that is to say, an infinity of | |
3502 forms. This seems to be indicated in the passage of Aristotle's | |
3503 <I>Physics</I> where, as an illustration of the view that the even | |
3504 is unlimited, he says that, where gnomons are put round 1, | |
3505 the resulting figures are in one case always different in | |
3506 species, while in the other they always preserve one form<note>Arist. <I>Phys.</I> iii. 4, 203 a 10-15.</note>; | |
3507 the one form is of course the square formed by adding the | |
3508 odd numbers as gnomons round 1; the words <G>kai\ *xwri/s</G> | |
3509 (‘and in the separate case’, as we may perhaps translate) | |
3510 imperfectly describe the second case, since in that case | |
3511 even numbers are put round 2, not 1, but the meaning | |
3512 seems clear.<note>Cf. Plut. (?) Stob. <I>Ecl.</I> i. pr. 10, p. 22. 16 Wachsmuth.</note> It is to be noted that the word <G>e(teromh/khs</G> | |
3513 (‘oblong’) is in Theon of Smyrna and Nicomachus limited to | |
3514 numbers which are the product of two factors differing by | |
3515 unity, while they apply the term <G>promh/khs</G> (‘prolate’, as it | |
3516 were) to numbers which are the product of factors differing | |
3517 by two or more (Theon makes <G>promh/khs</G> include <G>e(teromh/khs</G>). | |
3518 In Plato and Aristotle <G>e(teromh/khs</G> has the wider sense of any | |
3519 non-square number with two unequal factors. | |
3520 <p>It is obvious that any ‘oblong’ number <I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1) is the | |
3521 <FIG> | |
3522 sum of two equal triangular numbers. Scarcely less obvious | |
3523 is the theorem of Theon that any square number is made up | |
3524 of two triangular numbers<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 41. 3-8.</note>; in this case, as is seen from the | |
3525 <pb n=84><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3526 figure, the sides of the triangles differ by unity, and of course | |
3527 <FIG> | |
3528 <MATH>1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>-1)+1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)=<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
3529 <p>Another theorem connecting triangular num- | |
3530 bers and squares, namely that 8 times any | |
3531 triangular number +1 makes a square, may | |
3532 easily go back to the early Pythagoreans. It is | |
3533 quoted by Plutarch<note>Plutarch, <I>Plat. Quaest.</I> v. 2. 4, 1003 F.</note> and used by Diophantus,<note>Dioph. IV. 38.</note> and is equi- | |
3534 valent to the formula | |
3535 <MATH>8.1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)+1=4<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)+1=(2<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
3536 <p>It may easily have been proved by means of a figure | |
3537 <FIG> | |
3538 made up of dots in the usual way. Two | |
3539 equal triangles make up an oblong figure | |
3540 of the form <I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1), as above. Therefore | |
3541 we have to prove that four equal figures | |
3542 of this form with one more dot make up | |
3543 (2<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP>. The annexed figure representing | |
3544 7<SUP>2</SUP> shows how it can be divided into four | |
3545 ‘oblong’ figures 3.4 leaving 1 over. | |
3546 <p>In addition to Speusippus, Philippus of Opus (fourth | |
3547 century), the editor of Plato's <I>Laws</I> and author of the <I>Epi- | |
3548 nomis</I>, is said to have written a work on polygonal numbers.<note><G>*biogra/foi</G>, <I>Vitarum scriptores Graeci minores</I>, ed. Westermann, p. 446.</note> | |
3549 Hypsicles, who wrote about 170 B.C., is twice mentioned in | |
3550 Diophantus's <I>Polygonal Numbers</I> as the author of a ‘defini- | |
3551 tion’ of a polygonal number. | |
3552 <C>The theory of proportion and means.</C> | |
3553 <p>The ‘summary’ of Proclus (as to which see the beginning | |
3554 of Chapter IV) states (if Friedlein's reading is right) that | |
3555 Pythagoras discovered ‘the theory of irrationals (<G>th\n tw=n | |
3556 a)lo/gwn pragmatei/an</G>) and the construction of the cosmic | |
3557 figures’ (the five regular solids).<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 65. 19.</note> We are here concerned | |
3558 with the first part of this statement in so far as the reading | |
3559 <G>a)lo/gwn</G> (‘irrationals’) is disputed. Fabricius seems to have | |
3560 been the first to record the variant <G>a)nalo/gwn</G>, which is also | |
3561 noted by E. F. August<note>In his edition of the Greek text of Euclid (1824-9), vol. i, p. 290.</note>; Mullach adopted this reading from | |
3562 <pb n=85><head>THE THEORY OF PROPORTION AND MEANS</head> | |
3563 Fabricius. <G>a)nalo/gwn</G> is not the correct form of the word, but | |
3564 the meaning would be ‘proportions’ or ‘proportionals’, and | |
3565 the true reading may be either <G>tw=n a)nalogiw=n</G> (‘proportions’), | |
3566 or, more probably, <G>tw=n a)na\ lo/gon</G> (‘proportionals’); Diels | |
3567 reads <G>tw=n a)na\ lo/gon</G>, and it would seem that there is now | |
3568 general agreement that <G>a)lo/gwn</G> is wrong, and that the theory | |
3569 which Proclus meant to attribute to Pythagoras is the theory | |
3570 of <I>proportion</I> or <I>proportionals</I>, not of irrationals. | |
3571 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Arithmetic, geometric, and harmonic means.</I></C> | |
3572 <p>It is true that we have no positive evidence of the use by | |
3573 Pythagoras of proportions in geometry, although he must | |
3574 have been conversant with similar figures, which imply some | |
3575 theory of proportion. But he discovered the dependence of | |
3576 musical intervals on numerical ratios, and the theory of <I>means</I> | |
3577 was developed very early in his school with reference to | |
3578 the theory of music and arithmetic. We are told that in | |
3579 Pythagoras's time there were three means, the arithmetic, | |
3580 the geometric, and the subcontrary, and that the name of the | |
3581 third (‘subcontrary’) was changed by Archytas and Hippasus | |
3582 to ‘harmonic’.<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 100. 19-24.</note> A fragment of Archytas's work <I>On Music</I> | |
3583 actually defines the three; we have the <I>arithmetic</I> mean | |
3584 when, of three terms, the first exceeds the second by the | |
3585 same amount as the second exceeds the third; the <I>geometric</I> | |
3586 mean when, of the three terms, the first is to the second as | |
3587 the second is to the third; the ‘<I>subcontrary</I>, which we call | |
3588 <I>harmonic</I>’, when the three terms are such that ‘by whatever | |
3589 part of itself the first exceeds the second, the second exceeds | |
3590 the third by the same part of the third’.<note>Porph. <I>in Ptol. Harm.</I>, p. 267 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 334. 17 sq.).</note> That is, if <I>a, b, c</I> | |
3591 are in harmonic progression, and <MATH><I>a</I>=<I>b</I>+<I>a</I>/<I>n</I></MATH>, we must have | |
3592 <MATH><I>b</I>=<I>c</I>+<I>c</I>/<I>n</I></MATH>, whence in fact | |
3593 <MATH><I>a</I>/<I>c</I>=(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)</MATH>, or <MATH>1/<I>c</I>-1/<I>b</I>=1/<I>b</I>-1/<I>a</I></MATH>. | |
3594 Nicomachus too says that the name ‘harmonic mean’ was | |
3595 adopted in accordance with the view of Philolaus about the | |
3596 ‘geometrical harmony’, a name applied to the cube because | |
3597 it has 12 edges, 8 angles, and 6 faces, and 8 is the mean | |
3598 <pb n=86><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3599 between 12 and 6 according to the theory of harmonics (<G>kata\ | |
3600 th\n a(rmonikh/n</G>).<note>Nicom. ii. 26. 2.</note> | |
3601 <p>Iamblichus,<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 118. 19sq.</note> after Nicomachus,<note>Nicom. ii. 29.</note> mentions a special ‘most | |
3602 perfect proportion’ consisting of four terms and called | |
3603 ‘musical’, which, according to tradition, was discovered by | |
3604 the Babylonians and was first introduced into Greece by | |
3605 Pythagoras. It was used, he says, by many Pythagoreans, | |
3606 e.g. (among others) Aristaeus of Croton, Timaeus of Locri, | |
3607 Philolaus and Archytas of Tarentum, and finally by Plato | |
3608 in the <I>Timaeus</I>, where we are told that the double and triple | |
3609 intervals were filled up by two means, one of which exceeds | |
3610 and is exceeded by the same part of the extremes (the | |
3611 harmonic mean), and the other exceeds and is exceeded by | |
3612 the same numerical magnitude (the arithmetic mean).<note>Plato, <I>Timaeus</I>, 36 A.</note> The | |
3613 proportion is | |
3614 <MATH><I>a</I>:(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)/2=(2<I>ab</I>)/(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>):<I>b</I></MATH>, | |
3615 an example being 12:9=8:6. | |
3616 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>Seven other means distinguished.</I></C> | |
3617 <p>The theory of means was further developed in the school | |
3618 by the gradual addition of seven others to the first three, | |
3619 making ten in all. The accounts of the discovery of the | |
3620 fourth, fifth, and sixth are not quite consistent. In one place | |
3621 Iamblichus says they were added by Eudoxus<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 101. 1-5.</note>; in other | |
3622 places he says they were in use by the successors of Plato | |
3623 down to Eratosthenes, but that Archytas and Hippasus made | |
3624 a beginning with their discovery,<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 116. 1-4.</note> or that they were part of | |
3625 the Archytas and Hippasus tradition.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 113, 16-18.</note> The remaining four | |
3626 means (the seventh to the tenth) are said to have been added | |
3627 by two later Pythagoreans, Myonides and Euphranor.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 116. 4-6.</note> From | |
3628 a remark of Porphyry it would appear that one of the first | |
3629 seven means was discovered by Simus of Posidonia, but | |
3630 that the jealousy of other Pythagoreans would have robbed | |
3631 him of the credit.<note>Porphyry, <I>Vit. Pyth.</I> 3; <I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 343. 12-15 and note.</note> The ten means are described by | |
3632 <pb n=87><head>THE SEVERAL MEANS DISTINGUISHED</head> | |
3633 Nicomachus<note>Nicom. ii. 28.</note> and Pappus<note>Pappus, iii, p. 102.</note>; their accounts only differ as | |
3634 regards one of the ten. If <I>a>b>c</I>, the formulae in the third | |
3635 column of the following table show the various means. | |
3636 <table> | |
3637 <tr><td>No. in Nicom.</td><td>No. in Pappus.</td><td>Formulae.</td><td>Equivalent.</td></tr> | |
3638 <tr><td align=center>1</td><td align=center>1</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>a</I>=<I>b</I>/<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>+<I>c</I>=2<I>b</I></MATH> (arithmetic)</td></tr> | |
3639 <tr><td align=center>2</td><td align=center>2</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>b</I>[=<I>b</I>/<I>c</I>]</MATH></td><td><MATH><I>ac</I>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> (geometric)</td></tr> | |
3640 <tr><td align=center>3</td><td align=center>3</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH>1/<I>a</I>+1/<I>c</I>=2/<I>b</I></MATH> (harmonic)</td></tr> | |
3641 <tr><td align=center>4</td><td align=center>4</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>c</I>/<I>a</I></MATH></td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>)/(<I>a</I>+<I>c</I>)=<I>b</I></MATH> (subcontrary to harmonic)</td></tr> | |
3642 <tr><td align=center>5</td><td align=center>5</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>c</I>/<I>b</I></MATH></td> | |
3643 <td><MATH><BRACE><note>(subcontrary to geometric)</note><I>a</I>=<I>b</I>+<I>c</I>-<I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>b</I><I>c</I>=<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>-<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>b</I></BRACE></MATH></td></tr> | |
3644 <tr><td align=center>6</td><td align=center>6</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>b</I>/<I>a</I></MATH></td></tr> | |
3645 <tr><td align=center>7</td><td align=center>(omitted)</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>=2<I>ac</I>-<I>ab</I></MATH></td></tr> | |
3646 <tr><td align=center>8</td><td align=center>9</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)/(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>a</I>(<I>b</I>+<I>c</I>)</MATH></td></tr> | |
3647 <tr><td align=center>9</td><td align=center>10</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>b</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>c</I>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)</MATH></td></tr> | |
3648 <tr><td align=center>10</td><td align=center>7</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)/(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)=<I>b</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=<I>b</I>+<I>c</I></MATH></td></tr> | |
3649 <tr><td align=center>(omitted)</td><td align=center>8</td><td><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)/(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>b</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>=2<I>ab</I>-<I>bc</I></MATH></td></tr> | |
3650 </table> | |
3651 <p>The two lists together give <I>five</I> means in addition to the | |
3652 first six which are common to both; there would be six more | |
3653 (as Theon of Smyrna says<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 106. 15, p. 116. 3.</note>) were it not that <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>b</I></MATH> is | |
3654 illusory, since it gives <MATH><I>a</I>=<I>b</I></MATH>. Tannery has remarked that | |
3655 <pb n=88><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3656 Nos. 4, 5, 6 of the above means give equations of the second | |
3657 degree, and he concludes that the geometrical and even the | |
3658 arithmetical solution of such equations was known to the dis- | |
3659 coverer of these means, say about the time of Plato<note>Tannery, <I>Mémoires scientifiques</I>, i, pp. 92-3.</note>; Hippo- | |
3660 crates of Chios, in fact, assumed the geometrical solution of | |
3661 a mixed quadratic equation in his quadrature of lunes. | |
3662 <p>Pappus has an interesting series of propositions with | |
3663 regard to eight out of the ten means defined by him.<note>Pappus, iii, pp. 84-104.</note> He | |
3664 observes that if <G>a, b, g</G> be three terms in geometrical pro- | |
3665 gression, we can form from these terms three other terms | |
3666 <I>a, b, c</I>, being linear functions of <G>a, b, g</G> which satisfy respec- | |
3667 tively eight of the above ten relations; that is to say, he | |
3668 gives a solution of eight problems in indeterminate analysis | |
3669 of the second degree. The solutions are as follows: | |
3670 <table> | |
3671 <tr align=center><td>No. in Nicom.</td><td>No. in Pappus.</td><td>Formulae.</td><td>Solution in terms of <G>a, b, g.</G></td><td>Smallest solution.</td></tr> | |
3672 <tr><td rowspan=2>2</td><td rowspan=2>2</td><td rowspan=2><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>b</I>=<I>b</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=<G>a</G>+2<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=4</MATH></td></tr> | |
3673 <tr><td><MATH><I>b</I>=<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>b</I>=2</MATH></td></tr> | |
3674 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=1</MATH></td></tr> | |
3675 <tr><td rowspan=2>3</td><td rowspan=2>3</td><td rowspan=2><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=2<G>a</G>+3<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=6</MATH></td></tr> | |
3676 <tr><td><MATH><I>b</I>=2<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>b</I>=3</MATH></td></tr> | |
3677 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=2</MATH></td></tr> | |
3678 <tr><td rowspan=2>4</td><td rowspan=2>4</td><td rowspan=2><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>c</I>/<I>a</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=2<G>a</G>+3<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=6</MATH></td></tr> | |
3679 <tr><td><MATH><I>b</I>=2<G>a</G>+2<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>b</I>=5</MATH></td></tr> | |
3680 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=2</MATH></td></tr> | |
3681 <tr><td rowspan=2>5</td><td rowspan=2>5</td><td rowspan=2><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>c</I>/<I>b</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=<G>a</G>+3<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=5</MATH></td></tr> | |
3682 <tr><td><MATH><I>b</I>=<G>a</G>+2<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>b</I>=4</MATH></td></tr> | |
3683 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=2</MATH></td></tr> | |
3684 <tr><td rowspan=2>6</td><td rowspan=2>6</td><td rowspan=2><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>b</I>/<I>a</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=<G>a</G>+3<G>b</G>+2<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=6</MATH></td></tr> | |
3685 <tr><td><MATH><I>b</I>=<G>a</G>+2<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>b</I>=4</MATH></td></tr> | |
3686 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=<G>a</G>+<G>b</G>-<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=1</MATH></td></tr> | |
3687 </table> | |
3688 <pb n=89><head>THE SEVERAL MEANS DISTINGUISHED</head> | |
3689 <table> | |
3690 <tr align=center><td>No. in Nicom.</td><td>No. in Pappus.</td><td>Formulae.</td><td>Solution in terms of <G>a, b, g.</G></td><td>Smallest solution.</td></tr> | |
3691 <tr><td rowspan=2>---</td><td rowspan=2>8</td><td rowspan=2><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)/(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>b</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=2<G>a</G>+3<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=6</MATH></td></tr> | |
3692 <tr><td><MATH><I>b</I>=<G>a</G>+2<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>b</I>=4</MATH></td></tr> | |
3693 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=2<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=3</MATH></td></tr> | |
3694 <tr><td rowspan=2>8</td><td rowspan=2>9</td><td rowspan=2><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)/(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=<G>a</G>+2<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=4</MATH></td></tr> | |
3695 <tr><td><MATH><I>b</I>=<G>a</G>+<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>b</I>=3</MATH></td></tr> | |
3696 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=2</MATH></td></tr> | |
3697 <tr><td rowspan=2>9</td><td rowspan=2>10</td><td rowspan=2><MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>b</I>/<I>c</I></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=<G>a</G>+<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>a</I>=3</MATH></td></tr> | |
3698 <tr><td><MATH><I>b</I>=<G>b</G>+<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>b</I>=2</MATH></td></tr> | |
3699 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=<G>g</G></MATH></td><td><MATH><I>c</I>=1</MATH></td></tr> | |
3700 </table> | |
3701 <p>Pappus does not include a corresponding solution for his | |
3702 No. 1 and No. 7, and Tannery suggests as the reason for this | |
3703 that, the equations in these cases being already linear, there | |
3704 is no necessity to assume <MATH><G>ag</G>=<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, and consequently there is | |
3705 one indeterminate too many.<note>Tannery, <I>loc. cit.</I>, pp. 97-8.</note> Pappus does not so much prove | |
3706 as verify his results, by transforming the proportion <MATH><G>a</G>/<G>b</G>=<G>b</G>/<G>g</G></MATH> | |
3707 in all sorts of ways, <I>componendo, dividendo</I>, &c. | |
3708 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Plato on geometric means between two squares | |
3709 or two cubes.</I></C> | |
3710 <p>It is well known that the mathematics in Plato's <I>Timaeus</I> | |
3711 is essentially Pythagorean. It is therefore <I>a priori</I> probable | |
3712 that Plato <G>puqagori/zei</G> in the passage<note>Plato, <I>Timaeus</I>, 32 A, B.</note> where he says that | |
3713 between two <I>planes</I> one mean suffices, but to connect two | |
3714 <I>solids</I> two means are necessary. By <I>planes</I> and <I>solids</I> he | |
3715 really means square and cube numbers, and his remark is | |
3716 equivalent to stating that, if <I>p</I><SUP>2</SUP>, <I>q</I><SUP>2</SUP> are two square numbers, | |
3717 <MATH><I>p</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>pq</I>=<I>pq:q</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
3718 while, if <I>p</I><SUP>3</SUP>, <I>q</I><SUP>3</SUP> are two cube numbers, | |
3719 <MATH><I>p</I><SUP>3</SUP>:<I>p</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>q</I>=<I>p</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>q:pq</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>pq</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>q</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH>, | |
3720 the means being of course means in continued geometric pro- | |
3721 portion. Euclid proves the properties for square and cube | |
3722 <pb n=90><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3723 numbers in VIII. 11, 12, and for similar plane and solid num- | |
3724 bers in VIII. 18, 19. Nicomachus quotes the substance of | |
3725 Plato's remark as a ‘Platonic theorem’, adding in explanation | |
3726 the equivalent of Eucl. VIII. 11, 12.<note>Nicom. ii. 24. 6, 7.</note> | |
3727 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>A theorem of Archytas.</I></C> | |
3728 <p>Another interesting theorem relative to geometric means | |
3729 evidently goes back to the Pythagoreans. If we have two | |
3730 numbers in the ratio known as <G>e)pimo/rios</G>, or <I>superparticularis</I>, | |
3731 i.e. the ratio of <I>n</I>+1 to <I>n</I>, there can be no number which is | |
3732 a mean proportional between them. The theorem is Prop. 3 of | |
3733 Euclid's <I>Sectio Canonis</I>,<note><I>Musici Scriptores Graeci</I>, ed. Jan, pp. 148-66; Euclid, vol. viii, ed. | |
3734 Heiberg and Menge, p. 162.</note> and Boëtius has preserved a proof | |
3735 of it by Archytas, which is substantially identical with that of | |
3736 Euclid.<note>Boëtius, <I>De Inst. Musica</I>, iii. 11 (pp. 285-6, ed. Friedlein); see <I>Biblio- | |
3737 theca Mathematica</I>, vi<SUB>3</SUB>, 1905/6, p. 227.</note> The proof will be given later (pp. 215-16). So far as | |
3738 this chapter is concerned, the importance of the proposition lies | |
3739 in the fact that it implies the existence, at least as early | |
3740 as the date of Archytas (about 430-365 B.C.), of an <I>Elements | |
3741 of Arithmetic</I> in the form which we call Euclidean; and no | |
3742 doubt text-books of the sort existed even before Archytas, | |
3743 which probably Archytas himself and others after him im- | |
3744 proved and developed in their turn. | |
3745 <C>The ‘irrational’.</C> | |
3746 <p>We mentioned above the dictum of Proclus (if the reading | |
3747 <G>a)lo/gwn</G> is right) that Pythagoras discovered the theory, or | |
3748 study, of <I>irrationals.</I> This subject was regarded by the | |
3749 Greeks as belonging to geometry rather than arithmetic. | |
3750 The irrationals in Euclid, Book X, are straight lines or areas, | |
3751 and Proclus mentions as special topics in geometry matters | |
3752 relating (1) to <I>positions</I> (for numbers have no position), (2) to | |
3753 <I>contacts</I> (for tangency is between <I>continuous</I> things), and (3) | |
3754 to <I>irrational straight lines</I> (for where there is division <I>ad | |
3755 infinitum</I>, there also is the irrational).<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 60. 12-16.</note> I shall therefore | |
3756 postpone to Chapter V on the Pythagorean geometry the | |
3757 question of the date of the discovery of the theory of irra- | |
3758 tionals. But it is certain that the incommensurability of the | |
3759 <pb n=91><head>THE ‘IRRATIONAL’</head> | |
3760 diagonal of a square with its side, that is, the ‘irrationality’ | |
3761 of √2, was discovered in the school of Pythagoras, and it is | |
3762 more appropriate to deal with this particular case here, both | |
3763 because the traditional proof of the fact depends on the | |
3764 elementary theory of numbers, and because the Pythagoreans | |
3765 invented a method of obtaining an infinite series of arith- | |
3766 metical ratios approaching more and more closely to the value | |
3767 of √2. | |
3768 <p>The actual method by which the Pythagoreans proved the | |
3769 fact that √2 is incommensurable with 1 was doubtless that | |
3770 indicated by Aristotle, a <I>reductio ad absurdum</I> showing that, | |
3771 if the diagonal of a square is commensurable with its side, it | |
3772 will follow that the same number is both odd and even.<note>Arist. <I>Anal. pr.</I> i. 23, 41 a 26-7.</note> This | |
3773 is evidently the proof interpolated in the texts of Euclid as | |
3774 X. 117, which is in substance as follows: | |
3775 <p>Suppose <I>AC</I>, the diagonal of a square, to be commensur- | |
3776 able with <I>AB</I>, its side; let <G>a</G>:<G>b</G> be their ratio expressed in | |
3777 the smallest possible numbers. | |
3778 <p>Then <G>a</G>><G>b</G>, and therefore <G>a</G> is necessarily > 1. | |
3779 <p>Now <MATH><I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<G>a</G><SUP>2</SUP>:<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP>;</MATH> | |
3780 and, since <MATH><I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>=2<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>, <G>a</G><SUP>2</SUP>=2<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
3781 <p>Hence <G>a</G><SUP>2</SUP>, and therefore <G>a</G>, is even. | |
3782 <p>Since <G>a</G>:<G>b</G> is in its lowest terms, it follows that <G>b</G> must | |
3783 be <I>odd.</I> | |
3784 <p>Let <MATH><G>a</G>=2<G>g</G></MATH>; therefore <MATH>4<G>g</G><SUP>2</SUP>=2<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, or <MATH>2<G>g</G><SUP>2</SUP>=<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, so that <G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP>, | |
3785 and therefore <G>b</G>, is <I>even.</I> | |
3786 <p>But <G>b</G> was also <I>odd</I>: which is impossible. | |
3787 <p>Therefore the diagonal <I>AC</I> cannot be commensurable with | |
3788 the side <I>AB.</I> | |
3789 <C>Algebraic equations.</C> | |
3790 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>‘Side-’ and ‘diameter-’ numbers, giving successive | |
3791 approximations to</I> √2.</C> | |
3792 <p>The Pythagorean method of finding any number of succes- | |
3793 sive approximations to the value of √2 amounts to finding | |
3794 all the integral solutions of the indeterminate equations | |
3795 <MATH>2<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=±1</MATH>, | |
3796 the solutions being successive pairs of what were called <I>side-</I> | |
3797 <pb n=92><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3798 and <I>diameter-</I> (diagonal-) <I>numbers</I> respectively. The law of | |
3799 formation of these numbers is explained by Theon of Smyrna, | |
3800 and is as follows.<note>Theon of Smyrna, pp. 43, 44.</note> The unit, being the beginning of all things, | |
3801 must be potentially both a side and a diameter. Consequently | |
3802 we begin with two units, the one being the first <I>side</I>, which we | |
3803 will call <I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>, the other being the first <I>diameter</I>, which we will | |
3804 call <I>d</I><SUB>1</SUB>. | |
3805 <p>The second side and diameter (<I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>, <I>d</I><SUB>2</SUB>) are formed from the | |
3806 first, the third side and diameter (<I>a</I><SUB>3</SUB>, <I>d</I><SUB>3</SUB>) from the second, and | |
3807 so on, as follows: | |
3808 <MATH><I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>=<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>+<I>d</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>d</I><SUB>2</SUB>=2<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>+<I>d</I><SUB>1</SUB>, | |
3809 <I>a</I><SUB>3</SUB>=<I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>+<I>d</I><SUB>2</SUB>, <I>d</I><SUB>3</SUB>=2<I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>+<I>d</I><SUB>2</SUB>, | |
3810 . . . . . . . . . . | |
3811 <I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>+1</SUB>=<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I>+<I>d<SUB>n</SUB></I>, <I>d</I><SUB><I>n</I>+1</SUB>=2<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I>+<I>d<SUB>n</SUB></I></MATH>. | |
3812 <p>Since <MATH><I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>=<I>d</I><SUB>1</SUB>=1</MATH>, it follows that | |
3813 <MATH><I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>=1+1=2, <I>d</I><SUB>2</SUB>=2.1+1=3, | |
3814 <I>a</I><SUB>3</SUB>=2+3=5, <I>d</I><SUB>3</SUB>=2.2+3=7, | |
3815 <I>a</I><SUB>4</SUB>=5+7=12, <I>d</I><SUB>4</SUB>=2.5+7=17</MATH>, | |
3816 and so on. | |
3817 <p>Theon states, with reference to these numbers, the general | |
3818 proposition that | |
3819 <MATH><I>d<SUB>n</SUB></I><SUP>2</SUP>=2<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I><SUP>2</SUP>±1</MATH>, | |
3820 and he observes (1) that the signs alternate as successive <I>d</I>'s | |
3821 and <I>a</I>'s are taken, <I>d</I><SUB>1</SUB><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB><SUP>2</SUP> being equal to -1, <I>d</I><SUB>2</SUB><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB><SUP>2</SUP> | |
3822 equal to +1, <I>d</I><SUB>3</SUB><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>a</I><SUB>3</SUB><SUP>2</SUP> equal to -1, and so on, while (2) the | |
3823 sum of the squares of <I>all</I> the <I>d</I>'s will be double of the squares | |
3824 of <I>all</I> the <I>a</I>'s. [If the number of successive terms in each | |
3825 series is finite, it is of course necessary that the number should | |
3826 be even.] | |
3827 <p>The properties stated depend on the truth of the following | |
3828 identity | |
3829 <MATH>(2<I>x</I>+<I>y</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>-2(<I>x</I>+<I>y</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>=2<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>;</MATH> | |
3830 for, if <I>x, y</I> be numbers which satisfy one of the two equations | |
3831 <MATH>2<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=±1</MATH>, | |
3832 the formula (if true) gives us two higher numbers, <I>x</I>+<I>y</I> and | |
3833 2<I>x</I>+<I>y</I>, which satisfy the other of the two equations. | |
3834 <p>Not only is the identity true, but we know from Proclus | |
3835 <pb n=93><head>‘SIDE-’ AND ‘DIAMETER-’ NUMBERS</head> | |
3836 how it was proved.<note>Proclus, <I>Comm. on Rep. of Plato</I>, ed. Kroll, vol. ii, 1901, cc. 23 and | |
3837 27, pp. 24, 25, and 27-9.</note> Observing that ‘it is proved by him | |
3838 (Euclid) graphically (<G>grammikw=s</G>) in the Second Book of the | |
3839 <FIG> | |
3840 Elements’, Proclus adds the enunciation of Eucl. II. 10. | |
3841 This proposition proves that, if <I>AB</I> is bisected at <I>C</I> and pro- | |
3842 duced to <I>D</I>, then | |
3843 <MATH><I>AD</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>DB</I><SUP>2</SUP>=2<I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>+2<I>CD</I><SUP>2</SUP>;</MATH> | |
3844 and, if <MATH><I>AC</I>=<I>CB</I>=<I>x</I></MATH> and <MATH><I>BD</I>=<I>y</I></MATH>, this gives | |
3845 <MATH>(2<I>x</I>+<I>y</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=2<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+2(<I>x</I>+<I>y</I>)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
3846 or <MATH>(2<I>x</I>+<I>y</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>-2(<I>x</I>+<I>y</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>=2<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
3847 which is the formula required. | |
3848 <p>We can of course prove the property of consecutive side- | |
3849 and diameter- numbers algebraically thus: | |
3850 <MATH><I>d<SUB>n</SUB></I><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I><SUP>2</SUP>=(2<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>+<I>d</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>)<SUP>2</SUP>-2(<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>+<I>d</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>)<SUP>2</SUP> | |
3851 =2<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>d</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB><SUP>2</SUP> | |
3852 =-(<I>d</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB><SUP>2</SUP>) | |
3853 =+(<I>d</I><SUB><I>n</I>-2</SUB><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-2</SUB><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>, in like manner; | |
3854 and so on. | |
3855 <p>In the famous passage of the <I>Republic</I> (546 C) dealing with | |
3856 the geometrical number Plato distinguishes between the | |
3857 ‘irrational diameter of 5’, i.e. the diagonal of a square having | |
3858 5 for its side, or √(50), and what he calls the ‘rational | |
3859 diameter’ of 5. The square of the ‘rational diameter’ is less | |
3860 by 1 than the square of the ‘irrational diameter’, and is there- | |
3861 fore 49, so that the ‘rational diameter’ is 7; that is, Plato | |
3862 refers to the fact that <MATH>2.5<SUP>2</SUP>-7<SUP>2</SUP>=1</MATH>, and he has in mind the | |
3863 particular pair of side- and diameter- numbers, 5 and 7, which | |
3864 must therefore have been known before his time. As the proof | |
3865 of the property of these numbers in general is found, as Proclus | |
3866 says, in the geometrical theorem of Eucl. II. 10, it is a fair | |
3867 inference that that theorem is Pythagorean, and was prob- | |
3868 ably invented for the special purpose. | |
3869 <pb n=94><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3870 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The</I> <G>e)pa/nqhma</G> (‘<I>bloom</I>’) <I>of Thymaridas.</I></C> | |
3871 <p>Thymaridas of Paros, an ancient Pythagorean already | |
3872 mentioned (p. 69), was the author of a rule for solving a | |
3873 certain set of <I>n</I> simultaneous simple equations connecting <I>n</I> | |
3874 unknown quantities. The rule was evidently well known, for | |
3875 it was called by the special name of <G>e)pa/nqhm(a</G>, the ‘flower’ or | |
3876 ‘bloom’ of Thymaridas.<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 62. 18 sq.</note> (The term <G>e)pa/nqhma</G> is not, how- | |
3877 ever, confined to the particular proposition now in question; | |
3878 Iamblichus speaks of <G>e)panqh/mata</G> of the <I>Introductio arith- | |
3879 metica</I>, ‘arithmetical <G>e)panqh/mata</G>’ and <G>e)panqh/mata</G> of par- | |
3880 ticular numbers.) The rule is stated in general terms and no | |
3881 symbols are used, but the content is pure algebra. The known | |
3882 or determined quantities (<G>w(risme/non</G>) are distinguished from | |
3883 the undetermined or unknown (<G>a)o/riston</G>), the term for the | |
3884 latter being the very word used by Diophantus in the expres- | |
3885 sion <G>plh=qos mona/dwn a)o/riston</G>, ‘an undefined or undetermined | |
3886 number of units’, by which he describes his <G>a)riqmo/s</G> or un- | |
3887 known quantity (=<I>x</I>). The rule is very obscurely worded, | |
3888 but it states in effect that, if we have the following <I>n</I> equa- | |
3889 tions connecting <I>n</I> unknown quantities <I>x</I>, <I>x</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>x</I><SUB>2</SUB>...<I>x</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>, | |
3890 namely | |
3891 <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>x</I><SUB>1</SUB>+<I>x</I><SUB>2</SUB>+...+<I>x</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>=<I>s</I>, | |
3892 <I>x</I>+<I>x</I><SUB>1</SUB>=<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>, | |
3893 <I>x</I>+<I>x</I><SUB>2</SUB>=<I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB> | |
3894 . . . . | |
3895 <I>x</I>+<I>x</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>=<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB></MATH>, | |
3896 the solution is given by | |
3897 <MATH><I>x</I>=((<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>+<I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>+...+<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>)-<I>s</I>)/(<I>n</I>-2)</MATH>. | |
3898 <p>Iamblichus, our informant on this subject, goes on to show | |
3899 that other types of equations can be reduced to this, so that | |
3900 the rule does not ‘leave us in the lurch’ in those cases either.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 63. 16.</note> | |
3901 He gives as an instance the indeterminate problem represented | |
3902 by the following three linear equations between four unknown | |
3903 quantities: | |
3904 <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>=<I>a</I>(<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>), | |
3905 <I>x</I>+<I>z</I>=<I>b</I>(<I>u</I>+<I>y</I>), | |
3906 <I>x</I>+<I>u</I>=<I>c</I>(<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>)</MATH>. | |
3907 <pb n=95><head>THE <G>*)e*p*a*n*q*h*m*a</G> (‘BLOOM’) OF THYMARIDAS</head> | |
3908 <p>From these equations we obtain | |
3909 <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>=(<I>a</I>+1)(<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>)=(<I>b</I>+1)(<I>u</I>+<I>y</I>)=(<I>c</I>+1)(<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>)</MATH>. | |
3910 <p>If now <I>x, y, z, u</I> are all to be integers, <I>x</I>+<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>+<I>u</I> must | |
3911 contain <MATH><I>a</I>+1, <I>b</I>+1, <I>c</I>+1</MATH> as factors. If <I>L</I> be the least common | |
3912 multiple of <MATH><I>a</I>+1, <I>b</I>+1, <I>c</I>+1</MATH>, we can put <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>=<I>L</I></MATH>, and | |
3913 we obtain from the above equations in pairs | |
3914 <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>=(<I>a</I>/(<I>a</I>+1))<I>L</I>, | |
3915 <I>x</I>+<I>z</I>=(<I>b</I>/(<I>b</I>+1))<I>L</I>, | |
3916 <I>x</I>+<I>u</I>=(<I>c</I>/(<I>c</I>+1))<I>L</I></MATH>, | |
3917 while <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>=<I>L</I></MATH>. | |
3918 <p>These equations are of the type to which Thymaridas's rule | |
3919 applies, and, since the number of unknown quantities (and | |
3920 equations) is 4, <I>n</I>-2 is in this case 2, and | |
3921 <MATH><I>x</I>=(<I>L</I>(<I>a</I>/(<I>a</I>+1)+<I>b</I>/(<I>b</I>+1)+<I>c</I>/(<I>c</I>+1))-<I>L</I>)/2</MATH> | |
3922 <p>The numerator is integral, but it may be an odd number, in | |
3923 which case, in order that <I>x</I> may be integral, we must take 2<I>L</I> | |
3924 instead of <I>L</I> as the value of <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>+<I>u</I></MATH>. | |
3925 <p>Iamblichus has the particular case where <I>a</I>=2, <I>b</I>=3, <I>c</I>=4. | |
3926 <I>L</I> is thus 3.4.5=60, and the numerator of the expression for | |
3927 <I>x</I> becomes 133-60, or 73, an odd number; he has therefore | |
3928 to put 2<I>L</I> or 120 in place of <I>L</I>, and so obtains <MATH><I>x</I>=73, <I>y</I>=7, | |
3929 <I>z</I>=17, <I>u</I>=23</MATH>. | |
3930 <p>Iamblichus goes on to apply the method to the equations | |
3931 <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>=3/2(<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>), | |
3932 <I>x</I>+<I>z</I>=4/3(<I>u</I>+<I>y</I>), | |
3933 <I>x</I>+<I>u</I>=5/4(<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>)</MATH>, | |
3934 <pb n=96><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3935 which give | |
3936 <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>=5/2(<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>=7/3(<I>u</I>+<I>y</I>)=9/4(<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>)</MATH>. | |
3937 <p>Therefore | |
3938 <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>=5/3(<I>x</I>+<I>y</I>)=7/4(<I>x</I>+<I>z</I>)=9/5(<I>x</I>+<I>u</I>)</MATH>. | |
3939 <p>In this case we take <I>L</I>, the least common multiple of 5, 7, 9, | |
3940 or 315, and put | |
3941 <MATH><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>+<I>z</I>+<I>u</I>=<I>L</I>=315, | |
3942 <I>x</I>+<I>y</I>=3/5<I>L</I>=189, | |
3943 <I>x</I>+<I>z</I>=4/7<I>L</I>=180, | |
3944 <I>x</I>+<I>u</I>=5/9<I>L</I>=175</MATH>, | |
3945 whence <MATH><I>x</I>=(544-315)/2=229/2</MATH>. | |
3946 <p>In order that <I>x</I> may be integral, we have to take 2<I>L</I>, or 630, | |
3947 instead of <I>L</I>, or 315, and the solution is <MATH><I>x</I>=229, <I>y</I>=149, | |
3948 <I>z</I>=131, <I>u</I>=121</MATH>. | |
3949 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Area of rectangles in relation to perimeter</I>.</C> | |
3950 <p>Sluse,<note><I>Œuvres complètes de C. Huygens</I>, pp. 64, 260.</note> in letters to Huygens dated Oct. 4, 1657, and Oct. 25, | |
3951 1658, alludes to a property of the numbers 16 and 18 of | |
3952 which he had read somewhere in Plutarch that it was known | |
3953 to the Pythagoreans, namely that each of these numbers | |
3954 represents the perimeter as well as the area of a rectangle; | |
3955 for 4.4=2.4+2.4 and 3.6=2.3+2.6. I have not found the | |
3956 passage of Plutarch, but the property of 16 is mentioned in the | |
3957 <I>Theologumena Arithmetices</I>, where it is said that 16 is the only | |
3958 square the area of which is equal to its perimeter, the peri- | |
3959 meter of smaller squares being greater, and that of all larger | |
3960 squares being less, than the area.<note><I>Theol. Ar.</I>, pp. 10, 23 (Ast).</note> We do not know whether | |
3961 the Pythagoreans proved that 16 and 18 were the only num- | |
3962 bers having the property in question; but it is likely enough | |
3963 that they did, for the proof amounts to finding the integral | |
3964 <pb n=97><head>TREATISES ON ARITHMETIC</head> | |
3965 solutions of <MATH><I>xy</I>=2(<I>x</I>+<I>y</I>)</MATH>. This is easy, for the equation is | |
3966 equivalent to <MATH>(<I>x</I>-2)(<I>y</I>-2)=4</MATH>, and we have only to equate | |
3967 <I>x</I>-2 and <I>y</I>-2 to the respective factors of 4. Since 4 is only | |
3968 divisible into integral factors in two ways, as 2.2 or as 1.4, | |
3969 we get, as the only possible solutions for <I>x, y</I>, (4, 4) or (3, 6). | |
3970 <C>Systematic treatises on arithmetic (theory of | |
3971 numbers).</C> | |
3972 <p>It will be convenient to include in this chapter some | |
3973 account of the arithmetic of the later Pythagoreans, begin- | |
3974 ning with NICOMACHUS. If any systematic treatises on | |
3975 arithmetic were ever written between Euclid (Books VII-IX) | |
3976 and Nicomachus, none have survived. Nicomachus, of | |
3977 Gerasa, probably the Gerasa in Judaea east of the river | |
3978 Jordan, flourished about 100 A.D., for, on the one hand, in | |
3979 a work of his entitled the <I>Enchiridion Harmonices</I> there is | |
3980 an allusion to Thrasyllus, who arranged the Platonic dialogues, | |
3981 wrote on music, and was the astrologer-friend of Tiberius; on | |
3982 the other hand, the <I>Introductio Arithmetica</I> of Nicomachus | |
3983 was translated into Latin by Apuleius of Madaura under the | |
3984 Antonines. Besides the <G>*)ariqmhtikh\ ei)sagwgh/</G>, Nicomachus | |
3985 is said to have written another treatise on the theology or the | |
3986 mystic properties of numbers, called <G>*qeologou/mena a)riqmh- | |
3987 tikh=s</G>, in two Books. The curious farrago which has come | |
3988 down to us under that title and which was edited by Ast<note><I>Theologumena arithmeticae. Accedit Nicomachi Geraseni Institutio | |
3989 arithmetica</I>, ed. Ast, Leipzig, 1817.</note> is, | |
3990 however, certainly not by Nicomachus; for among the authors | |
3991 from whom it gives extracts is Anatolius, Bishop of Laodicaea | |
3992 (A.D. 270); but it contains quotations from Nicomachus which | |
3993 appear to come from the genuine work. It is possible that | |
3994 Nicomachus also wrote an <I>Introduction to Geometry</I>, since in | |
3995 one place he says, with regard to certain solid numbers, that | |
3996 they have been specially treated ‘in the geometrical intro- | |
3997 duction, being more appropriate to the theory of magnitude’<note>Nicom. <I>Arithm</I>. ii. 6. 1.</note>; | |
3998 but this geometrical introduction may not necessarily have | |
3999 been a work of his own. | |
4000 <p>It is a very far cry from Euclid to Nicomachus. In the | |
4001 <pb n=98><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4002 <I>Introductio arithmetica</I> we find the form of exposition | |
4003 entirely changed. Numbers are represented in Euclid by | |
4004 straight lines with letters attached, a system which has the | |
4005 advantage that, as in algebraical notation, we can work with | |
4006 numbers in general without the necessity of giving them | |
4007 specific values; in Nicomachus numbers are no longer de- | |
4008 noted by straight lines, so that, when different undetermined | |
4009 numbers have to be distinguished, this has to be done by | |
4010 circumlocution, which makes the propositions cumbrous and | |
4011 hard to follow, and it is necessary, after each proposition | |
4012 has been stated, to illustrate it by examples in concrete | |
4013 numbers. Further, there are no longer any proofs in the | |
4014 proper sense of the word; when a general proposition has been | |
4015 enunciated, Nicomachus regards it as sufficient to show that | |
4016 it is true in particular instances; sometimes we are left to | |
4017 infer the general proposition by induction from particular | |
4018 cases which are alone given. Occasionally the author makes | |
4019 a quite absurd remark through failure to distinguish between | |
4020 the general and the particular case, as when, after he has | |
4021 defined the mean which is ‘subcontrary to the harmonic’ as | |
4022 being determined by the relation <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>c</I>/<I>a</I></MATH>, where <MATH><I>a</I>><I>b</I>><I>c</I></MATH>, | |
4023 and has given 6, 5, 3 as an illustration, he goes on to observe | |
4024 that it is a property peculiar to this mean that the product of | |
4025 the greatest and middle terms is double of the product of the | |
4026 middle and least,<note>Nicom. ii. 28. 3.</note> simply because this happens to be true in | |
4027 the particular case! Probably Nicomachus, who was not | |
4028 really a mathematician, intended his <I>Introduction</I> to be, not | |
4029 a scientific treatise, but a popular treatment of the subject | |
4030 calculated to awaken in the beginner an interest in the theory | |
4031 of numbers by making him acquainted with the most note- | |
4032 worthy results obtained up to date; for proofs of most of his | |
4033 propositions he could refer to Euclid and doubtless to other | |
4034 treatises now lost. The style of the book confirms this hypo- | |
4035 thesis; it is rhetorical and highly coloured; the properties of | |
4036 numbers are made to appear marvellous and even miraculous; | |
4037 the most obvious relations between them are stated in turgid | |
4038 language very tiresome to read. It was the mystic rather | |
4039 than the mathematical side of the theory of numbers that | |
4040 <pb n=99><head>NICOMACHUS</head> | |
4041 interested Nicomachus. If the verbiage is eliminated, the | |
4042 mathematical content can be stated in quite a small com- | |
4043 pass. Little or nothing in the book is original, and, except | |
4044 for certain definitions and refinements of classification, the | |
4045 essence of it evidently goes back to the early Pythagoreans. | |
4046 Its success is difficult to explain except on the hypothesis that | |
4047 it was at first read by philosophers rather than mathemati- | |
4048 cians (Pappus evidently despised it), and afterwards became | |
4049 generally popular at a time when there were no mathemati- | |
4050 cians left, but only philosophers who incidentally took an | |
4051 interest in mathematics. But a success it undoubtedly was; | |
4052 this is proved by the number of versions or commentaries | |
4053 which appeared in ancient times. Besides the Latin transla- | |
4054 tion by Apuleius of Madaura (born about A.D. 125), of which | |
4055 no trace remains, there was the version of Boëtius (born about | |
4056 480, died 524 A.D.); and the commentators include Iamblichus | |
4057 (fourth century), Heronas,<note><I>v.</I> Eutoc. <I>in Archim.</I> (ed. Heib. iii, p. 120. 22).</note> Asclepius of Tralles (sixth century), | |
4058 Joannes Philoponus, Proclus.<note><I>v.</I> Suidas.</note> The commentary of Iamblichus | |
4059 has been published,<note>The latest edition is Pistelli's (Teubner, 1894).</note> as also that of Philoponus,<note>Ed. Hoche, Heft 1, Leipzig, 1864, Heft 2, Berlin, 1867.</note> while that of | |
4060 Asclepius is said to be extant in MSS. When (the pseudo-) | |
4061 Lucian in his <I>Philopatris</I> (c. 12) makes Critias say to Triephon | |
4062 ‘you calculate like Nicomachus’, we have an indication that | |
4063 the book was well known, although the remark may be less a | |
4064 compliment than a laugh at Pythagorean subtleties.<note>Triephon tells Critias to swear by the Trinity (‘One (proceeding) from | |
4065 Three and Three from One’), and Critias replies, ‘You would have me | |
4066 learn to calculate, for your oath is mere arithmetic and you calculate | |
4067 like Nicomachus of Gerasa. I do not know what you mean by your | |
4068 “One-Three and Three-One”; I suppose you don't mean the <G>tetraktu/s</G> | |
4069 of Pythagoras or the <G>o)gdoa/s</G> or the <G>triaka/s</G>?’</note> | |
4070 <p>Book I of the <I>Introductio</I>, after a philosophical prelude | |
4071 (cc. 1-6), consists principally of definitions and laws of forma- | |
4072 tion. Numbers, odd and even, are first dealt with (c. 7); then | |
4073 comes the subdivision of even into three kinds (1) evenly-even, | |
4074 of the form 2<SUP><I>n</I></SUP>, (2) even-odd, of the form 2(2<I>n</I>+1), and (3) | |
4075 odd-even, of the form 2<SUP><I>m</I>+1</SUP>(2<I>n</I>+1), the last-named occupying | |
4076 a sort of intermediate position in that it partakes of the | |
4077 character of both the others. The odd is next divided into | |
4078 three kinds: (1) ‘prime and incomposite’, (2) ‘secondary and | |
4079 <pb n=100><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4080 composite’, a product of prime factors (excluding 2, which is | |
4081 even and not regarded as prime), and (3) ‘that which is in itself | |
4082 secondary and composite but in relation to another is prime and | |
4083 incomposite’, e.g. 9 in relation to 25, which again is a sort of | |
4084 intermediate class between the two others (cc. 11-13); the | |
4085 defects of this classification have already been noted (pp. 73-4). | |
4086 In c. 13 we have these different classes of odd numbers ex- | |
4087 hibited in a description of Eratosthenes's ‘sieve’ (<G>ko/skinon</G>), an | |
4088 appropriately named device for finding prime numbers. The | |
4089 method is this. We set out the series of odd numbers begin- | |
4090 ning from 3. | |
4091 3, 5, 7, 9, 11, 13, 15, 17, 19, 21, 23, 25, 27, 29, 31, ...... | |
4092 <p>Now 3 is a prime number, but multiples of 3 are not; these | |
4093 multiples, 9, 15 ... are got by passing over two numbers at | |
4094 a time beginning from 3; we therefore strike out these num- | |
4095 bers as not being prime. Similarly 5 is a prime number, but | |
4096 by passing over four numbers at a time, beginning from 5, we | |
4097 get multiples of 5, namely 15, 25 ...; we accordingly strike | |
4098 out all these multiples of 5. In general, if <I>n</I> be a prime num- | |
4099 ber, its multiples appearing in the series are found by passing | |
4100 over <I>n</I>-1 terms at a time, beginning from <I>n</I>; and we can | |
4101 strike out all these multiples. When we have gone far enough | |
4102 with this process, the numbers which are still left will be | |
4103 primes. Clearly, however, in order to make sure that the | |
4104 odd number 2<I>n</I>+1 in the series is prime, we should have to | |
4105 try all the prime divisors between 3 and √(2<I>n</I>+1); it is | |
4106 obvious, therefore, that this primitive empirical method would | |
4107 be hopeless as a practical means of obtaining prime numbers | |
4108 of any considerable size. | |
4109 <p>The same c. 13 contains the rule for finding whether two | |
4110 given numbers are prime to one another; it is the method of | |
4111 Eucl. VII. 1, equivalent to our rule for finding the greatest | |
4112 common measure, but Nicomachus expresses the whole thing | |
4113 in words, making no use of any straight lines or symbols to | |
4114 represent the numbers. If there is a common measure greater | |
4115 than unity, the process gives it; if there is none, i.e. if 1 is | |
4116 left as the last remainder, the numbers are prime to one | |
4117 another. | |
4118 <p>The next chapters (cc. 14-16) are on <I>over-perfect</I> (<G>u(pertelh/s</G>), | |
4119 <pb n=101><head>NICOMACHUS</head> | |
4120 <I>deficient</I> (<G>e)lliph/s</G>), and <I>perfect</I> (<G>te/leios</G>) numbers respectively. | |
4121 The definitions, the law of formation of perfect numbers, | |
4122 and Nicomachus's observations thereon have been given above | |
4123 (p. 74). | |
4124 <p>Next comes (cc. 17-23) the elaborate classification of | |
4125 numerical ratios greater than unity, with their counterparts | |
4126 which are less than unity. There are five categories of each, | |
4127 and under each category there is (<I>a</I>) the general name, (<I>b</I>) the | |
4128 particular names corresponding to the particular numbers | |
4129 taken. | |
4130 <p>The enumeration is tedious, but, for purposes of reference, | |
4131 is given in the following table:— | |
4132 <table width=100%> | |
4133 <tr><th colspan=2 width=60%>RATIOS GREATER THAN UNITY</th><th colspan=2 width=40%>RATIOS LESS THAN UNITY</th></tr> | |
4134 <tr><td width=20%>1. (a)</td><td width=30%>General</td><td width=20%>1. (a)</td><td width=30%>General</td></tr> | |
4135 <tr><td></td><td><G>pollapla/sios</G>, multiple</td><td></td><td><G>u(popollapla/sios</G>, submultiple</td></tr> | |
4136 <tr><td></td><td>(multiplex)</td><td></td><td>(submultiplex)</td></tr> | |
4137 <tr><td> (b)</td><td>Particular</td><td> (b)</td><td>Particular</td></tr> | |
4138 <tr><td></td><td><G>dipla/sios</G>, double</td><td></td><td><G>u(podipla/sios</G>, one half</td></tr> | |
4139 <tr><td></td><td>(duplus)</td><td></td><td>(subduplus)</td></tr> | |
4140 <tr><td></td><td><G>tripla/sios</G>, triple</td><td></td><td><G>u(potripla/sios</G>, one third</td></tr> | |
4141 <tr><td></td><td>(triplus)</td><td></td><td>(subtriplus)</td></tr> | |
4142 <tr><td></td><td> &c.</td><td></td><td> &c.</td></tr> | |
4143 <tr><td>2. (a)</td><td>General</td><td>2. (a)</td><td>General</td></tr> | |
4144 <tr><td></td><td><BRACE><LABLE>a number which is of the form 1+1/<I>n</I> or (<I>n</I>+1)/<I>n</I>, where <I>n</I> is any integer.</LABLE><G>e)pimo/rios</G> (superparticularis)</BRACE></td><td></td><td><BRACE><LABLE>the fraction <I>n</I>/(<I>n</I>+1), | |
4145 where <I>n</I> is any integer.</LABLE><G>u(pepimo/rios</G> (subsuperparticularis)</BRACE></td></tr> | |
4146 <tr><td> (b)</td><td>Particular</td><td> (b)</td><td>Particular</td></tr> | |
4147 <tr><td></td><td>According to the value of</td><td></td><td><G>u(fhmio/lios</G> =2/3</td></tr> | |
4148 <tr><td></td><td align=center><I>n</I>, we have the names</td><td></td><td>(subsesquialter)</td></tr> | |
4149 <tr><td></td><td><G>h(mio/lios</G> =1 1/2</td><td></td><td><G>u(pepi/tritos</G> =3/4</td></tr> | |
4150 <tr><td></td><td>(sesquialter)</td><td></td><td>(subsesquitertius)</td></tr> | |
4151 <tr><td></td><td><G>e)pi/tritos</G>) =1 1/3</td><td></td><td><G>u(pepite/tartos</G> =4/5</td></tr> | |
4152 <tr><td></td><td>(sesquitertius)</td><td></td><td>(subsesquiquartus)</td></tr> | |
4153 <tr><td></td><td><G>e)pite/tartos</G> =1 1/4</td><td></td><td> &c.</td></tr> | |
4154 <tr><td></td><td>(sesquiquartus)</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
4155 <tr><td></td><td> &c.</td><td></td><td></td></tr> | |
4156 </table> | |
4157 <pb n=102><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4158 <table> | |
4159 <tr><th colspan=2>RATIOS GREATER THAN UNITY </th><th colspan=2>RATIOS LESS THAN UNITY</th></tr> | |
4160 <tr><td>3. (a) General</td><td>3. (a) General</td></tr> | |
4161 <tr><td align=right><BRACE><LABLE>which exceeds 1 by twice, thrice, or more times a submultiple, and which therefore may be represented by 1+<I>m</I>/(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>) or (2<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)/(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>).</LABLE><G>e)pimerh/s</G> | |
4162 (superpartiens)</BRACE></td><td align=right><BRACE><LABLE>which is of the form (<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)/(2<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>).</LABLE><G>u(pepimerh/s</G> (subsuperpartiens)</BRACE></td></tr> | |
4163 <tr><td> (b) Particular</td><td></td></tr> | |
4164 <tr><td>The formation of the names for the series of particular <I>superpartientes</I> follows three different plans.</td><td></td></tr> | |
4165 <tr><td>Thus, of numbers of the form 1+<I>m</I>/(<I>m</I>+1),</td><td></td></tr> | |
4166 <tr><td align=center><MATH><BRACE><note>1 2/3</note><G>e)pidimerh/s</G> (superbipartiens) or <G>e)pidi/tritos</G> (superbitertius) or <G>disepi/tritos</G></BRACE></MATH></td><td>The corresponding names are not specified in Nicomachus.</td></tr> | |
4167 <tr><td align=center><MATH><BRACE><note>1 3/4</note><G>e)pitrimerh/s</G> (supertripartiens) or <G>e)pitrite/tartos</G> (supertriquartus) or <G>trisepite/tartos</G></BRACE></MATH></td><td></td></tr> | |
4168 <tr><td align=center><MATH><BRACE><note>1 4/5 is</note><G>e)pitetramerh/s</G> (superquadripartiens) or <G>e)pitetra/pemptos</G> (superquadriquintus) or <G>tetrakisepi/pemptos</G></BRACE></MATH></td><td></td></tr> | |
4169 <tr><td> &c.</td><td></td></tr> | |
4170 <tr><td>As regards the first name in each case we note that, with <G>e)pidimerh/s</G> we must understand <G>tri/twn</G>; with <G>e)pitrimerh/s</G>, <G>teta/rtwn</G>, and so on.</td><td></td></tr> | |
4171 </table> | |
4172 <pb n=103><head>NICOMACHUS</head> | |
4173 <table width=100%> | |
4174 <tr><th width=30%>RATIOS GREATER THAN UNITY</th><th width=70%>RATIOS LESS THAN UNITY</th></tr> | |
4175 <tr><td>Where the more general form 1+<I>m</I>/(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>), instead of 1+<I>m</I>/(<I>m</I>+1), has to be expressed, Nicomachus uses terms following the <I>third</I> plan of formation above, e.g.</td><td></td></tr> | |
4176 <tr><td align=center>1 3/5=<G>trisepi/pemptos</G></td><td></td></tr> | |
4177 <tr><td align=center>1 4/7=<G>tetrakisefe/bdomos</G></td><td></td></tr> | |
4178 <tr><td align=center>1 5/9=<G>pentakisepe/natos</G></td><td></td></tr> | |
4179 <tr><td>and so on, although he might have used the second and called these ratios <G>e)pitri/pemptos</G>, &c.</td><td></td></tr> | |
4180 <tr><td width=30%>4. (a) General</td><td width=70% align=center>4. (a) General</td></tr> | |
4181 <tr><td> <G>pollaplasiepimo/rios</G></td><td align=center> <G>u(popollaplasiepimo/rios</G></td></tr> | |
4182 <tr><td> (multiplex superparticularis)</td><td align=center> (submultiplex superparticularis)</td></tr> | |
4183 <tr><td>This contains a certain <I>multiple</I> plus a certain submultiple (instead of 1 plus a submultiple) and is therefore of the form <I>m</I>+1/<I>n</I> (instead of the 1+1/<I>n</I> of the <G>e)pimo/rios</G>) or | |
4184 (<I>mn</I>+1)/<I>n</I>.</td><td align=center>of the form <I>n</I>/(<I>mn</I>+1).</td></tr> | |
4185 <tr><td> (b) Particular</td><td></td></tr> | |
4186 <tr><td> 2 1/2=<G>diplasiefh/misus</G></td><td align=center> The corresponding particular</td></tr> | |
4187 <tr><td align=right>(duplex sesquialter)</td><td align=center>names do not seem to occur in</td></tr> | |
4188 <tr><td> 2 1/3=<G>diplasiepi/tritos</G></td><td align=center>Nicomachus, but Boëtius has</td></tr> | |
4189 <tr><td align=right>(duplex sesquitertius) </td><td align=center>them, e.g. subduplex sesquialter,</td></tr> | |
4190 <tr><td> 3 1/5=<G>triplasiepi/pemptos</G></td><td align=center>subduplex sesquiquartus.</td></tr> | |
4191 <tr><td align=right>(triplex sesquiquintus) </td><td></td></tr> | |
4192 <tr><td> &c.</td><td></td></tr> | |
4193 <tr><td>5. (a) General</td><td align=center>5. (a) General</td></tr> | |
4194 <tr><td> <G>pollaplasiepimerh/s</G></td><td align=center> <G>u(popollaplasiepimerh/s</G></td></tr> | |
4195 <tr><td> (multiplex superpartiens).</td><td align=center>(submultiplex superpartiens),</td></tr> | |
4196 <tr><td>This is related to <G>e)pimerh/s</G> [(3) above] in the same way as <G>pollaplasiepimo/rios</G> to <G>e)pimo/rios</G>; that is to say, it is of the form <I>p</I>+<I>m</I>/(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>) or | |
4197 ((<I>p</I>+1)<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)/(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>).</td><td align=center>a fraction of the form (<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)/((<I>p</I>+1)<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>).</td></tr> | |
4198 </table> | |
4199 <pb n=104><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4200 <table> | |
4201 <tr><th align=right>RATIOS GREATER THAN UNITY </th><th align=center>RATIOS LESS THAN UNITY</th></tr> | |
4202 <tr><td> (b) Particular</td><td></td></tr> | |
4203 <tr><td> These names are only given for cases where <I>n</I>=1; they follow the first form of the names for particular <G>e)pimerei=s</G>, e.g.</td> | |
4204 <td> Corresponding names not found in Nicomachus; but Boëtius has <I>subduplex superbipartiens</I>, | |
4205 &c.</td></tr> | |
4206 <tr><td> 2 2/3=<G>diplasiepidimerh/s</G></td><td></td></tr> | |
4207 <tr><td align=right>(duplex superbipartiens)</td><td></td></tr> | |
4208 <tr><td> &c.</td><td></td></tr> | |
4209 </table> | |
4210 <p>In c. 23 Nicomachus shows how these various ratios can be | |
4211 got from one another by means of a certain rule. Suppose | |
4212 that | |
4213 <I>a, b, c</I> | |
4214 are three numbers such that <I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=one of the ratios | |
4215 described; we form the three numbers | |
4216 <MATH><I>a, a</I>+<I>b, a</I>+2<I>b</I>+<I>c</I></MATH> | |
4217 and also the three numbers | |
4218 <MATH><I>c, c</I>+<I>b</I>, <I>c</I>+2<I>b</I>+<I>a</I></MATH> | |
4219 Two illustrations may be given. If <I>a</I>=<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>=1, repeated | |
4220 application of the first formula gives (1, 2, 4), then (1, 3, 9), | |
4221 then (1, 4, 16), and so on, showing the successive multiples. | |
4222 Applying the second formula to (1, 2, 4), we get (4, 6, 9) where | |
4223 the ratio is 3/2; similarly from (1, 3, 9) we get (9, 12, 16) where | |
4224 the ratio is 4/3, and so on; that is, from the <G>pollapla/sioi</G> we | |
4225 get the <G>e)pimo/rioi</G>. Again from (9, 6, 4), where the ratio is | |
4226 of the latter kind, we get by the first formula (9, 15, 25), | |
4227 giving the ratio 1 2/3, an <G>e)pimerh/s</G>, and by the second formula | |
4228 (4, 10, 25), giving the ratio 2 1/2, a <G>pollaplasiepimo/rios</G>. And | |
4229 so on. | |
4230 <p>Book II begins with two chapters showing how, by a con- | |
4231 verse process, three terms in continued proportion with any | |
4232 one of the above forms as common ratio can be reduced to | |
4233 three equal terms. If | |
4234 <I>a, b, c</I> | |
4235 <pb n=105><head>NICOMACHUS</head> | |
4236 are the original terms, <I>a</I> being the smallest, we take three | |
4237 terms of the form | |
4238 <MATH><I>a, b</I>-<I>a</I>, {<I>c</I>-<I>a</I>-2(<I>b</I>-<I>a</I>)}=<I>c</I>+<I>a</I>-2<I>b</I></MATH>, | |
4239 then apply the same rule to these three, and so on. | |
4240 <p>In cc. 3-4 it is pointed out that, if | |
4241 <MATH>1, <I>r</I>, <I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>..., <I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP>...</MATH> | |
4242 be a geometrical progression, and if | |
4243 <MATH><G>r</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>=<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP>+<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP></MATH>, | |
4244 then <MATH><G>r</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>/<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP>=(<I>r</I>+1)/<I>r</I></MATH>, an <G>e)pimo/rios</G> ratio, | |
4245 and similarly, if <MATH><G>r/</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>=<G>r</G><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>+<G>r</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>, | |
4246 <G>r/</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>/<G>r</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>=(<I>r</I>+1)/<I>r</I></MATH>; | |
4247 and so on. | |
4248 <p>If we set out in rows numbers formed in this way, | |
4249 <table> | |
4250 <tr><td>1,</td><td><I>r</I>,</td><td><I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>,</td><td><I>r</I><SUP>3</SUP>...</td><td><I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP></td></tr> | |
4251 <tr><td></td><td><I>r</I>+1,</td><td><I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>r</I>,</td><td><I>r</I><SUP>3</SUP>+<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>...</td><td><I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP>+<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP></td></tr> | |
4252 <tr><td></td><td></td><td><I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>+2<I>r</I>+1,</td><td><I>r</I><SUP>3</SUP>+2<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>r</I>...</td><td><I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP>+2<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP>+<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I>-2</SUP></td></tr> | |
4253 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><I>r</I><SUP>3</SUP>+3<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>+3<I>r</I>+1...</td><td><I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP>+3<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP>+3<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I>-2</SUP>+<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I>-3</SUP></td></tr> | |
4254 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td align=center>.</td></tr> | |
4255 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td align=center>.</td></tr> | |
4256 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td align=center>.</td></tr> | |
4257 <tr><td></td><td></td><td></td><td></td><td><I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP>+<I>nr</I><SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP>+(<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>-1))/2<I>r</I><SUP><I>n</I>-2</SUP>+...+1,</td></tr> | |
4258 </table> | |
4259 the vertical rows are successive numbers in the ratio <I>r</I>/(<I>r</I>+1), | |
4260 while diagonally we have the geometrical series 1, <I>r</I>+1, | |
4261 (<I>r</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP>, (<I>r</I>+1)<SUP>3</SUP>.... | |
4262 <p>Next follows the theory of polygonal numbers. It is pre- | |
4263 faced by an explanation of the quasi-geometrical way of | |
4264 representing numbers by means of dots or <I>a</I>'s. Any number | |
4265 from 2 onwards can be represented as a <I>line</I>; the <I>plane</I> num- | |
4266 bers begin with 3, which is the first number that can be | |
4267 represented in the form of a <I>triangle</I>; after triangles follow | |
4268 squares, pentagons, hexagons, &c. (c. 7). Triangles (c. 8) arise | |
4269 by adding any number of successive terms, beginning with 1, | |
4270 of the series of natural numbers | |
4271 1, 2, 3, ... <I>n</I>, .... | |
4272 <pb n=106><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4273 The <I>gnomons</I> of triangles are therefore the successive natural | |
4274 numbers. Squares (c. 9) are obtained by adding any number | |
4275 of successive terms of the series of odd numbers, beginning | |
4276 with 1, or | |
4277 <MATH>1, 3, 5, ...2<I>n</I>-1,....</MATH> | |
4278 The <I>gnomons</I> of squares are the successive odd numbers. | |
4279 Similarly the <I>gnomons</I> of pentagonal numbers (c. 10) are the | |
4280 numbers forming an arithmetical progression with 3 as com- | |
4281 mon difference, or | |
4282 <MATH>1, 4, 7, ... 1+(<I>n</I>-1) 3, ...</MATH>; | |
4283 and generally (c. 11) the gnomons of polygonal numbers of <I>a</I> | |
4284 sides are | |
4285 <MATH>1, 1+(<I>a</I>-2), 1+2(<I>a</I>-2),...1+(<I>r</I>-1)(<I>a</I>-2),...</MATH> | |
4286 and the <I>a</I>-gonal number with side <I>n</I> is | |
4287 <MATH>1+1+(<I>a</I>-2)+1+2(<I>a</I>-2)+...+1+(<I>n</I>-1)(<I>a</I>-2) | |
4288 =<I>n</I>+1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>-1)(<I>a</I>-2)</MATH> | |
4289 The general formula is not given by Nicomachus, who con- | |
4290 tents himself with writing down a certain number of poly- | |
4291 gonal numbers of each species up to heptagons. | |
4292 <p>After mentioning (c. 12) that any square is the sum of two | |
4293 successive triangular numbers, i.e. | |
4294 <MATH><I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>=1/2(<I>n</I>-1)<I>n</I>+1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)</MATH>, | |
4295 and that an <I>a</I>-gonal number of side <I>n</I> is the sum of an | |
4296 (<I>a</I>-1)-gonal number of side <I>n</I> plus a triangular number of | |
4297 side <I>n</I>-1, i.e. | |
4298 <MATH><I>n</I>+1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>-1)(<I>a</I>-2)=<I>n</I>+1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>-1)(<I>a</I>-3)+1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>-1)</MATH>, | |
4299 he passes (c. 13) to the first <I>solid</I> number, the <I>pyramid.</I> The | |
4300 base of the pyramid may be a triangular, a square, or any | |
4301 polygonal number. If the base has the side <I>n</I>, the pyramid is | |
4302 formed by similar and similarly situated polygons placed | |
4303 successively upon it, each of which has 1 less in its side than | |
4304 that which precedes it; it ends of course in a unit at the top, | |
4305 the unit being ‘potentially’ any polygonal number. Nico- | |
4306 machus mentions the first triangular pyramids as being 1, 4, | |
4307 10, 20, 35, 56, 84, and (c. 14) explains the formation of the | |
4308 series of pyramids with square bases, but he gives no general | |
4309 <pb n=107><head>NICOMACHUS</head> | |
4310 formula or summation. An <I>a</I>-gonal number with <I>n</I> in its | |
4311 side being | |
4312 <MATH><I>n</I>+1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>-1)(<I>a</I>-2)</MATH>, | |
4313 it follows that the pyramid with that polygonal number for | |
4314 base is | |
4315 <MATH>1+2+3+...+<I>n</I>+1/2(<I>a</I>-2){1.2+2.3+...+(<I>n</I>-1)<I>n</I>} | |
4316 =(<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1))/2+(<I>a</I>-2)/2.((<I>n</I>-1)<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1))/3</MATH>. | |
4317 <p>A pyramid is <G>ko/louros</G>, <I>truncated</I>, when the unit is cut off | |
4318 the top, <G>diko/louros</G>, <I>twice-truncated</I>, when the unit and the | |
4319 next layer is cut off, <G>triko/louros</G>, <I>thrice-truncated</I>, when three | |
4320 layers are cut off, and so on (c. 14). | |
4321 <p>Other solid numbers are then classified (cc. 15-17): <I>cubes</I>, | |
4322 which are the product of three equal numbers; <I>scalene</I> num- | |
4323 bers, which are the product of three numbers all unequal, | |
4324 and which are alternatively called <I>wedges</I> (<G>sfhni/skoi</G>), <I>stakes</I> | |
4325 (<G>sfhki/skoi</G>), or <I>altars</I> (<G>bwmi/skoi</G>). The latter three names are | |
4326 in reality inappropriate to mere products of three unequal | |
4327 factors, since the figure which could properly be called by | |
4328 these names should <I>taper</I>, i.e. should have the plane face at | |
4329 the top less than the base. We shall find when we come to | |
4330 the chapter on Heron's mensuration that true (geometrical) | |
4331 <G>bwmi/skoi</G> and <G>sfhni/skoi</G> have there to be measured in which | |
4332 the top rectangular face is in fact smaller than the rectangular | |
4333 base parallel to it. Iamblichus too indicates the true nature | |
4334 of <G>bwmi/skoi</G> and <G>sfhni/skoi</G> when he says that they have not | |
4335 only their dimensions but also their faces and angles unequal, | |
4336 and that, while the <G>plinqi/s</G> or <G>doki/s</G> corresponds to the paral- | |
4337 lelogram, the <G>sfhni/skos</G> corresponds to the trapezium.<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 93. 18, 94. 1-3.</note> The | |
4338 use, therefore, of the terms in question as alternatives to <I>scalene</I> | |
4339 appears to be due to a misapprehension. Other varieties of | |
4340 solid numbers are <I>parallelepipeds</I>, in which there are faces | |
4341 which are <G>e(teromh/keis</G> (oblong) or of the form <I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1), so | |
4342 that two factors differ by unity; <I>beams</I> (<G>doki/des</G>) or <I>columns</I> | |
4343 (<G>sthli/des</G>, Iamblichus) of the form <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>); <I>tiles</I> (<G>plinqi/des</G>) | |
4344 of the form <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>(<I>m</I>-<I>n</I>). Cubes, the last digit (the units) of | |
4345 which are the same as the last digit in the side, are <I>spherical</I> | |
4346 <pb n=108><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4347 (<G>sfairikoi/</G>) or <I>recurring</I> (<G>a)pokatastatikoi/</G>); these sides and | |
4348 cubes end in 1, 5, or 6, and, as the squares end in the same | |
4349 digits, the squares are called <I>circular</I> (<G>kuklikoi/</G>). | |
4350 <p><I>Oblong</I> numbers (<G>e(teromh/keis</G>) are, as we have seen, of the | |
4351 form <I>m</I>(<I>m</I>+1); <I>prolate</I> numbers (<G>promh/keis</G>) of the form | |
4352 <I>m</I>(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>) where <I>n</I>>1 (c. 18). Some simple relations between | |
4353 oblong numbers, squares, and triangular numbers are given | |
4354 (cc. 19-20). If <I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB> represents the oblong number <I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1), and | |
4355 <I>t</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB> the triangular number 1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1) of side <I>n</I>, we have, for | |
4356 example, | |
4357 <MATH><I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>/<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>n</I>+1)/<I>n</I>, <I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>-<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>n</I>, <I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>=<I>n</I>/(<I>n</I>-1), | |
4358 <I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>=<I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>/(<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP>, <I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP>+2<I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>=(2<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP>, | |
4359 <I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>=<I>t</I><SUB>2<I>n</I></SUB>, <I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>+(<I>n</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP>=<I>t</I><SUB>2<I>n</I>+1</SUB></MATH>, | |
4360 <MATH><I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>±<I>n</I>=<BRACE><I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB> | |
4361 <I>h</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB></BRACE></MATH>, | |
4362 all of which formulae are easily verified. | |
4363 <C><I>Sum of series of cube numbers.</I></C> | |
4364 <p>C. 20 ends with an interesting statement about cubes. If, | |
4365 says Nicomachus, we set out the series of odd numbers | |
4366 1, 3, 5, 7, 9, 11, 13, 15, 17, 19,... | |
4367 the first (1) is a cube, the sum of the next <I>two</I> (3+5) is a | |
4368 cube, the sum of the next <I>three</I> (7+9+11) is a cube, and so on. | |
4369 We can prove this law by assuming that <I>n</I><SUP>3</SUP> is equal to the | |
4370 sum of <I>n</I> odd numbers beginning with 2<I>x</I>+1 and ending | |
4371 with 2<I>x</I>+2<I>n</I>-1. The sum is (2<I>x</I>+<I>n</I>)<I>n</I>; since therefore | |
4372 <MATH>(2<I>x</I>+<I>n</I>)<I>n</I>=<I>n</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH>, | |
4373 <MATH><I>x</I>=1/2(<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>n</I>)</MATH>, | |
4374 and the formula is | |
4375 <MATH>(<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>n</I>+1)+(<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>n</I>+3)+...+(<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>n</I>-1)=<I>n</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH>. | |
4376 <p>By putting successively <I>n</I>=1, 2, 3...<I>r</I>, &c., in this formula | |
4377 and adding the results we find that | |
4378 <MATH>1<SUP>3</SUP>+2<SUP>3</SUP>+3<SUP>3</SUP>+...+<I>r</I><SUP>3</SUP>=1+(3+5)+(7+9+11)+...+(...<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>r</I>-1)</MATH>. | |
4379 <p>The number of terms in this series of odd numbers is clearly | |
4380 <MATH>1+2+3+...+<I>r</I> or 1/2<I>r</I>(<I>r</I>+1)</MATH>. | |
4381 <p>Therefore <MATH>1<SUP>3</SUP>+2<SUP>3</SUP>+3<SUP>3</SUP>+...+<I>r</I><SUP>3</SUP>=1/4<I>r</I>(<I>r</I>+1)(1+<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>r</I>-1) | |
4382 ={1/2<I>r</I>(<I>r</I>+1)}<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
4383 <pb n=109><head>SUM OF SERIES OF CUBE NUMBERS</head> | |
4384 <p>Nicomachus does not give this formula, but it was known | |
4385 to the Roman <I>agrimensores</I>, and it would be strange if | |
4386 Nicomachus was not aware of it. It may have been dis- | |
4387 covered by the same mathematician who found out the | |
4388 proposition actually stated by Nicomachus, which probably | |
4389 belongs to a much earlier time. For the Greeks were from | |
4390 the time of the early Pythagoreans accustomed to summing | |
4391 the series of odd numbers by placing 3, 5, 7, &c., successively | |
4392 as gnomons round 1; they knew that the result, whatever | |
4393 the number of gnomons, was always a square, and that, if the | |
4394 number of gnomons added to 1 is (say) <I>r</I>, the sum (including | |
4395 the 1) is (<I>r</I>+1)<SUP>2</SUP>. Hence, when it was once discovered that | |
4396 the first cube after 1, i.e. 2<SUP>3</SUP>, is 3+5, the second, or 3<SUP>3</SUP>, is | |
4397 7+9+11, the third, or 4<SUP>3</SUP>, is 13+15+17+19, and so on, they | |
4398 were in a position to sum the series 1<SUP>3</SUP>+2<SUP>3</SUP>+3<SUP>3</SUP>+...+<I>r</I><SUP>3</SUP>; | |
4399 for it was only necessary to find out how many terms of the | |
4400 series 1+3+5+... this sum of cubes includes. The number | |
4401 of terms being clearly 1+2+3+...+<I>r</I>, the number of | |
4402 gnomons (including the 1 itself) is 1/2<I>r</I>(<I>r</I>+1); hence the sum | |
4403 of them all (including the 1), which is equal to | |
4404 <MATH>1<SUP>3</SUP>+2<SUP>3</SUP>+3<SUP>3</SUP>+...+<I>r</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH>, | |
4405 is <MATH>{1/2<I>r</I>(<I>r</I>+1)}<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. Fortunately we possess a piece of evidence | |
4406 which makes it highly probable that the Greeks actually | |
4407 dealt with the problem in this way. Alkarkhī, the Arabian | |
4408 algebraist of the tenth-eleventh century, wrote an algebra | |
4409 under the title <I>Al-Fakhrī.</I> It would seem that there were at | |
4410 the time two schools in Arabia which were opposed to one | |
4411 another in that one favoured Greek, and the other Indian, | |
4412 methods. Alkarkhī was one of those who followed Greek | |
4413 models almost exclusively, and he has a proof of the theorem | |
4414 now in question by means of a figure with gnomons drawn | |
4415 in it, furnishing an excellent example of the geometrical | |
4416 algebra which is so distinctively Greek. | |
4417 <p>Let <I>AB</I> be the side of a square <I>AC</I>; let | |
4418 <MATH><I>AB</I>=1+2+...+<I>n</I>=1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)</MATH>, | |
4419 and suppose <I>BB</I>′=<I>n</I>, <I>B</I>′<I>B</I>″=<I>n</I>-1, <I>B</I>″<I>B</I>‴=<I>n</I>-2, and so on. | |
4420 Draw the squares on <I>AB</I>′, <I>AB</I>″... forming the gnomons | |
4421 shown in the figure. | |
4422 <pb n=110><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4423 <FIG> | |
4424 <p>Then the gnomon | |
4425 <MATH><I>BC</I>′<I>D</I>=<I>BB</I>′.<I>BC</I>+<I>DD</I>′.<I>C</I>′<I>D</I>′ | |
4426 =<I>BB</I>′(<I>BC</I>+<I>C</I>′<I>D</I>′)</MATH>. | |
4427 <p>Now <MATH><I>BC</I>=1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)</MATH>, | |
4428 <MATH><I>C</I>′<I>D</I>′=1+2+3+...+(<I>n</I>-1)=1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>-1), <I>BB</I>′=<I>n</I></MATH>; | |
4429 therefore (gnomon <I>BC</I>′<I>D</I>)=<I>n</I>.<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>n</I><SUP>3</SUP>. | |
4430 <p>Similarly (gnomon <I>B</I>′<I>C</I>″<I>D</I>′)=(<I>n</I>-1)<SUP>3</SUP>, and so on. | |
4431 <p>Therefore 1<SUP>3</SUP>+2<SUP>3</SUP>+...+<I>n</I><SUP>3</SUP>=the sum of the gnomons round | |
4432 the small square at <I>A</I> which has 1 for its side <I>plus</I> that small | |
4433 square; that is, | |
4434 <MATH>1<SUP>3</SUP>+2<SUP>3</SUP>+3<SUP>3</SUP>+...+<I>n</I><SUP>3</SUP>=square <I>AC</I>={1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1)}<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
4435 <p>It is easy to see that the first gnomon about the small | |
4436 square at <I>A</I> is 3+5=2<SUP>3</SUP>, the next gnomon is <MATH>7+9+11=3<SUP>3</SUP></MATH>, | |
4437 and so on. | |
4438 <p>The demonstration therefore hangs together with the | |
4439 theorem stated by Nicomachus. Two alternatives are possible. | |
4440 Alkarkhī may have devised the proof himself in the Greek | |
4441 manner, following the hint supplied by Nicomachus's theorem. | |
4442 Or he may have found the whole proof set out in some | |
4443 Greek treatise now lost and reproduced it. Whichever alter- | |
4444 native is the true one, we can hardly doubt the Greek origin | |
4445 of the summation of the series of cubes. | |
4446 <p>Nicomachus passes to the theory of arithmetical proportion | |
4447 and the various <I>means</I> (cc. 21-9), a description of which has | |
4448 already been given (p. 87 above). There are a few more | |
4449 propositions to be mentioned under this head. If <MATH><I>a</I>-<I>b</I>=<I>b</I>-<I>c</I></MATH>, | |
4450 so that <I>a, b, c</I> are in arithmetical progression, then (c. 23. 6) | |
4451 <MATH><I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>ac</I>=(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
4452 <pb n=111><head>NICOMACHUS</head> | |
4453 a fact which, according to Nicomachus, was not generally | |
4454 known. Boëtius<note>Boëtius, <I>Inst. Ar.</I> ii. c. 43.</note> mentions this proposition which, if we | |
4455 take <MATH><I>a</I>+<I>d, a, a</I>-<I>d</I></MATH> as the three terms in arithmetical pro- | |
4456 gression, may be written <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>a</I>+<I>d</I>)(<I>a</I>-<I>d</I>)+<I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. This is | |
4457 presumably the origin of the <I>regula Nicomachi</I> quoted by | |
4458 one Ocreatus (? O'Creat), the author of a tract, <I>Prologus in | |
4459 Helceph</I>, written in the twelfth or thirteenth century<note>See <I>Abh. zur Gesch. d. Math</I>. 3, 1880, p. 134.</note> | |
4460 (‘Helceph’ or ‘Helcep’ is evidently equivalent to <I>Algo- | |
4461 rismus</I>; may it perhaps be meant for the <I>Al-Kāfī</I> of | |
4462 Alkarkhī?). The object of the <I>regula</I> is to find the square | |
4463 of a number containing a single digit. If <I>d</I>=10-<I>a</I>, or | |
4464 <I>a</I>+<I>d</I>=10, the rule is represented by the formula | |
4465 <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>=10(<I>a</I>-<I>d</I>)+<I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
4466 so that the calculation of <I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP> is made to depend on that of <I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP> | |
4467 which is easier to evaluate if <I>d</I><<I>a</I>. | |
4468 <p>Again (c. 24. 3, 4), if <I>a, b, c</I> be three terms in descending | |
4469 geometrical progression, <I>r</I> being the common ratio (<I>a/b</I> or <I>b/c</I>), | |
4470 then | |
4471 <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)/(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=<I>a</I>/<I>b</I>=<I>b</I>/<I>c</I></MATH> | |
4472 and <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)=(<I>r</I>-1)<I>b</I>, (<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=(<I>r</I>-1)<I>c</I>, | |
4473 (<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)-(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)=(<I>r</I>-1)(<I>b</I>-<I>c</I>)</MATH>. | |
4474 <p>It follows that | |
4475 <MATH><I>b</I>=<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>(<I>r</I>-1)=<I>c</I>+<I>c</I>(<I>r</I>-1)</MATH>. | |
4476 <p>This is the property of three terms in geometrical pro- | |
4477 gression which corresponds to the property of three terms | |
4478 <I>a, b, c</I> of a harmonical progression | |
4479 <MATH><I>b</I>=<I>a</I>-<I>a</I>/<I>n</I>=<I>c</I>+<I>c</I>/<I>n</I></MATH>, | |
4480 from which we derive | |
4481 <MATH><I>n</I>=(<I>a</I>+<I>c</I>)/(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>)</MATH>. | |
4482 <p>If <I>a, b, c</I> are in descending order, Nicomachus observes | |
4483 (c. 25) that <I>a</I>/<I>b</I><=><I>b</I>/<I>c</I> according as <I>a, b, c</I> are in arith- | |
4484 metical, geometrical, or harmonical progression. | |
4485 <pb n=112><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4486 <p>The ‘Platonic theorem’ (c. 24. 6) about the number of | |
4487 possible means (geometric) between two square numbers and | |
4488 between two cube numbers respectively has already been | |
4489 mentioned (pp. 89, 90), as also the ‘most perfect proportion’ | |
4490 (p. 86). | |
4491 <p>THEON OF SMYRNA was the author of a book purporting | |
4492 to be a manual of mathematical subjects such as a student | |
4493 would require to enable him to understand Plato. A fuller | |
4494 account of this work will be given later; at present we are | |
4495 only concerned with the arithmetical portion. This gives the | |
4496 elementary theory of numbers on much the same lines as | |
4497 we find it in Nicomachus, though less systematically. We | |
4498 can here pass over the things which are common to Theon | |
4499 and Nicomachus and confine ourselves to what is peculiar to | |
4500 the former. The important things are two. One is the | |
4501 theory of side- and diameter-numbers invented by the Pytha- | |
4502 goreans for the purpose of finding the successive integral | |
4503 solutions of the equations <MATH>2<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=±1</MATH>; as to this see | |
4504 pp. 91-3 above. The other is an explanation of the limited | |
4505 number of forms which square numbers may have.<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 35. 17-36. 2.</note> If <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP> is | |
4506 a square number, says Theon, either <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP> or <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1 is divisible | |
4507 by 3, and again either <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP> or <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1 is divisible by 4: which | |
4508 is equivalent to saying that a square number cannot be of | |
4509 any of the following forms, <MATH>3<I>n</I>+2, 4<I>n</I>+2, 4<I>n</I>+3</MATH>. Again, he | |
4510 says, for any square number <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>, <I>one</I> of the following alterna- | |
4511 tives must hold: | |
4512 <MATH>(1) (<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)/3, <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4 both integral (e.g. <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>=4), | |
4513 (2) (<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)/4, <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>/3 both integral (e.g. <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>=9), | |
4514 (3) <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>/3, <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4 both integral (e.g. <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>=36), | |
4515 (4) (<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)/3, (<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)/4 both integral (e.g. <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>=25)</MATH>. | |
4516 <pb n=113><head>ARITHMETIC IN THEON OF SMYRNA</head> | |
4517 Iamblichus states the same facts in a slightly different form.<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 90. 6-11.</note> | |
4518 The truth of these statements can be seen in the following | |
4519 way.<note>Cf. Loria, <I>Le scienze esatte nell</I>' <I>antica Grecia</I>, p. 834.</note> Since any number <I>m</I> must have one of the following | |
4520 forms | |
4521 <MATH>6<I>k</I>, 6<I>k</I>±1, 6<I>k</I>±2, 6<I>k</I>±3</MATH>, | |
4522 any square <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP> must have one or other of the forms | |
4523 <MATH>36<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>, 36<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>±12<I>k</I>+1, 36<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>±24<I>k</I>+4, 36<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>±36<I>k</I>+9</MATH>. | |
4524 For squares of the first type <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>/3 and <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4 are both integral, | |
4525 for those of the second type (<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)/3, (<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)/4 are both integral, | |
4526 for those of the third type (<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)/3 and <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4 are both integral, | |
4527 and for those of the fourth type <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>/3 and (<I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)/4 are both | |
4528 integral; which agrees with Theon's statement. Again, if | |
4529 the four forms of squares be divided by 3 or 4, the remainder | |
4530 is always either 0 or 1; so that, as Theon says, no square can | |
4531 be of the form 3<I>n</I>+2, 4<I>n</I>+2, or 4<I>n</I>+3. We can hardly | |
4532 doubt that these discoveries were also Pythagorean. | |
4533 <p>IAMBLICHUS, born at Chalcis in Coele-Syria, was a pupil of | |
4534 Anatolius and Porphyry, and belongs to the first half of the | |
4535 fourth century A.D. He wrote nine Books on the Pythagorean | |
4536 Sect, the titles of which were as follows: I. On the Life of | |
4537 Pythagoras; II. Exhortation to philosophy (<G>*protreptiko\s | |
4538 e)pi\ filosofi/an</G>); III. On mathematical science in general; | |
4539 IV. On Nicomachus's <I>Introductio Arithmetica</I>; V. On arith- | |
4540 metical science in physics; VI. On arithmetical science in | |
4541 ethics; VII. On arithmetical science in theology; VIII. On | |
4542 the Pythagorean geometry; IX. On the Pythagorean music. | |
4543 The first four of these books survive and are accessible in | |
4544 modern editions; the other five are lost, though extracts | |
4545 from VII. are doubtless contained in the <I>Theologumena | |
4546 arithmetices.</I> Book IV. on Nicomachus's <I>Introductio</I> is that | |
4547 which concerns us here; and the few things requiring notice | |
4548 are the following. The first is the view of a square number | |
4549 <pb n=114><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4550 as a race-course (<G>di/aulos</G>)<note>Iambl. <I>in Nicom.</I>, p. 75. 25-77. 4.</note> formed of successive numbers | |
4551 from 1 (as <I>start</I>, <G>u(/splhx</G>) up to <I>n</I>, the side of the square, | |
4552 which is the turning-point (<G>kampth/r</G>), and then back again | |
4553 through (<I>n</I>-1), (<I>n</I>-2), &c., to 1 (the <I>goal</I>, <G>nu/ssa</G>), thus: | |
4554 <MATH>1+2+3+4... (<I>n</I>-1)+<I>n</I> | |
4555 1+2+3+4...(<I>n</I>-2)+(<I>n</I>-1)+<I>n</I></MATH>. | |
4556 This is of course equivalent to the proposition that <I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP> is the | |
4557 sum of the two triangular numbers 1/2<I>n</I>(<I>n</I>+1) and 1/2(<I>n</I>-1)<I>n</I> | |
4558 with sides <I>n</I> and <I>n</I>-1 respectively. Similarly Iamblichus | |
4559 points out<note><I>Ib.</I>, pp. 77. 4-80. 9.</note> that the <I>oblong</I> number | |
4560 <MATH><I>n</I>(<I>n</I>-1)=(1+2+3+...+<I>n</I>)+(<I>n</I>-2+<I>n</I>-3+...+3+2)</MATH>. | |
4561 He observes that it was on this principle that, after 10, | |
4562 which was called the <I>unit of the second course</I> (<G>deuterw- | |
4563 doume/nh mona/s</G>), the Pythagoreans regarded 100=10.10 as | |
4564 the <I>unit of the third course</I> (<G>triwdoume/nh mona/s</G>), 1000=10<SUP>3</SUP> | |
4565 as the <I>unit of the fourth course</I> (<G>tetrwdoume/nh mona/s</G>), and | |
4566 so on,<note><I>Ib.</I>, pp. 88. 15-90. 2.</note> since | |
4567 <MATH>1+2+3+...+10+9+8+...+2+1=10.10, | |
4568 10+20+30+...+100+90+80+...+20+10=10<SUP>3</SUP>, | |
4569 100+200+300+...+1000+900+...+200+100=10<SUP>4</SUP></MATH>, | |
4570 and so on. Iamblichus sees herein the special virtue of 10: | |
4571 but of course the same formulae would hold in any scale | |
4572 of notation as well as the decimal. | |
4573 <p>In connexion with this Pythagorean decimal terminology | |
4574 Iamblichus gives a proposition of the greatest interest.<note><I>Ib.</I>, pp. 103. 10-104. 13.</note> | |
4575 Suppose we have any three consecutive numbers the greatest | |
4576 of which is divisible by 3. Take the sum of the three | |
4577 numbers; this will consist of a certain number of units, | |
4578 a certain number of tens, a certain number of hundreds, and | |
4579 so on. Now take the units in the said sum as they are, then | |
4580 as many units as there are tens in the sum, as many units as | |
4581 there are hundreds, and so on, and add all the units so | |
4582 obtained together (i.e. add the <I>digits</I> of the sum expressed | |
4583 in our decimal notation). Apply the same procedure to the | |
4584 <pb n=115><head>IAMBLICHUS</head> | |
4585 result, and so on. Then, says Iamblichus, <I>the final result | |
4586 will be the number</I> 6. E.g. take the numbers 10, 11, 12; the | |
4587 sum is 33. Add the digits, and the result is 6. Take | |
4588 994, 995, 996: the sum is 2985; the sum of the digits is 24; | |
4589 and the sum of the digits of 24 is again 6. The truth of the | |
4590 general proposition is seen in this way.<note>Loria, <I>op. cit.</I>, pp. 841-2.</note> | |
4591 <p>Let <MATH><I>N</I>=<I>n</I><SUB>0</SUB>+10<I>n</I><SUB>1</SUB>+10<SUP>2</SUP><I>n</I><SUB>2</SUB>+...</MATH> | |
4592 be a number written in the decimal notation. Let <I>S</I>(<I>N</I>) | |
4593 represent the sum of its digits, <I>S</I><SUP>(2)</SUP>(<I>N</I>) the sum of the digits | |
4594 of <I>S</I>(<I>N</I>) and so on. | |
4595 <p>Now <MATH><I>N</I>-<I>S</I>(<I>N</I>)=9(<I>n</I><SUB>1</SUB>+11<I>n</I><SUB>2</SUB>+111<I>n</I><SUB>3</SUB>+...)</MATH>, | |
4596 whence <MATH><I>N</I>&equals3;<I>S</I>(<I>N</I>)</MATH> (mod. 9). | |
4597 Similarly <MATH><I>S</I>(<I>N</I>)&equals3;<I>S</I><SUP>(2)</SUP><I>N</I></MATH> (mod. 9). | |
4598 . | |
4599 . | |
4600 . | |
4601 <p>Let <MATH><I>S</I><SUP>(<I>k</I>-1)</SUP>(<I>N</I>)&equals3;<I>S</I><SUP>(<I>k</I>)</SUP><I>N</I></MATH> (mod. 9) | |
4602 be the last possible relation of this kind; <I>S</I><SUP>(<I>k</I>)</SUP><I>N</I> will be a | |
4603 number <I>N</I>′<02>9. | |
4604 <p>Adding the congruences, we obtain | |
4605 <MATH><I>N</I>&equals3;<I>N</I>′</MATH> (mod. 9), while <MATH><I>N</I>′<02>9</MATH>. | |
4606 <p>Now, if we have three consecutive numbers the greatest | |
4607 of which is divisible by 3, we can put for their sum | |
4608 <MATH><I>N</I>=(3<I>p</I>+1)+(3<I>p</I>+2)+(3<I>p</I>+3)=9<I>p</I>+6</MATH>, | |
4609 and the above congruence becomes | |
4610 <MATH>9<I>p</I>+6&equals3;<I>N</I>′</MATH> (mod. 9), | |
4611 so that <MATH><I>N</I>′&equals3;6</MATH> (mod. 9); | |
4612 and, since <MATH><I>N</I>′<02>9</MATH>, <I>N</I>′ can only be equal to 6. | |
4613 <p>This addition of the digits of a number expressed in our | |
4614 notation has an important parallel in a passage of the | |
4615 <I>Refutation of all Heresies</I> by saint Hippolytus,<note>Hippolytus, <I>Refut.</I> iv, c. 14.</note> where there | |
4616 is a description of a method of foretelling future events | |
4617 called the ‘Pythagorean calculus’. Those, he says, who | |
4618 claim to predict events by means of calculations with numbers, | |
4619 letters and names use the principle of the <I>pythmen</I> or <I>base</I>, | |
4620 <pb n=116><head>PYTHAGOREAN ARITHMETIC</head> | |
4621 that is, what we call a digit of a number expressed in our | |
4622 decimal notation; for the Greeks, in the case of any number | |
4623 above 9, the <I>pythmen</I> was the same number of units as the | |
4624 alphabetical numeral contains tens, hundreds, thousands, &c. | |
4625 Thus the <I>pythmen</I> of 700 (<G>y</G> in Greek) is 7 (<G>z</G>); that of | |
4626 <G><SUB>'</SUB>s</G> (6000) is <G>s</G> (6), and so on. The method then proceeded | |
4627 to find the <I>pythmen</I> of a certain name, say <G>*)agame/mnwn</G>. | |
4628 Taking the <I>pythmenes</I> of all the letters and adding them, | |
4629 we have | |
4630 <MATH>1+3+1+4+5+4+5+8+5=36</MATH>. | |
4631 Take the <I>pythmenes</I> of 36, namely 3 and 6, and their sum is | |
4632 9. The <I>pythmen</I> of <G>*)agame/mnwn</G> is therefore 9. Next take | |
4633 the name <G>*(/ektwr</G>; the <I>pythmenes</I> are 5, 2, 3, 8, 1, the sum of | |
4634 which is 19; the <I>pythmenes</I> of 19 are 1, 9; the sum of 1 and | |
4635 9 is 10, the pythmen of which is 1. The <I>pythmen</I> of <G>*(/ektwr</G> | |
4636 is therefore 1. ‘It is easier’, says Hippolytus, ‘to proceed | |
4637 thus. Finding the <I>pythmenes</I> of the letters, we obtain, in the | |
4638 case of <G>*(/ektwr</G>, 19 as their sum. Divide this by 9 and note | |
4639 the remainder: thus, if I divide 19 by 9, the remainder is 1, | |
4640 for nine times 2 is 18, and 1 is left, which will accordingly | |
4641 be the <I>pythmen</I> of the name <G>*(/ektwr</G>.’ Again, take the name | |
4642 <G>*pa/troklos</G>. The sum of the <I>pythmenes</I> is | |
4643 <MATH>8+1+3+1+7+2+3+7+2=34</MATH>: | |
4644 and 3+4=7, so that 7 is the <I>pythmen</I> of <G>*pa/troklos</G>. | |
4645 ‘Those then who calculate by the <I>rule of nine</I> take one-ninth | |
4646 of the sum of the <I>pythmenes</I> and then determine the sum of | |
4647 the <I>pythmenes</I> in the remainder. Those on the other hand | |
4648 who follow the “rule of seven” divide by 7. Thus the sum | |
4649 of the <I>pythmenes</I> in <G>*pa/troklos</G> was found to be 34. This, | |
4650 divided by 7, gives 4, and since 7 times 4 is 28, the remainder | |
4651 is 6....’ ‘It is necessary to observe that, if the division | |
4652 gives an integral quotient (without remainder),... the | |
4653 <I>pythmen</I> is the number 9 itself’ (that is, if the <I>rule of nine</I> is | |
4654 followed). And so on. | |
4655 <p>Two things emerge from this fragment. (1) The use of the | |
4656 <I>pythmen</I> was not appearing for the first time when Apollonius | |
4657 framed his system for expressing and multiplying large | |
4658 numbers; it originated much earlier, with the Pythagoreans. | |
4659 <pb n=117><head>IAMBLICHUS</head> | |
4660 (2) The method of calculating the <I>pythmen</I> is like the opera- | |
4661 tion of ‘casting out nines’ in the proof which goes by that | |
4662 name, where we take the sum of the digits of a number and | |
4663 divide by 9 to get the remainder. The method of verification | |
4664 by ‘casting out nines’ came to us from the Arabs, who may, | |
4665 as Avicenna and Maximus Planudes tell us, have got it from | |
4666 the Indians; but the above evidence shows that, at all events, | |
4667 the elements from which it was built up lay ready to hand | |
4668 in the Pythagorean arithmetic. | |
4669 <pb> | |
4670 <C>IV</C> | |
4671 <C>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</C> | |
4672 <C>The ‘Summary’ of Proclus.</C> | |
4673 <p>WE shall often, in the course of this history, have occasion | |
4674 to quote from the so-called ‘Summary’ of Proclus, which has | |
4675 already been cited in the preceding chapter. Occupying a | |
4676 few pages (65-70) of Proclus's <I>Commentary on Euclid</I>, Book I, | |
4677 it reviews, in the briefest possible outline, the course of Greek | |
4678 geometry from the earliest times to Euclid, with special refer- | |
4679 ence to the evolution of the Elements. At one time it was | |
4680 often called the ‘Eudemian summary’, on the assumption | |
4681 that it was an extract from the great <I>History of Geometry</I> in | |
4682 four Books by Eudemus, the pupil of Aristotle. But a perusal | |
4683 of the summary itself is sufficient to show that it cannot | |
4684 have been written by Eudemus; the most that can be said is | |
4685 that, down to a certain sentence, it was probably based, more | |
4686 or less directly, upon data appearing in Eudemus's <I>History.</I> | |
4687 At the sentence in question there is a break in the narrative, | |
4688 as follows: | |
4689 <p>‘Those who have compiled histories bring the development | |
4690 of this science up to this point. Not much younger than | |
4691 these is Euclid, who put together the Elements, collecting | |
4692 many of the theorems of Eudoxus, perfecting many others by | |
4693 Theaetetus, and bringing to irrefragable demonstration the | |
4694 propositions which had only been somewhat loosely proved by | |
4695 his predecessors.’ | |
4696 <p>Since Euclid was later than Eudemus, it is impossible that | |
4697 Eudemus can have written this; while the description ‘those | |
4698 who have compiled histories’, and who by implication were | |
4699 a little older than Euclid, suits Eudemus excellently. Yet the | |
4700 style of the summary after the break does not show any | |
4701 such change from that of the earlier portion as to suggest | |
4702 <pb n=119><head>THE ‘SUMMARY’ OF PROCLUS</head> | |
4703 different authorship. The author of the earlier portion fre- | |
4704 quently refers to the question of the origin of the Elements of | |
4705 Geometry in a way in which no one would be likely to write | |
4706 who was not later than Euclid; and it seems to be the same | |
4707 hand which, in the second portion, connects the Elements of | |
4708 Euclid with the work of Eudoxus and Theaetetus. Indeed | |
4709 the author, whoever he was, seems to have compiled the sum- | |
4710 mary with one main object in view, namely, to trace the origin | |
4711 and growth of the Elements of Geometry; consequently he | |
4712 omits to refer to certain famous discoveries in geometry such | |
4713 as the solutions of the problem of the duplication of the cube, | |
4714 doubtless because they did not belong to the Elements. In | |
4715 two cases he alludes to such discoveries, as it were in paren- | |
4716 thesis, in order to recall to the mind of the reader a current | |
4717 association of the name of a particular geometer with a par- | |
4718 ticular discovery. Thus he mentions Hippocrates of Chios as | |
4719 a famous geometer for the particular reason that he was the | |
4720 first to write Elements, and he adds to his name, for the pur- | |
4721 pose of identification, ‘the discoverer of the quadrature of the | |
4722 lune’. Similarly, when he says of Pythagoras ‘(he it was) | |
4723 who’ (<G>o(\s dh\</G> . . .) ‘discovered the theory of irrationals [or | |
4724 “proportions”] and the construction of the cosmic figures’, | |
4725 he seems to be alluding, entirely on his own account, to a | |
4726 popular tradition to that effect. If the summary is the work | |
4727 of one author, who was it? Tannery answers that it was | |
4728 Geminus; but this seems highly improbable, for the extracts | |
4729 from Geminus's work which we possess suggest that the | |
4730 subjects therein discussed were of a different kind; they seem | |
4731 rather to have been general questions relating to the philoso- | |
4732 phy and content of mathematics, and even Tannery admits | |
4733 that historical details could only have come incidentally into | |
4734 the work. | |
4735 <p>Could the author have been Proclus himself? This again | |
4736 seems, on the whole, improbable. In favour of the authorship | |
4737 of Proclus are the facts (1) that the question of the origin of | |
4738 the Elements is kept prominent and (2) that there is no men- | |
4739 tion of Democritus, whom Eudemus would not have ignored, | |
4740 while a follower of Plato such as Proclus might have done | |
4741 him this injustice, following the example of Plato himself, who | |
4742 was an opponent of Democritus, never once mentions him, and | |
4743 <pb n=120><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
4744 is said to have wished to burn all his writings. On the other | |
4745 hand (1) the style of the summary is not such as to point | |
4746 to Proclus as the author; (2) if he wrote it, it is hardly | |
4747 conceivable that he would have passed over in silence the dis- | |
4748 covery of the analytical method, ‘the finest’, as he says else- | |
4749 where, of the traditional methods in geometry, ‘which Plato is | |
4750 said to have communicated to Leodamas’. Nor (3) is it | |
4751 easy to suppose that Proclus would have spoken in the | |
4752 detached way that the author does of Euclid whose <I>Elements</I> | |
4753 was the subject of his whole commentary: ‘Not much younger | |
4754 than these is Euclid, who compiled the Elements . . .’. ‘This | |
4755 man lived in the time of the first Ptolemy . . .’. On the whole, | |
4756 therefore, it would seem probable that the body of the sum- | |
4757 mary was taken by Proclus from a compendium made by some | |
4758 writer later than Eudemus, though the earlier portion was | |
4759 based, directly or indirectly, upon notices in Eudemus's <I>History.</I> | |
4760 But the prelude with which the summary is introduced may | |
4761 well have been written, or at all events expanded, by Proclus | |
4762 himself, for it is in his manner to bring in ‘the inspired | |
4763 Aristotle’ (<G>o( daimo/nios *)aristote/lhs</G>)—as he calls him here and | |
4764 elsewhere—and the transition to the story of the Egyptian | |
4765 origin of geometry may also be his: | |
4766 <p>‘Since, then, we have to consider the beginnings of the arts | |
4767 and sciences with reference to the particular cycle [of the | |
4768 series postulated by Aristotle] through which the universe is | |
4769 at present passing, <I>we say</I> that, according to most accounts, | |
4770 geometry was first discovered in Egypt, having had its origin | |
4771 in the measurement of areas. For this was a necessity for the | |
4772 Egyptians owing to the rising of the Nile which effaced the | |
4773 proper boundaries of everybody's lands.’ | |
4774 <p>The next sentences also may well be due to Proclus: | |
4775 <p>‘And it is in no way surprising that the discovery of this as | |
4776 well as the other sciences had its beginning in practical needs, | |
4777 seeing that everything that is in the course of becoming pro- | |
4778 gresses from the imperfect to the perfect. Thus the transition | |
4779 from sensation to reasoning and from reasoning to under- | |
4780 standing is only natural.’ | |
4781 <p>These sentences look like reflections by Proclus, and the | |
4782 transition to the summary proper follows, in the words: | |
4783 <p>‘Accordingly, just as exact arithmetic began among the | |
4784 <pb n=121><head>ORIGIN OF GEOMETRY</head> | |
4785 Phoenicians owing to its use in commerce and contracts, so | |
4786 geometry was discovered in Egypt for the reason aforesaid.’ | |
4787 <C>Tradition as to the origin of geometry.</C> | |
4788 <p>Many Greek writers besides Proclus give a similar account | |
4789 of the origin of geometry. Herodotus says that Sesostris | |
4790 (Ramses II, <I>circa</I> 1300 B.C.) distributed the land among all the | |
4791 Egyptians in equal rectangular plots, on which he levied an | |
4792 annual tax; when therefore the river swept away a portion | |
4793 of a plot and the owner applied for a corresponding reduction | |
4794 in the tax, surveyors had to be sent down to certify what the | |
4795 reduction in the area had been. ‘This, in my opinion (<G>doke/ei | |
4796 moi</G>)’, he continues, ‘was the origin of geometry, which then | |
4797 passed into Greece.’<note>Herodotus ii. 109.</note> The same story, a little amplified, is | |
4798 repeated by other writers, Heron of Alexandria,<note>Heron, <I>Geom.</I> c. 2, p. 176, Heib.</note> Diodorus | |
4799 Siculus,<note>Diod. Sic. i. 69, 81.</note> and Strabo.<note>Strabo xvii. c. 3.</note> True, all these statements (even if that | |
4800 in Proclus was taken directly from Eudemus's <I>History of | |
4801 Geometry</I>) may all be founded on the passage of Herodotus, | |
4802 and Herodotus may have stated as his own inference what he | |
4803 was told in Egypt; for Diodorus gives it as an Egyptian | |
4804 tradition that geometry and astronomy were the discoveries | |
4805 of Egypt, and says that the Egyptian priests claimed Solon, | |
4806 Pythagoras, Plato, Democritus, Oenopides of Chios, and | |
4807 Eudoxus as their pupils. But the Egyptian claim to the | |
4808 discoveries was never disputed by the Greeks. In Plato's | |
4809 <I>Phaedrus</I> Socrates is made to say that he had heard that the | |
4810 Egyptian god Theuth was the first to invent arithmetic, the | |
4811 science of calculation, geometry, and astronomy.<note>Plato, <I>Phaedrus</I> 274 c.</note> Similarly | |
4812 Aristotle says that the mathematical arts first took shape in | |
4813 Egypt, though he gives as the reason, not the practical need | |
4814 which arose for a scientific method of measuring land, but the | |
4815 fact that in Egypt there was a leisured class, the priests, who | |
4816 could spare time for such things.<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> A. 1, 981 b 23.</note> Democritus boasted that no | |
4817 one of his time had excelled him ‘in making lines into figures | |
4818 and proving their properties, not even the so-called <I>Harpe- | |
4819 donaptae</I> in Egypt’.<note>Clem. <I>Strom.</I> i. 15. 69 (<I>Vorsokratiker</I>, ii<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 123. 5-7).</note> This word, compounded of two Greek | |
4820 words, <G>a(rpedo/nh</G> and <G>a(/ptein</G>, means ‘rope-stretchers’ or ‘rope- | |
4821 <pb n=122><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
4822 fasteners’; and, while it is clear from the passage that the | |
4823 persons referred to were clever geometers, the word reveals a | |
4824 characteristic <I>modus operandi.</I> The Egyptians were ex- | |
4825 tremely careful about the orientation of their temples, and | |
4826 the use of ropes and pegs for marking out the limits, | |
4827 e.g. corners, of the sacred precincts is portrayed in all | |
4828 pictures of the laying of foundation stones of temples.<note>Brugsch, <I>Steininschrift und Bibelwort</I>, 2nd ed., p. 36.</note> The | |
4829 operation of ‘rope-stretching’ is mentioned in an inscription on | |
4830 leather in the Berlin Museum as having been in use as early | |
4831 as Amenemhat I (say 2300 B.C.).<note>Dümichen, <I>Denderatempel</I>, p. 33.</note> Now it was the practice | |
4832 of ancient Indian and probably also of Chinese geometers | |
4833 to make, for instance, a right angle by stretching a rope | |
4834 divided into three lengths in the ratio of the sides of a right- | |
4835 angled triangle in rational numbers, e.g. 3, 4, 5, in such a way | |
4836 that the three portions formed a triangle, when of course a right | |
4837 angle would be formed at the point where the two smaller | |
4838 sides meet. There seems to be no doubt that the Egyptians | |
4839 knew that the triangle (3, 4, 5), the sides of which are so | |
4840 related that the square on the greatest side is equal to the | |
4841 sum of the squares on the other two, is right-angled; if this | |
4842 is so, they were acquainted with at least one case of the | |
4843 famous proposition of Pythagoras. | |
4844 <C>Egyptian geometry, i.e. mensuration.</C> | |
4845 <p>We might suppose, from Aristotle's remark about the | |
4846 Egyptian priests being the first to cultivate mathematics | |
4847 because they had leisure, that their geometry would have | |
4848 advanced beyond the purely practical stage to something | |
4849 more like a theory or science of geometry. But the docu- | |
4850 ments which have survived do not give any ground for this | |
4851 supposition; the art of geometry in the hands of the priests | |
4852 never seems to have advanced beyond mere routine. The | |
4853 most important available source of information about Egyptian | |
4854 mathematics is the Papyrus Rhind, written probably about | |
4855 1700 B.C. but copied from an original of the time of King | |
4856 Amenemhat III (Twelfth Dynasty), say 2200 B.C. The geo- | |
4857 metry in this ‘guide for calculation, a means of ascertaining | |
4858 everything, of elucidating all obscurities, all mysteries, all | |
4859 <pb n=123><head>EGYPTIAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
4860 difficulties’, as it calls itself, is rough <I>mensuration.</I> The | |
4861 following are the cases dealt with which concern us here. | |
4862 (1) There is the <I>rectangle</I>, the area of which is of course | |
4863 obtained by multiplying together the numbers representing | |
4864 the sides. (2) The measure of a <I>triangle</I> is given as the pro- | |
4865 duct of half the base into the <I>side.</I> And here there is a differ- | |
4866 ence of opinion as to the kind of triangle measured. Eisenlohr | |
4867 and Cantor, taking the diagram to represent an <I>isosceles</I> tri- | |
4868 angle rather inaccurately drawn, have to assume error on | |
4869 the part of the writer in making the area 1/2<I>ab</I> instead of | |
4870 <MATH>1/2<I>a</I>√(<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1/4<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> where <I>a</I> is the base and <I>b</I> the ‘side’, an error | |
4871 which of course becomes less serious as <I>a</I> becomes smaller | |
4872 relatively to <I>b</I> (in the case taken <I>a</I>=4, <I>b</I>=10, and the area | |
4873 as given according to the rule, i.e. 20, is not greatly different | |
4874 from the true value 19.5959). But other authorities take the | |
4875 triangle to be <I>right-angled</I> and <I>b</I> to be the side perpendicular | |
4876 to the base, their argument being that the triangle as drawn | |
4877 is not a worse representation of a right-angled triangle than | |
4878 other triangles purporting to be right-angled which are found | |
4879 in other manuscripts, and indeed is a better representation of | |
4880 a right-angled triangle than it is of an isosceles triangle, while | |
4881 the number representing the side is shown in the figure along- | |
4882 side one only of the sides, namely that adjacent to the angle | |
4883 which the more nearly represents a right angle. The advan- | |
4884 tage of this interpretation is that the rule is then correct | |
4885 instead of being more inaccurate than one would expect from | |
4886 a people who had expert land surveyors to measure land for | |
4887 the purpose of assessing it to tax. The same doubt arises | |
4888 with reference to (3) the formula for the area of a trapezium, | |
4889 namely <MATH>1/2(<I>a</I>+<I>c</I>)x<I>b</I></MATH>, where <I>a, c</I> are the base and the opposite | |
4890 parallel side respectively, while <I>b</I> is the ‘side’, i.e. one of the | |
4891 non-parallel sides. In this case the figure seems to have been | |
4892 intended to be isosceles, whereas the formula is only accurate | |
4893 if <I>b</I>, one of the non-parallel sides, is at right angles to the base, | |
4894 in which case of course the side opposite to <I>b</I> is not at right | |
4895 angles to the base. As the parallel sides (6, 4) in the case | |
4896 taken are short relatively to the ‘side’ (20), the angles at the | |
4897 base are not far short of being right angles, and it is possible | |
4898 that one of them, adjacent to the particular side which is | |
4899 marked 20, was intended to be right. The hypothesis that | |
4900 <pb n=124><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
4901 the triangles and trapezia are isosceles, and that the formulae | |
4902 are therefore crude and inaccurate, was thought to be con- | |
4903 firmed by the evidence of inscriptions on the Temple of Horus | |
4904 at Edfu. This temple was planned out in 237 B.C.; the in- | |
4905 scriptions which refer to the assignment of plots of ground to | |
4906 the priests belong to the reign of Ptolemy XI, Alexander I | |
4907 (107-88 B.C.). From so much of these inscriptions as were | |
4908 published by Lepsius<note>‘Ueber eine hieroglyphische Inschrift am Tempel von Edfu’ (<I>Abh. | |
4909 der Berliner Akad.</I>, 1855, pp. 69-114).</note> we gather that <MATH>1/2(<I>a</I>+<I>c</I>).1/2(<I>b</I>+<I>d</I>)</MATH> was a | |
4910 formula for the area of a quadrilateral the sides of which in | |
4911 order are <I>a, b, c, d.</I> Some of the quadrilateral figures are | |
4912 evidently trapezia with the non-parallel sides equal; others are | |
4913 not, although they are commonly not far from being rectangles | |
4914 or isosceles trapezia. Examples are ‘16 to 15 and 4 to 3 1/2 make | |
4915 58 1/8’ (i.e. <MATH>1/2(16+15)x1/2(4+3 1/2)=58 1/8</MATH>); ‘9 1/2 to 10 1/2 and 24 1/2 1/8 to | |
4916 22 1/2 1/8 make 236 1/4’; ‘22 to 23 and 4 to 4 make 90’, and so on. | |
4917 Triangles are not made the subject of a separate formula, but | |
4918 are regarded as cases of quadrilaterals in which the length of | |
4919 one side is zero. Thus the triangle 5, 17, 17 is described as a | |
4920 figure with sides ‘0 to 5 and 17 to 17’, the area being accord- | |
4921 ingly <MATH>1/2(0+5).1/2(17+17)</MATH> or 42 1/2; 0 is expressed by hieroglyphs | |
4922 meaning the word Nen. It is remarkable enough that the use | |
4923 of a formula so inaccurate should have lasted till 200 years or | |
4924 so after Euclid had lived and taught in Egypt; there is also | |
4925 a case of its use in the <I>Liber Geeponicus</I> formerly attributed to | |
4926 Heron,<note>Heron, ed. Hultsch, p. 212. 15-20 (Heron, <I>Geom.</I> c. 6. 2, Heib.).</note> the quadrilateral having two opposite sides parallel | |
4927 and the pairs of opposite sides being (32, 30) and (18, 16). But | |
4928 it is right to add that, in the rest of the Edfu inscriptions | |
4929 published later by Brugsch, there are cases where the inaccu- | |
4930 rate formula is not used, and it is suggested that what is being | |
4931 attempted in these cases is an approximation to the square | |
4932 root of a non-square number.<note>M. Simon, <I>Gesch. d. Math. im Altertum</I>, p. 48.</note> | |
4933 <p>We come now (4) to the mensuration of circles as found | |
4934 in the Papyrus Rhind. If <I>d</I> is the diameter, the area is | |
4935 given as <MATH><BRACE>(1-1/9)<I>d</I></BRACE><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> or 64/81<I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP>. As this is the corresponding | |
4936 figure to 1/4<G>p</G><I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP>, it follows that the value of <G>p</G> is taken as | |
4937 <MATH>256/81=(16/9)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, or 3.16, very nearly. A somewhat different | |
4938 value for <G>p</G> has been inferred from measurements of certain | |
4939 <pb n=125><head>EGYPTIAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
4940 heaps of grain or of spaces which they fill. Unfortunately | |
4941 the shape of these spaces or heaps cannot be determined with | |
4942 certainty. The word in the Papyrus Rhind is <I>shaa</I>; it is | |
4943 evident that it ordinarily means a rectangular parallelepiped, | |
4944 but it can also be applied to a figure with a circular base, | |
4945 e.g. a cylinder, or a figure resembling a thimble, i.e. with | |
4946 a rounded top. There is a measurement of a mass of corn | |
4947 apparently of the latter sort in one of the Kahu&ndot; papyri.<note>Griffith, <I>Kahu&ndot; Papyri</I>, Pt. I, Plate 8.</note> | |
4948 The figure shows a circle with 1365 1/3 as the content of the | |
4949 heap written within it, and with 12 and 8 written above and | |
4950 to the left of the circle respectively. The calculation is done | |
4951 in this way. 12 is taken and 1/3 of it added; this gives 16; | |
4952 16 is squared, which gives 256, and finally 256 is multiplied | |
4953 by 2/3 of 8, which gives 1365 1/3. If for the original figures | |
4954 12 and 8 we write <I>h</I> and <I>k</I> respectively, the formula used for | |
4955 the content is <MATH>(4/3<I>h</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>.2/3<I>k.</I></MATH> Griffith took 12 to be the height | |
4956 of the figure and 8 to be the diameter of the base. But | |
4957 according to another interpretation,<note>Simon, <I>l. c.</I></note> 12 is simply 3/2 of 8, and | |
4958 the figure to be measured is a hemisphere with diameter | |
4959 8 ells. If this is so, the formula makes the content of a | |
4960 hemisphere of diameter <I>k</I> to be <MATH>(4/3.3/2<I>k</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>.2/3<I>k</I></MATH> or 8/3<I>k</I><SUP>3</SUP>. Com- | |
4961 paring this with the true volume of the hemisphere, <MATH>2/3.1/8<G>p</G><I>k</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH> | |
4962 or <MATH>1/12<G>p</G><I>k</I><SUP>3</SUP>=134.041</MATH> cubic ells, we see that the result 1365 1/3 | |
4963 obtained by the formula must be expressed in 1/10ths of a cubic | |
4964 ell: consequently for 1/12<G>p</G> the formula substitutes 8/30, so that | |
4965 the formula gives 3.2 in place of <G>p</G>, a value different from the | |
4966 3.16 of Ahmes. Borchardt suggests that the formula for the | |
4967 measurement of a hemisphere was got by repeated practical | |
4968 measurements of heaps of corn built up as nearly as possible | |
4969 in that form, in which case the inaccuracy in the figure for <G>p</G> | |
4970 is not surprising. With this problem from the Kahu&ndot; papyri | |
4971 must be compared No. 43 from the Papyrus Rhind. A curious | |
4972 feature in the measurements of stores or heaps of corn in | |
4973 the Papyrus Rhind is the fact, not as yet satisfactorily ex- | |
4974 plained, that the area of the base (square or circular) is first | |
4975 found and is then regularly multiplied, not into the ‘height’ | |
4976 itself, but into 3/2 times the height. But in No. 43 the calcula- | |
4977 tion is different and more parallel to the case in the Kahu&ndot; | |
4978 papyrus. The problem is to find the content of a space round | |
4979 <pb n=126><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
4980 in form ‘9 in height and 6 in breadth’. The word <I>qa</I>, here | |
4981 translated ‘height’, is apparently used in other documents | |
4982 for ‘length’ or ‘greatest dimension’, and must in this case | |
4983 mean the diameter of the base, while the ‘breadth’ is the | |
4984 height in our sense. If we denote the diameter of the circular | |
4985 base by <I>k</I>, and the height by <I>h</I>, the formula used in this | |
4986 problem for finding the volume is <MATH>(4/3.8/9<I>k</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>.2/3<I>h</I></MATH>. Here it is | |
4987 not 3/2<I>h</I>, but 2/3<I>h</I>, which is taken as the last factor of the | |
4988 product. Eisenlohr suggests that the analogy of the formula | |
4989 for a hemisphere, <MATH><G>p</G><I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>.2/3<I>r</I></MATH>, may have operated to make the | |
4990 calculator take 2/3 of the height, although the height is not | |
4991 in the particular case the same as the radius of the base, but | |
4992 different. But there remains the difficulty that (4/3)<SUP>2</SUP> or 16/9 | |
4993 times the area of the circle of diameter <I>k</I> is taken instead | |
4994 of the area itself. As to this Eisenlohr can only suggest that | |
4995 the circle of diameter <I>k</I> which was accessible for measurement | |
4996 was not the real or mean circular section, and that allowance | |
4997 had to be made for this, or that the base was not a circle of | |
4998 diameter <I>k</I> but an <I>ellipse</I> with 16/9<I>k</I> and <I>k</I> as major and minor | |
4999 axes. But such explanations can hardly be applied to the | |
5000 factor (4/3)<SUP>2</SUP> in the Kahu&ndot; case <I>if</I> the latter is really the case | |
5001 of a hemispherical space as suggested. Whatever the true | |
5002 explanation may be, it is clear that these rules of measure- | |
5003 ment must have been empirical and that there was little or | |
5004 no geometry about them. | |
5005 <p>Much more important geometrically are certain calculations | |
5006 with reference to the proportions of pyramids (Nos. 56-9 of | |
5007 <FIG> | |
5008 the Papyrus Rhind) and a monu- | |
5009 ment (No. 60). In the case | |
5010 of the pyramid two lines in the | |
5011 figure are distinguished, (1) | |
5012 <I>ukha-thebt</I>, which is evidently | |
5013 some line in the base, and | |
5014 (2) <I>pir-em-us</I> or <I>per-em-us</I> | |
5015 (‘height’), a word from which | |
5016 the name <G>purami/s</G> may have | |
5017 been derived.<note>Another view is that the words <G>purami/s</G> and <G>puramou=s</G>, meaning a kind | |
5018 of cake made from roasted wheat and honey, are derived from <G>puroi/</G>, | |
5019 ‘wheat’, and are thus of purely Greek origin.</note> The object of | |
5020 <pb n=127><head>MEASUREMENT OF PYRAMIDS</head> | |
5021 the problems is to find a certain relation called <I>se-qe⃛</I>, | |
5022 literally ‘that which makes the nature’, i.e. that which | |
5023 determines the proportions of the pyramid. The relation | |
5024 <MATH><I>se-qe⃛</I>=(1/2<I>ukha-thebt</I>)/<I>piremus</I></MATH>. In the case of the monument we have | |
5025 two other names for lines in the figure, (1) <I>senti</I>, ‘foundation’, | |
5026 or base, (2) <I>qay en &hdot;eru</I>, ‘vertical length’, or height; the | |
5027 same term <I>se-qe⃛</I> is used for the relation <MATH>(1/2<I>senti</I>)/(<I>qay en &hdot;eru</I>)</MATH> or | |
5028 the same inverted. Eisenlohr and Cantor took the lines | |
5029 (1) and (2) in the case of the pyramid to be different from | |
5030 the lines (1) and (2) called by different names in the monument. | |
5031 Suppose <I>ABCD</I> to be the square base of a pyramid, <I>E</I> its | |
5032 centre, <I>H</I> the vertex, and <I>F</I> the middle point of the side <I>AD</I> | |
5033 of the base. According to Eisenlohr and Cantor the <I>ukha- | |
5034 thebt</I> is the diagonal, say <I>AC</I>, of the base, and the <I>pir-em-us</I> | |
5035 is the <I>edge</I>, as <I>AH.</I> On this assumption the <I>se-qe⃛</I> | |
5036 <MATH>=<I>AE</I>/<I>AH</I>=cos <I>HAE</I></MATH>. | |
5037 In the case of the monument they took the <I>senti</I> to be the | |
5038 side of the base, as <I>AB</I>, the <I>qay en &hdot;eru</I> to be the height of | |
5039 the pyramid <I>EH</I>, and the <I>se-qe⃛</I> to be the ratio of <I>EH</I> to | |
5040 1/2<I>AB</I> or of <I>EH</I> to <I>EF</I>, i.e. the <I>tangent</I> of the angle <I>HFE</I> | |
5041 which is the slope of the faces of the pyramid. According | |
5042 to Eisenlohr and Cantor, therefore, the one term <I>se-qe⃛</I> was | |
5043 used in two different senses, namely, in Nos. 56-9 for cos <I>HAE</I> | |
5044 and in No. 60 for tan <I>HFE.</I> Borchardt has, however, proved | |
5045 that the <I>se-qe⃛</I> in all the cases has one meaning, and represents | |
5046 the <I>cotangent</I> of the slope of the faces of the pyramid, | |
5047 i. e. cot <I>HFE</I> or the ratio of <I>FE</I> to <I>EH.</I> There is no difficulty | |
5048 in the use of the different words <I>ukha-thebt</I> and <I>senti</I> to | |
5049 express the same thing, namely, the side of the base, and | |
5050 of the different words <I>per-em-us</I> and <I>qay en &hdot;eru</I> in the same | |
5051 sense of ‘height’; such synonyms are common in Egypt, and, | |
5052 moreover, the word <I>mer</I> used of the pyramids is different | |
5053 from the word <I>&adot;n</I> for the monument. Again, it is clear that, | |
5054 while the <I>slope</I>, the angle <I>HFE</I>, is what the builder would | |
5055 want to know, the cosine of the angle <I>HAE</I>, formed by the | |
5056 <I>edge</I> with the plane of the base, would be of no direct use | |
5057 <pb n=128><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
5058 to him. But, lastly, the <I>se-qe⃛</I> in No. 56 is 18/25 and, if <I>se-qe⃛</I> | |
5059 is taken in the sense of cot <I>HFE</I>, this gives for the angle | |
5060 <I>HFE</I> the value of 54°14′16″, which is <I>precisely</I>, to the | |
5061 seconds, the slope of the lower half of the southern stone | |
5062 pyramid of Dakshūr; in Nos. 57-9 the <I>se-qe⃛</I>, 3/4, is the co- | |
5063 tangent of an angle of 53°7′48″, which again is exactly the | |
5064 slope of the second pyramid of Gizeh as measured by Flinders | |
5065 Petrie; and the <I>se-qe⃛</I> in No. 60, which is 1/4, is the cotangent | |
5066 of an angle of 75°57′50″, corresponding exactly to the slope | |
5067 of the Mastaba-tombs of the Ancient Empire and of the | |
5068 sides of the Mēdūm pyramid.<note>Flinders Petrie, <I>Pyramids and Temples of Gizeh</I>, p. 162.</note> | |
5069 <p>These measurements of <I>se-qe⃛</I> indicate at all events a rule- | |
5070 of-thumb use of geometrical proportion, and connect themselves | |
5071 naturally enough with the story of Thales's method of measuring | |
5072 the heights of pyramids. | |
5073 <C>The beginnings of Greek geometry.</C> | |
5074 <p>At the beginning of the summary of Proclus we are told | |
5075 that THALES (624-547 B. C.) | |
5076 ‘first went to Egypt and thence introduced this study | |
5077 (geometry) into Greece. He discovered many propositions | |
5078 himself, and instructed his successors in the principles under- | |
5079 lying many others, his method of attack being in some cases | |
5080 more general (i. e. more theoretical or scientific), in others | |
5081 more empirical (<G>ai)sqhtikw/teron</G>, more in the nature of simple | |
5082 inspection or observation).’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 65. 7-11.</note> | |
5083 <p>With Thales, therefore, geometry first becomes a deductive | |
5084 science depending on general propositions; this agrees with | |
5085 what Plutarch says of him as one of the Seven Wise Men: | |
5086 <p>‘he was apparently the only one of these whose wisdom | |
5087 stepped, in speculation, beyond the limits of practical utility: | |
5088 the rest acquired the reputation of wisdom in politics.’<note>Plutarch, <I>Solon</I>, c. 3.</note> | |
5089 <p>(Not that Thales was inferior to the others in political | |
5090 wisdom. Two stories illustrate the contrary. He tried to | |
5091 save Ionia by urging the separate states to form a federation | |
5092 <pb n=129><head>MEASUREMENT OF PYRAMIDS</head> | |
5093 with a capital at Teos, that being the most central place in | |
5094 Ionia. And when Croesus sent envoys to Miletus to propose | |
5095 an alliance, Thales dissuaded his fellow-citizens from accepting | |
5096 the proposal, with the result that, when Cyrus conquered, the | |
5097 city was saved.) | |
5098 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Measurement of height of pyramid.</I></C> | |
5099 <p>The accounts of Thales's method of measuring the heights | |
5100 of pyramids vary. The earliest and simplest version is that | |
5101 of Hieronymus, a pupil of Aristotle, quoted by Diogenes | |
5102 Laertius: | |
5103 <p>‘Hieronymus says that he even succeeded in measuring the | |
5104 pyramids by observation of the length of their shadow at | |
5105 the moment when our shadows are equal to our own height.’<note>Diog. L. i. 27.</note> | |
5106 <p>Pliny says that | |
5107 <p>‘Thales discovered how to obtain the height of pyramids | |
5108 and all other similar objects, namely, by measuring the | |
5109 shadow of the object at the time when a body and its shadow | |
5110 are equal in length.’<note><I>N. H.</I> xxxvi. 12 (17).</note> | |
5111 <p>Plutarch embellishes the story by making Niloxenus say | |
5112 to Thales: | |
5113 <p>‘Among other feats of yours, he (Amasis) was particularly | |
5114 pleased with your measurement of the pyramid, when, without | |
5115 trouble or the assistance of any instrument, you merely set | |
5116 up a stick at the extremity of the shadow cast by the | |
5117 pyramid and, having thus made two triangles by the impact | |
5118 of the sun's rays, you showed that the pyramid has to the | |
5119 stick the same ratio which the shadow has to the shadow.’<note>Plut. <I>Conv. sept. sap.</I> 2, p. 147 A.</note> | |
5120 <p>The first of these versions is evidently the original one and, | |
5121 as the procedure assumed in it is more elementary than the | |
5122 more general method indicated by Plutarch, the first version | |
5123 seems to be the more probable. Thales could not have failed | |
5124 to observe that, at the time when the shadow of a particular | |
5125 object is equal to its height, the same relation holds for all | |
5126 other objects casting a shadow; this he would probably | |
5127 infer by induction, after making actual measurements in a | |
5128 <pb n=130><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
5129 considerable number of cases at a time when he found the | |
5130 length of the shadow of one object to be equal to its height. | |
5131 But, even if Thales used the more general method indicated | |
5132 by Plutarch, that method does not, any more than the Egyptian | |
5133 <I>se-qet</I> calculations, imply any general theory of similar tri- | |
5134 angles or proportions; the solution is itself a <I>se-qe⃛</I> calculation, | |
5135 just like that in No. 57 of Ahmes's handbook. In the latter | |
5136 problem the base and the <I>se-qe⃛</I> are given, and we have to | |
5137 find the height. So in Thales's problem we get a certain | |
5138 <I>se-qe⃛</I> by dividing the measured length of the shadow of the | |
5139 stick by the length of the stick itself; we then only require | |
5140 to know the distance between the point of the shadow corre- | |
5141 sponding to the apex of the pyramid and the centre of the | |
5142 base of the pyramid in order to determine the height; the | |
5143 only difficulty would be to measure or estimate the distance | |
5144 from the apex of the shadow to the centre of the base. | |
5145 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>Geometrical theorems attributed to Thales.</I></C> | |
5146 <p>The following are the general theorems in elementary | |
5147 geometry attributed to Thales. | |
5148 <p>(1) He is said to have been the first to demonstrate that | |
5149 a circle is bisected by its diameter.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 157. 10.</note> | |
5150 <p>(2) Tradition credited him with the first statement of the | |
5151 theorem (Eucl. I. 5) that the angles at the base of any | |
5152 isosceles triangle are equal, although he used the more archaic | |
5153 term ‘similar’ instead of ‘equal’.<note><I>Ib.</I>, pp. 250. 20-251. 2.</note> | |
5154 <p>(3) The proposition (Eucl. I. 15) that, if two straight lines | |
5155 cut one another, the vertical and opposite angles are equal | |
5156 was discovered, though not scientifically proved, by Thales. | |
5157 Eudemus is quoted as the authority for this.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 299. 1-5.</note> | |
5158 <p>(4) Eudemus in his History of Geometry referred to Thales | |
5159 the theorem of Eucl. I. 26 that, if two triangles have two | |
5160 angles and one side respectively equal, the triangles are equal | |
5161 in all respects. | |
5162 <p>‘For he (Eudemus) says that the method by which Thales | |
5163 showed how to find the distances of ships from the shore | |
5164 necessarily involves the use of this theorem.’<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 352. 14-18.</note> | |
5165 <pb n=131><head>GEOMETRICAL THEOREMS</head> | |
5166 <p>(5) ‘Pamphile says that Thales, who learnt geometry from | |
5167 the Egyptians, was the first to describe on a circle a triangle | |
5168 (which shall be) right-angled (<G>katagra/yai ku/klou to\ tri/gwnon | |
5169 o)rqogw/nion</G>), and that he sacrificed an ox (on the strength of | |
5170 the discovery). Others, however, including Apollodorus the | |
5171 calculator, say that it was Pythagoras.’<note>Diog. L. i. 24, 25.</note> | |
5172 <p>The natural interpretation of Pamphile's words is to suppose | |
5173 that she attributed to Thales the discovery that the angle | |
5174 in a semicircle is a right angle. | |
5175 <p>Taking these propositions in order, we may observe that, | |
5176 when Thales is said to have ‘demonstrated’ (<G>a)podei=xai</G>) that | |
5177 a circle is bisected by its diameter, whereas he only ‘stated’ | |
5178 the theorem about the isosceles triangle and ‘discovered’, | |
5179 without scientifically proving, the equality of vertically | |
5180 opposite angles, the word ‘demonstrated’ must not be taken | |
5181 too literally. Even Euclid did not ‘demonstrate’ that a circle | |
5182 is bisected by its diameter, but merely stated the fact in | |
5183 <FIG> | |
5184 I. Def. 17. Thales therefore probably | |
5185 observed rather than proved the property; | |
5186 and it may, as Cantor says, have been | |
5187 suggested by the appearance of certain | |
5188 figures of circles divided into a number | |
5189 of equal sectors by 2, 4, or 6 diameters | |
5190 such as are found on Egyptian monu- | |
5191 ments or represented on vessels brought | |
5192 by Asiatic tributary kings in the time of the eighteenth | |
5193 dynasty.<note>Cantor, <I>Gesch. d. Math.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, pp. 109, 140.</note> | |
5194 <p>It has been suggested that the use of the word ‘similar’ to | |
5195 describe the equal angles of an isosceles triangle indicates that | |
5196 Thales did not yet conceive of an angle as a magnitude, but | |
5197 as a <I>figure</I> having a certain <I>shape</I>, a view which would agree | |
5198 closely with the idea of the Egyptian <I>se-qe⃛</I>, ‘that which | |
5199 makes the nature’, in the sense of determining a similar or | |
5200 the same inclination in the faces of pyramids. | |
5201 <p>With regard to (4), the theorem of Eucl. I. 26, it will be | |
5202 observed that Eudemus only inferred that this theorem was | |
5203 known to Thales from the fact that it is necessary to Thales's | |
5204 determination of the distance of a ship from the shore. | |
5205 Unfortunately the method used can only be conjectured. | |
5206 <pb n=132><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
5207 The most usual supposition is that Thales, observing the ship | |
5208 from the top of a tower on the sea-shore, used the practical | |
5209 equivalent of the proportionality of the sides of two similar | |
5210 right-angled triangles, one small and one large. Suppose <I>B</I> | |
5211 to be the base of the tower, <I>C</I> the ship. It was only necessary | |
5212 <FIG> | |
5213 for a man standing at the top of the | |
5214 tower to have an instrument with | |
5215 two legs forming a right angle, to | |
5216 place it with one leg <I>DA</I> vertical and | |
5217 in a straight line with <I>B</I>, and the | |
5218 other leg <I>DE</I> in the direction of the | |
5219 ship, to take any point <I>A</I> on <I>DA</I>, | |
5220 and then to mark on <I>DE</I> the point <I>E</I> | |
5221 where the line of sight from <I>A</I> to <I>C</I> cuts the leg <I>DE.</I> Then | |
5222 <I>AD</I> (=<I>l</I>, say) and <I>DE</I> (=<I>m</I>, say) can be actually measured, | |
5223 as also the height <I>BD</I> (= <I>h</I>, say) from <I>D</I> to the foot of the | |
5224 tower, and, by similar triangles, | |
5225 <MATH><I>BC</I>=(<I>h</I>+<I>l</I>).<I>m</I>/<I>l</I></MATH>. | |
5226 The objection to this solution is that it does not depend | |
5227 directly on Eucl. I. 26, as Eudemus implies. Tannery<note>Tannery, <I>La géométrie grecque</I>, pp. 90-1.</note> there- | |
5228 fore favours the hypothesis of a solution on the lines followed | |
5229 by the Roman agrimensor Marcus Junius Nipsus in his | |
5230 <FIG> | |
5231 <I>fluminis varatio.</I>—To find the distance from | |
5232 <I>A</I> to an inaccessible point <I>B.</I> Measure from <I>A</I>, | |
5233 along a straight line at right angles to <I>AB</I>, | |
5234 a distance <I>AC</I>, and bisect it at <I>D.</I> From <I>C</I>, on | |
5235 the side of <I>AC</I> remote from <I>B</I>, draw <I>CE</I> at | |
5236 right angles to <I>AC</I>, and let <I>E</I> be the point on | |
5237 it which is in a straight line with <I>B</I> and <I>D.</I> | |
5238 Then clearly, by Eucl. I. 26, <I>CE</I> is equal to | |
5239 <I>AB</I>; and <I>CE</I> can be measured, so that <I>AB</I> | |
5240 is known. | |
5241 <p>This hypothesis is open to a different objec- | |
5242 tion, namely that, as a rule, it would be | |
5243 difficult, in the supposed case, to get a sufficient amount of | |
5244 free and level space for the construction and measurements. | |
5245 <p>I have elsewhere<note><I>The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements</I>, vol. i, p. 305.</note> suggested a still simpler method free | |
5246 <pb n=133><head>DISTANCE OF A SHIP AT SEA</head> | |
5247 from this objection, and depending equally directly on Eucl. | |
5248 I. 26. If the observer was placed on the top of a tower, he | |
5249 had only to use a rough instrument made of a straight stick | |
5250 and a cross-piece fastened to it so as to be capable of turning | |
5251 about the fastening (say a nail) so that it could form any | |
5252 angle with the stick and would remain where it was put. | |
5253 Then the natural thing would be to fix the stick upright (by | |
5254 means of a plumb-line) and direct the cross-piece towards the | |
5255 ship. Next, leaving the cross-piece at the angle so found, | |
5256 he would turn the stick round, while keeping it vertical, until | |
5257 the cross-piece pointed to some visible object on the shore, | |
5258 which would be mentally noted; after this it would only | |
5259 be necessary to measure the distance of the object from the | |
5260 foot of the tower, which distance would, by Eucl. I. 26, be | |
5261 equal to the distance of the ship. It appears that this precise | |
5262 method is found in so many practical geometries of the first | |
5263 century of printing that it must be assumed to have long | |
5264 been a common expedient. There is a story that one of | |
5265 Napoleon's engineers won the Imperial favour by quickly | |
5266 measuring, in precisely this way, the width of a stream that | |
5267 blocked the progress of the army.<note>David Eugene Smith, <I>The Teaching of Geometry</I>, pp. 172-3.</note> | |
5268 <p>There is even more difficulty about the dictum of Pamphile | |
5269 implying that Thales first discovered the fact that the angle | |
5270 in a semicircle is a right angle. Pamphile lived in the reign | |
5271 of Nero (A. D. 54-68), and is therefore a late authority. The | |
5272 date of Apollodorus the ‘calculator’ or arithmetician is not | |
5273 known, but he is given as only one of several authorities who | |
5274 attributed the proposition to Pythagoras. Again, the story | |
5275 of the sacrifice of an ox by Thales on the occasion of his | |
5276 discovery is suspiciously like that told in the distich of | |
5277 Apollodorus ‘when Pythagoras discovered that famous pro- | |
5278 position, on the strength of which he offered a splendid | |
5279 sacrifice of oxen’. But, in quoting the distich of Apollodorus, | |
5280 Plutarch expresses doubt whether the discovery so celebrated | |
5281 was that of the theorem of the square of the hypotenuse or | |
5282 the solution of the problem of ‘application of areas’<note>Plutarch, <I>Non posse suaviter vivi secundum Epicurum</I>, c. 11, p. 1094 B.</note>; there | |
5283 is nothing about the discovery of the fact of the angle in | |
5284 a semicircle being a right angle. It may therefore be that | |
5285 <pb n=134><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
5286 Diogenes Laertius was mistaken in bringing Apollodorus into | |
5287 the story now in question at all; the mere mention of the | |
5288 sacrifice in Pamphile's account would naturally recall Apollo- | |
5289 dorus's lines about Pythagoras, and Diogenes may have | |
5290 forgotten that they referred to a different proposition. | |
5291 <p>But, even if the story of Pamphile is accepted, there are | |
5292 difficulties of substance. As Allman pointed out, if Thales | |
5293 <FIG> | |
5294 knew that the angle in a semicircle | |
5295 is a right angle, he was in a position | |
5296 at once to infer that the sum of the | |
5297 angles of any <I>right-angled</I> triangle is | |
5298 equal to two right angles. For suppose | |
5299 that <I>BC</I> is the diameter of the semi- | |
5300 circle, <I>O</I> the centre, and <I>A</I> a point on | |
5301 the semicircle; we are then supposed | |
5302 to know that the angle <I>BAC</I> is a right angle. Joining <I>OA</I>, | |
5303 we form two isosceles triangles <I>OAB, OAC</I>; and Thales | |
5304 knows that the base angles in each of these triangles are | |
5305 equal. Consequently the sum of the angles <I>OAB, OAC</I> is | |
5306 equal to the sum of the angles <I>OBA, OCA.</I> The former sum | |
5307 is known to be a right angle; therefore the second sum is | |
5308 also a right angle, and the three angles of the triangle <I>ABC</I> | |
5309 are together equal to twice the said sum, i.e. to two right | |
5310 angles. | |
5311 <p>Next it would easily be seen that <I>any</I> triangle can be | |
5312 divided into two right-angled triangles by drawing a perpen- | |
5313 <FIG> | |
5314 dicular <I>AD</I> from a vertex <I>A</I> to the | |
5315 opposite side <I>BC.</I> Then the three | |
5316 angles of each of the right-angled | |
5317 triangles <I>ABD, ADC</I> are together equal | |
5318 to two right angles. By adding together | |
5319 the three angles of both triangles we | |
5320 find that the sum of the three angles of the triangle <I>ABC</I> | |
5321 together with the angles <I>ADB, ADC</I> is equal to four right | |
5322 angles; and, the sum of the latter two angles being two | |
5323 right angles, it follows that the sum of the remaining angles, | |
5324 the angles at <I>A, B, C</I>, is equal to two right angles. And <I>ABC</I> | |
5325 is <I>any</I> triangle. | |
5326 <p>Now Euclid in III. 31 proves that the angle in a semicircle | |
5327 is a right angle by means of the general theorem of I. 32 | |
5328 <pb n=135><head>THE ANGLE IN A SEMICIRCLE</head> | |
5329 that the sum of the angles of any triangle is equal to two | |
5330 right angles; but if Thales was aware of the truth of the | |
5331 latter general proposition and proved the proposition about | |
5332 the semicircle in this way, by means of it, how did Eudemus | |
5333 come to credit the Pythagoreans, not only with the general | |
5334 proof, but with the <I>discovery</I>, of the theorem that the angles | |
5335 of any triangle are together equal to two right angles?<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 379. 2-5.</note> | |
5336 <p>Cantor, who supposes that Thales proved his proposition | |
5337 after the manner of Euclid III. 31, i.e. by means of the general | |
5338 theorem of I. 32, suggests that Thales arrived at the truth of | |
5339 the latter, not by a general proof like that attributed by | |
5340 Eudemus to the Pythagoreans, but by an argument following | |
5341 the steps indicated by Geminus. Geminus says that | |
5342 <p>‘the <I>ancients</I> investigated the theorem of the two right | |
5343 angles in each individual species of triangle, first in the equi- | |
5344 lateral, then in the isosceles, and afterwards in the scalene | |
5345 triangle, but later geometers demonstrated the general theorem | |
5346 that in <I>any</I> triangle the three interior angles are equal to two | |
5347 right angles’.<note>See Eutocius, Comm. on <I>Conics</I> of Apollonius (vol. ii, p. 170, Heib.).</note> | |
5348 <p>The ‘later geometers’ being the Pythagoreans, it is assumed | |
5349 that the ‘ancients’ may be Thales and his contemporaries. | |
5350 As regards the equilateral triangle, the fact might be suggested | |
5351 by the observation that six such triangles arranged round one | |
5352 point as common vertex would fill up the space round that | |
5353 point; whence it follows that each angle is one-sixth of four | |
5354 right angles, and three such angles make up two right angles. | |
5355 Again, suppose that in either an equilateral or an isosceles | |
5356 <FIG> | |
5357 triangle the vertical angle is bisected by a straight line meet- | |
5358 ing the base, and that the rectangle of which the bisector and | |
5359 one half of the base are adjacent sides is completed; the | |
5360 rectangle is double of the half of the original triangle, and the | |
5361 angles of the half-triangle are together equal to half the sum | |
5362 <pb n=136><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
5363 of the angles of the rectangle, i.e. are equal to two right | |
5364 angles; and it immediately follows that the sum of the angles | |
5365 of the original equilateral or isosceles triangle is equal to two | |
5366 right angles. The same thing is easily proved of any triangle | |
5367 <FIG> | |
5368 by dividing it into two right-angled | |
5369 triangles and completing the rectangles | |
5370 which are their doubles respectively, as | |
5371 in the figure. But the fact that a proof | |
5372 on these lines is just as easy in the case | |
5373 of the general triangle as it is for the | |
5374 equilateral and isosceles triangles throws doubt on the whole | |
5375 procedure; and we are led to question whether there is any | |
5376 foundation for Geminus's account at all. Aristotle has a re- | |
5377 mark that | |
5378 <p>‘even if one should prove, with reference to each (sort of) | |
5379 triangle, the equilateral, scalene, and isosceles, separately, that | |
5380 each has its angles equal to two right angles, either by one | |
5381 proof or by different proofs, he does not yet know that <I>the | |
5382 triangle</I>, i.e. the triangle <I>in general</I>, has its angles equal to | |
5383 two right angles, except in a sophistical sense, even though | |
5384 there exists no triangle other than triangles of the kinds | |
5385 mentioned. For he knows it not <I>quâ</I> triangle, nor of <I>every</I> | |
5386 triangle, except in a numerical sense; he does not know it | |
5387 <I>notionally</I> of every triangle, even though there be actually no | |
5388 triangle which he does not know’.<note>Arist. <I>Anal. Post.</I> i. 5, 74 a 25 sq.</note> | |
5389 <p>It may well be that Geminus was misled into taking for | |
5390 a historical fact what Aristotle gives only as a hypothetical | |
5391 illustration, and that the exact stages by which the proposi- | |
5392 tion was first proved were not those indicated by Geminus. | |
5393 <p>Could Thales have arrived at his proposition about the | |
5394 semicircle without assuming, or even knowing, that the sum | |
5395 of the angles of <I>any</I> triangle is equal to two right angles? It | |
5396 <FIG> | |
5397 seems possible, and in the following way. | |
5398 Many propositions were doubtless first | |
5399 discovered by drawing all sorts of figures | |
5400 and lines in them, and observing <I>apparent</I> | |
5401 relations of equality, &c., between parts. | |
5402 It would, for example, be very natural | |
5403 to draw a rectangle, a figure with four right angles (which, it | |
5404 <pb n=137><head>THE ANGLE IN A SEMICIRCLE</head> | |
5405 would be found, could be drawn in practice), and to put in the | |
5406 two diagonals. The equality of the opposite sides would | |
5407 doubtless, in the first beginnings of geometry, be assumed as | |
5408 obvious, or verified by measurement. If then it was <I>assumed</I> | |
5409 that a rectangle is a figure with all its angles right angles and | |
5410 each side equal to its opposite, it would be easy to deduce | |
5411 certain consequences. Take first the two triangles <I>ADC, BCD.</I> | |
5412 Since by hypothesis <I>AD</I>=<I>BC</I> and <I>CD</I> is common, the two | |
5413 triangles have the sides <I>AD, DC</I> respectively equal to the sides | |
5414 <I>BC, CD</I>, and the included angles, being right angles, are equal; | |
5415 therefore the triangles <I>ADC, BCD</I> are equal in all respects | |
5416 (cf. Eucl. I. 4), and accordingly the angles <I>ACD</I> (i.e. <I>OCD</I>) and | |
5417 <I>BDC</I> (i.e. <I>ODC</I>) are equal, whence (by the converse of Eucl. I. 5, | |
5418 known to Thales) <I>OD</I>=<I>OC.</I> Similarly by means of the | |
5419 equality of <I>AB, CD</I> we prove the equality of <I>OB, OC.</I> Conse- | |
5420 quently <I>OB, OC, OD</I> (and <I>OA</I>) are all equal. It follows that | |
5421 a circle with centre <I>O</I> and radius <I>OA</I> passes through <I>B, C, D</I> | |
5422 also; since <I>AO, OC</I> are in a straight line, <I>AC</I> is a diameter of | |
5423 the circle, and the angle <I>ABC</I>, by hypothesis a right angle, is | |
5424 an ‘angle in a semicircle’. It would then appear that, given | |
5425 any right angle as <I>ABC</I> standing on <I>AC</I> as base, it was only | |
5426 necessary to bisect <I>AC</I> at <I>O</I>, and <I>O</I> would then be the centre of | |
5427 a semicircle on <I>AC</I> as diameter and passing through <I>B.</I> The | |
5428 construction indicated would be the construction of a circle | |
5429 about the right-angled triangle <I>ABC</I>, which seems to corre- | |
5430 spond well enough to Pamphile's phrase about ‘describing on | |
5431 (i.e. in) a circle a triangle (which shall be) right angled’. | |
5432 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Thales as astronomer.</I></C> | |
5433 <p>Thales was also the first Greek astronomer. Every one | |
5434 knows the story of his falling into a well when star-gazing, | |
5435 and being rallied by ‘a clever and pretty maidservant from | |
5436 Thrace’ for being so eager to know what goes on in the | |
5437 heavens that he could not see what was straight in front | |
5438 of him, nay, at his very feet. But he was not merely a star- | |
5439 gazer. There is good evidence that he predicted a solar eclipse | |
5440 which took place on May 28, 585 B. C. We can conjecture | |
5441 the basis of this prediction. The Babylonians, as the result | |
5442 of observations continued through centuries, had discovered | |
5443 the period of 223 lunations after which eclipses recur; and | |
5444 <pb n=138><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
5445 this period was doubtless known to Thales, either directly or | |
5446 through the Egyptians as intermediaries. Thales, however, | |
5447 cannot have known the <I>cause</I> of eclipses; he could not have | |
5448 given the true explanation of <I>lunar</I> eclipses (as the <I>Doxo- | |
5449 graphi</I> say he did) because he held that the earth is a circular | |
5450 disc floating on the water like a log; and, if he had correctly | |
5451 accounted for <I>solar</I> eclipses, it is impossible that all the | |
5452 succeeding Ionian philosophers should, one after another, have | |
5453 put forward the fanciful explanations which we find recorded. | |
5454 <p>Thales's other achievements in astronomy can be very | |
5455 shortly stated. Eudemus attributed to him the discovery of | |
5456 ‘the fact that the period of the sun with reference to the | |
5457 solstices is not always the same’<note>See Theon of Smyrna, p. 198. 17.</note>; the vague phrase seems | |
5458 to mean that he discovered the inequality of the length of | |
5459 the four astronomical seasons, that is, the four parts of the | |
5460 ‘tropical’ year as divided by the solstices and equinoxes. | |
5461 Eudemus presumably referred to the written works by Thales | |
5462 <I>On the Solstice</I> and <I>On the Equinoxes</I> mentioned by Diogenes | |
5463 Laertius.<note>Diog. L. i. 23.</note> He knew of the division of the year into 365 days, | |
5464 which he probably learnt from Egypt. | |
5465 <p>Thales observed of the Hyades that there were two of | |
5466 them, one north and the other south. He used the Little | |
5467 Bear as a means of finding the pole, and advised the Greeks | |
5468 to sail by the Little Bear, as the Phoenicians did, in preference | |
5469 to their own practice of sailing by the Great Bear. This | |
5470 instruction was probably noted in the handbook under the | |
5471 title of <I>Nautical Astronomy</I>, attributed by some to Thales | |
5472 and by others to Phocus of Samos. | |
5473 <p>It became the habit of the <I>Doxographi</I> to assign to Thales, | |
5474 in common with other astronomers in each case, a number | |
5475 of discoveries not made till later. The following is the list, | |
5476 with the names of the astronomers to whom the respective | |
5477 discoveries may with most certainty be attributed: (1) the | |
5478 fact that the moon takes its light from the sun (Anaxagoras | |
5479 and possibly Parmenides); (2) the sphericity of the earth | |
5480 (Pythagoras); (3) the division of the heavenly sphere into | |
5481 five zones (Pythagoras and Parmenides); (4) the obliquity | |
5482 of the ecliptic (Oenopides of Chios); (5) the estimate of the | |
5483 <pb n=139><head>THALES AS ASTRONOMER</head> | |
5484 sun's diameter as 1/720th part of the sun's circle (Aristarchus | |
5485 of Samos). | |
5486 <C>From Thales to Pythagoras.</C> | |
5487 <p>We are completely in the dark as to the progress of geometry | |
5488 between the times of Thales and Pythagoras. ANAXIMANDER | |
5489 (born about 611/10 B.C.) put forward some daring and original | |
5490 hypotheses in astronomy. According to him the earth is | |
5491 a short cylinder with two bases (on one of which we live) and | |
5492 of depth equal to one-third of the diameter of either base. | |
5493 It is suspended freely in the middle of the universe without | |
5494 support, being kept there in equilibrium by virtue of its | |
5495 equidistance from the extremities and from the other heavenly | |
5496 bodies all round. The sun, moon, and stars are enclosed in | |
5497 opaque rings of compressed air concentric with the earth and | |
5498 filled with fire; what we see is the fire shining through vents | |
5499 (like gas-jets, as it were). The sun's ring is 27 or 28 times, the | |
5500 moon's ring 19 times, as large as the earth, i.e. the sun's | |
5501 and moon's distances are estimated in terms (as we may | |
5502 suppose) of the radius of the circular face of the earth; the | |
5503 fixed stars and the planets are nearer to the earth than | |
5504 the sun and moon. This is the first speculation on record | |
5505 about sizes and distances. Anaximander is also said to have | |
5506 introduced the <I>gnomon</I> (or sun-dial with a vertical needle) | |
5507 into Greece and to have shown on it the solstices, the times, | |
5508 the seasons, and the equinox<note>Euseb. <I>Praep. Evang.</I> x. 14. 11 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 14. 28).</note> (according to Herodotus<note>Hdt. ii. 109.</note> the | |
5509 Greeks learnt the use of the <I>gnomon</I> from the Babylonians). | |
5510 He is also credited, like Thales before him, with having | |
5511 constructed a sphere to represent the heavens.<note>Diog. L. ii. 2.</note> But Anaxi- | |
5512 mander has yet another claim to undying fame. He was the | |
5513 first who ventured to draw a map of the inhabited earth. | |
5514 The Egyptians had drawn maps before, but only of particular | |
5515 districts; Anaximander boldly planned out the whole world | |
5516 with ‘the circumference of the earth and sea’.<note>Diog. L. <I>l. c.</I></note> This work | |
5517 involved of course an attempt to estimate the dimensions of | |
5518 the earth, though we have no information as to his results. | |
5519 It is clear, therefore, that Anaximander was something of | |
5520 <pb n=140><head>THE EARLIEST GREEK GEOMETRY. THALES</head> | |
5521 a mathematician; but whether he contributed anything to | |
5522 geometry as such is uncertain. True, Suidas says that he | |
5523 ‘introduced the gnomon and generally set forth a sketch | |
5524 or outline of geometry’ (<G>o(/lws gewmetri/as u(potu/pwsin e)/deixen</G>); | |
5525 but it may be that ‘geometry’ is here used in its literal sense | |
5526 of earth-measurement, and that the reference is only to the | |
5527 famous map. | |
5528 <p>‘Next to Thales, Ameristus, a brother of the poet Stesichorus, | |
5529 is mentioned as having engaged in the study of geometry; | |
5530 and from what Hippias of Elis says it appears that he acquired | |
5531 a reputation for geometry.’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 65. 11-15.</note> | |
5532 <p>Stesichorus the poet lived about 630-550 B.C. The brother | |
5533 therefore would probably be nearly contemporary with Thales. | |
5534 We know nothing of him except from the passage of Proclus, | |
5535 and even his name is uncertain. In Friedlein's edition of | |
5536 Proclus it is given as Mamercus, after a later hand in cod. | |
5537 Monac. 427; Suidas has it as Mamertinus (<I>s.v.</I> Stesichorus); | |
5538 Heiberg in his edition of Heron's <I>Definitions</I> writes Mamertius, | |
5539 noting <G>*marme/tios</G> as the reading of Cod. Paris. Gr. 2385. | |
5540 <pb> | |
5541 <C>V</C> | |
5542 <C>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</C> | |
5543 <p>The special service rendered by PYTHAGORAS to geometry is | |
5544 thus described in the Proclus summary: | |
5545 <p>‘After these (Thales and Ameristus or Mamercus) Pythagoras | |
5546 transformed the study of geometry into a liberal education, | |
5547 examining the principles of the science from the beginning | |
5548 and probing the theorems in an immaterial and intellectual | |
5549 manner: he it was who discovered the theory of irrationals’ | |
5550 (or ‘proportions’) ‘and the construction of the cosmic figures’.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 65. 15-21.</note> | |
5551 <p>These supposed discoveries will claim our attention pre- | |
5552 sently; the rest of the description agrees with another | |
5553 passage about the Pythagoreans: | |
5554 <p>‘Herein’, says Proclus, ‘I emulate the Pythagoreans who | |
5555 even had a conventional phrase to express what I mean, | |
5556 “a figure and a platform, not a figure and sixpence”, by | |
5557 which they implied that the geometry which is deserving of | |
5558 study is that which, at each new theorem, sets up a platform to | |
5559 ascend by, and lifts the soul on high instead of allowing it | |
5560 to go down among sensible objects and so become subser- | |
5561 vient to the common needs of this mortal life’.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 84. 15-22.</note> | |
5562 <p>In like manner we are told that ‘Pythagoras used defini- | |
5563 tions on account of the mathematical nature of the subject’,<note>Favorinus in Diog. L. viii. 25.</note> | |
5564 which again implies that he took the first steps towards the | |
5565 systematization of geometry as a subject in itself. | |
5566 <p>A comparatively early authority, Callimachus (about 250 B.C.), | |
5567 is quoted by Diodorus as having said that Pythagoras dis- | |
5568 covered some geometrical problems himself and was the first | |
5569 to introduce others from Egypt into Greece.<note>Diodorus x. 6. 4 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 346. 23).</note> Diodorus gives | |
5570 what appear to be five verses of Callimachus <I>minus</I> a few words; | |
5571 <pb n=142><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
5572 a longer fragment including the same passage is now available | |
5573 (though the text is still deficient) in the Oxyrhynchus Papyri.<note><I>Oxyrhynchus Papyri</I>, Pt. vii, p. 33 (Hunt).</note> | |
5574 The story is that one Bathycles, an Arcadian, bequeathed a | |
5575 cup to be given to the best of the Seven Wise Men. The cup | |
5576 first went to Thales, and then, after going the round of the | |
5577 others, was given to him a second time. We are told that | |
5578 Bathycles's son brought the cup to Thales, and that (presum- | |
5579 ably on the occasion of the first presentation) | |
5580 <p>‘by a happy chance he found . . . the old man scraping the | |
5581 ground and drawing the figure discovered by the Phrygian | |
5582 Euphorbus (= Pythagoras), who was the first of men to draw | |
5583 even scalene triangles and a circle . . ., and who prescribed | |
5584 abstinence from animal food’. | |
5585 <p>Notwithstanding the anachronism, the ‘figure discovered by | |
5586 Euphorbus’ is presumably the famous proposition about the | |
5587 squares on the sides of a right-angled triangle. In Diodorus's | |
5588 quotation the words after ‘scalene triangles’ are <G>ku/klon e(pta- | |
5589 mh/kh</G>(<G>e(ptamh/ke</G>’ Hunt), which seems unintelligible unless the | |
5590 ‘seven-lengthed circle’ can be taken as meaning the ‘lengths of | |
5591 seven circles’ (in the sense of the seven independent orbits | |
5592 of the sun, moon, and planets) or the circle (the zodiac) com- | |
5593 prehending them all.<note>The papyrus has an accent over the <G>e</G> and to the right of the | |
5594 accent, above the uncertain <G>p</G>, the appearance of a <G>l</G> in dark ink, | |
5595 <G>l</G> | |
5596 thus <G>kaikuklone/p</G>, a reading which is not yet satisfactorily explained. | |
5597 Diels (<I>Vorsokratiker</I>, i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 7) considers that the accent over the <G>e</G> is fatal | |
5598 to the reading <G>e(ptamh/kh</G>, and conjectures <G>kai\ ku/klon e(/l(ika) kh)di/dace | |
5599 nhsteu/ein</G> instead of Hunt's <G>kai\ ku/klon e(p</G>[<G>tamh/ke', h)de\ nhsteu/ein</G>] and | |
5600 Diodorus's <G>kai\ ku/klon e(ptamh/kh di/dace nhsteu/ein</G>. But <G>ku/klon e(/lika</G>, ‘twisted | |
5601 (or curved) circle’, is very indefinite. It may have been suggested to | |
5602 Diels by Hermesianax's lines (Athenaeus xiii. 599 A) attributing to | |
5603 Pythagoras the ‘refinements of the geometry of spirals’ (<G>e(li/kwn komya\ | |
5604 gewmetri/hs</G>). One naturally thinks of Plato's dictum (<I>Timaeus</I> 39 A, B) | |
5605 about the circles of the sun, moon, and planets being twisted into spirals | |
5606 by the combination of their own motion with that of the daily rotation; | |
5607 but this can hardly be the meaning here. A more satisfactory sense | |
5608 would be secured if we could imagine the circle to be the circle described | |
5609 about the ‘scalene’ (right-angled) triangle, i.e. if we could take the | |
5610 reference to be to the discovery of the fact that the angle in a semi- | |
5611 circle is a right angle, a discovery which, as we have seen, was alterna- | |
5612 tively ascribed to Thales and Pythagoras.</note> | |
5613 <p>But it is time to pass on to the propositions in geometry | |
5614 which are definitely attributed to the Pythagoreans. | |
5615 <pb n=143><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
5616 <C>Discoveries attributed to the Pythagoreans.</C> | |
5617 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Equality of the sum of the three angles of a triangle | |
5618 to two right angles.</I></C> | |
5619 <p>We have seen that Thales, if he really discovered that the | |
5620 angle in a semicircle is a right angle, was in a position, first, | |
5621 to show that in any right-angled triangle the sum of the three | |
5622 angles is equal to two right angles, and then, by drawing the | |
5623 perpendicular from a vertex of any triangle to the opposite | |
5624 side and so dividing the triangle into two right-angled | |
5625 triangles, to prove that the sum of the three angles of any | |
5626 triangle whatever is equal to two right angles. If this method | |
5627 of passing from the particular case of a right-angled triangle to | |
5628 that of any triangle did not occur to Thales, it is at any rate | |
5629 hardly likely to have escaped Pythagoras. But all that we know | |
5630 for certain is that Eudemus referred to the Pythagoreans | |
5631 the discovery of the general theorem that in any triangle | |
5632 the sum of the interior angles is equal to two right angles.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 397. 2.</note> | |
5633 Eudemus goes on to tell us how they proved it. The method | |
5634 differs slightly from that of Euclid, but depends, equally with | |
5635 Euclid's proof, on the properties of parallels; it can therefore | |
5636 only have been evolved at a time when those properties were | |
5637 already known. | |
5638 <p>Let <I>ABC</I> be any triangle; through <I>A</I> draw <I>DE</I> parallel | |
5639 to <I>BC</I>. | |
5640 <FIG> | |
5641 <p>Then, since <I>BC, DE</I> are parallel, the | |
5642 alternate angles <I>DAB, ABC</I> are equal. | |
5643 <p>Similarly the alternate angles <I>EAC, | |
5644 ACB</I> are equal. | |
5645 <p>Therefore the sum of the angles <I>ABC, | |
5646 ACB</I> is equal to the sum of the angles <I>DAB, EAC</I>. | |
5647 <p>Add to each sum the angle <I>BAC</I>; therefore the sum of the | |
5648 three angles <I>ABC, ACB, BAC</I>, i.e. the three angles of the | |
5649 triangle, is equal to the sum of the angles <I>DAB, BAC, CAE</I>, | |
5650 i.e. to two right angles. | |
5651 <p>We need not hesitate to credit the Pythagoreans with the | |
5652 more general propositions about the angles of any polygon, | |
5653 <pb n=144><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
5654 namely (1) that, if <I>n</I> be the number of the sides or angles, the | |
5655 interior angles of the polygon are together equal to 2<I>n</I> - 4 | |
5656 right angles, and (2) that the exterior angles of the polygon | |
5657 (being the supplements of the interior angles respectively) | |
5658 are together equal to four right angles. The propositions are | |
5659 interdependent, and Aristotle twice quotes the latter.<note><I>An. Post.</I> i. 24, 85 b 38; <I>ib.</I> ii. 17, 99 a 19.</note> The | |
5660 Pythagoreans also discovered that the only three regular | |
5661 polygons the angles of which, if placed together round a com- | |
5662 mon point as vertex, just fill up the space (four right angles) | |
5663 round the point are the equilateral triangle, the square, and | |
5664 the regular hexagon. | |
5665 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The ‘Theorem of Pythagoras&rsquo</I>; (= Eucl. I. 47).</C> | |
5666 <p>Though this is the proposition universally associated by | |
5667 tradition with the name of Pythagoras, no really trustworthy | |
5668 evidence exists that it was actually discovered by him. The | |
5669 comparatively late writers who attribute it to him add the | |
5670 story that he sacrificed an ox to celebrate his discovery. | |
5671 Plutarch<note>Plutarch, <I>Non posse suaviter vivi secundum Epicurum</I>, c. 11, p. 1094 B.</note> (born about A.D. 46), Athenaeus<note>Athenaeus x. 418 F.</note> (about A.D. 200), | |
5672 and Diogenes Laertius<note>Diog. L. viii. 12, i. 25.</note> (A.D. 200 or later) all quote the verses | |
5673 of Apollodorus the ‘calculator’ already referred to (p. 133). | |
5674 But Apollodorus speaks of the ‘famous theorem’, or perhaps | |
5675 ‘figure’ (<G>gra/mma</G>), the discovery of which was the occa- | |
5676 sion of the sacrifice, without saying what the theorem was. | |
5677 Apollodorus is otherwise unknown; he may have been earlier | |
5678 than Cicero, for Cicero<note>Cicero, <I>De nat. deor.</I> iii. 36, 88.</note> tells the story in the same form | |
5679 without specifying what geometrical discovery was meant, | |
5680 and merely adds that he does not believe in the sacrifice, | |
5681 because the Pythagorean ritual forbade sacrifices in which | |
5682 blood was shed. Vitruvius<note>Vitruvius, <I>De architectura</I>, ix. pref.</note> (first century B.C.) connects the | |
5683 sacrifice with the discovery of the property of the particular | |
5684 triangle 3, 4, 5. Plutarch, in quoting Apollodorus, questions | |
5685 whether the theorem about the square of the hypotenuse was | |
5686 meant, or the problem of the application of an area, while in | |
5687 another place<note>Plutarch, <I>Quaest. conviv.</I> viii. 2, 4, p. 720 A.</note> he says that the occasion of the sacrifice was | |
5688 <pb n=145><head>THE ‘THEOREM OF PYTHAGORAS’</head> | |
5689 the solution of the problem, ‘given two figures, to <I>apply</I> | |
5690 a third which shall be equal to the one and similar to | |
5691 the other’, and he adds that this problem is unquestionably | |
5692 finer than the theorem about the square on the hypotenuse. | |
5693 But Athenaeus and Porphyry<note>Porphyry, <I>Vit. Pyth.</I> 36.</note> (A.D. 233-304) connect the | |
5694 sacrifice with the latter proposition; so does Diogenes Laertius | |
5695 in one place. We come lastly to Proclus, who is very cautious, | |
5696 mentioning the story but declining to commit himself to | |
5697 the view that it was Pythagoras or even any single person | |
5698 who made the discovery: | |
5699 <p>‘If we listen to those who wish to recount ancient history, | |
5700 we may find some of them referring this theorem to Pytha- | |
5701 goras, and saying that he sacrificed an ox in honour of his | |
5702 discovery. But for my part, while I admire <I>those who</I> first | |
5703 observed the truth of this theorem, I marvel more at the | |
5704 writer of the Elements, not only because he made it fast by a | |
5705 most lucid demonstration, but because he compelled assent to | |
5706 the still more general theorem by the irrefutable arguments of | |
5707 science in the sixth book.’ | |
5708 <p>It is possible that all these authorities may have built upon | |
5709 the verses of Apollodorus; but it is remarkable that, although | |
5710 in the verses themselves the particular theorem is not speci- | |
5711 fied, there is practical unanimity in attributing to Pythagoras | |
5712 the theorem of Eucl. I. 47. Even in Plutarch's observations | |
5713 expressing doubt about the particular occasion of the sacrifice | |
5714 there is nothing to suggest that he had any hesitation in | |
5715 accepting as discoveries of Pythagoras <I>both</I> the theorem of the | |
5716 square on the hypotenuse and the problem of the application | |
5717 of an area. Like Hankel,<note>Hankel, <I>Zur Geschichte der Math. in Alterthum und Mittelalter</I>, p. 97.</note> therefore, I would not go so far as | |
5718 to deny to Pythagoras the credit of the discovery of our pro- | |
5719 position; nay, I like to believe that tradition is right, and that | |
5720 it was really his. | |
5721 <p>True, the discovery is also claimed for India.<note>Bürk in the <I>Zeitschrift der morgenländ. Gesellschaft</I>, lv, 1901, pp. 543-91; lvi, 1902, pp. 327-91.</note> The work | |
5722 relied on is the <I>Āpastamba-Śulba-Sūtra</I>, the date of which is | |
5723 put at least as early as the fifth or fourth century B.C., while | |
5724 it is remarked that the matter of it must have been much | |
5725 <pb n=146><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
5726 older than the book itself; thus one of the constructions for | |
5727 right angles, using cords of lengths 15, 36, 39 (= 5, 12, 13), was | |
5728 known at the time of the <I>Tāittirīya Samhitā</I> and the <I>Sata- | |
5729 patha Brāhmana</I>, still older works belonging to the eighth | |
5730 century B.C. at latest. A feature of the <I>Āpastamba-Śulba- | |
5731 Sūtra</I> is the construction of right angles in this way by means | |
5732 of cords of lengths equal to the three sides of certain rational | |
5733 right-angled triangles (or, as Āpastamba calls them, rational | |
5734 rectangles, i.e. those in which the diagonals as well as the | |
5735 sides are rational). The rational right-angled triangles actually | |
5736 used are (3, 4, 5), (5, 12, 13), (8, 15, 17), (12, 35, 37). There is | |
5737 a proposition stating the theorem of Eucl. I. 47 as a fact in | |
5738 general terms, but without proof, and there are rules based | |
5739 upon it for constructing a square equal to (1) the sum of two | |
5740 given squares and (2) the difference of two squares. But | |
5741 certain considerations suggest doubts as to whether the | |
5742 proposition had been established by any proof applicable to | |
5743 all cases. Thus Āpastamba mentions only seven rational | |
5744 right-angled triangles, really reducible to the above-mentioned | |
5745 four (one other, 7, 24, 25, appears, it is true, in the Bāudhā- | |
5746 yana Ś. S., supposed to be older than Āpastamba); he had no | |
5747 general rule such as that attributed to Pythagoras for forming | |
5748 any number of rational right-angled triangles; he refers to | |
5749 his seven in the words ‘so many <I>recognizable</I> constructions | |
5750 are there’, implying that he knew of no other such triangles. | |
5751 On the other hand, the truth of the theorem was recognized in | |
5752 the case of the isosceles right-angled triangle; there is even | |
5753 a construction for √2, or the length of the diagonal of a square | |
5754 with side unity, which is constructed as <MATH>(1+1/3+1/(3.4)-1/(3.4.34))</MATH> | |
5755 of the side, and is then used with the side for the purpose of | |
5756 drawing the square on the side: the length taken is of course | |
5757 an approximation to √2 derived from the consideration that | |
5758 <MATH>2.12<SUP>2</SUP>=288=17<SUP>2</SUP>-1</MATH>; but the author does not say anything | |
5759 which suggests any knowledge on his part that the approxi- | |
5760 mate value is not exact. Having drawn by means of the | |
5761 approximate value of the diagonal an inaccurate square, he | |
5762 proceeds to use it to construct a square with area equal to | |
5763 three times the original square, or, in other words, to con- | |
5764 struct √3, which is therefore only approximately found. | |
5765 <pb n=147><head>THE ‘THEOREM OF PYTHAGORAS’</head> | |
5766 Thus the theorem is enunciated and used as if it were of | |
5767 general application; there is, however, no sign of any general | |
5768 proof; there is nothing in fact to show that the assumption of | |
5769 its universal truth was founded on anything better than an | |
5770 imperfect induction from a certain number of cases, discovered | |
5771 empirically, of triangles with sides in the ratios of whole | |
5772 numbers in which the property (1) that the square on the | |
5773 longest side is equal to the sum of the squares on the other | |
5774 two was found to be always accompanied by the property | |
5775 (2) that the latter two sides include a right angle. But, even | |
5776 if the Indians had actually attained to a scientific proof of | |
5777 the general theorem, there is no evidence or probability that | |
5778 the Greeks obtained it from India; the subject was doubtless | |
5779 developed quite independently in the two countries. | |
5780 <p>The next question is, how was the theorem proved by | |
5781 Pythagoras or the Pythagoreans? Vitruvius says that | |
5782 Pythagoras first discovered the triangle (3, 4, 5), and doubtless | |
5783 the theorem was first suggested by the discovery that this | |
5784 triangle is right-angled; but this discovery probably came | |
5785 to Greece from Egypt. Then a very simple construction | |
5786 would show that the theorem is true of an <I>isosceles</I> right- | |
5787 angled triangle. Two possible lines are suggested on which | |
5788 the general proof may have been developed. One is that of | |
5789 decomposing square and rectangular areas into squares, rect- | |
5790 angles and triangles, and piecing them together again after | |
5791 the manner of Eucl., Book II; the isosceles right-angled | |
5792 triangle gives the most obvious case of this method. The | |
5793 other line is one depending upon proportions; and we have | |
5794 good reason for supposing that Pythagoras developed a theory | |
5795 of proportion. That theory was applicable to commensurable | |
5796 magnitudes only; but this would not be any obstacle to the | |
5797 use of the method so long as the existence of the incom- | |
5798 mensurable or irrational remained undiscovered. From | |
5799 Proclus's remark that, while he admired those who first | |
5800 noticed the truth of the theorem, he admired Euclid still | |
5801 more for his most clear proof of it and for the irrefutable | |
5802 demonstration of the extension of the theorem in Book VI, | |
5803 it is natural to conclude that Euclid's proof in I. 47 was new, | |
5804 though this is not quite certain. Now VI. 31 could be proved | |
5805 at once by using I. 47 along with VI. 22; but Euclid proves | |
5806 <pb n=148><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
5807 it independently of I. 47 by means of proportions. This | |
5808 seems to suggest that he proved I. 47 by the methods of | |
5809 Book I instead of by proportions in order to get the proposi- | |
5810 tion into Book I instead of Book VI, to which it must have | |
5811 been relegated if the proof by proportions had been used. | |
5812 If, on the other hand, Pythagoras had proved it by means | |
5813 of the methods of Books I and II, it would hardly have been | |
5814 necessary for Euclid to devise a new proof of I. 47. Hence | |
5815 it would appear most probable that Pythagoras would prove | |
5816 the proposition by means of his (imperfect) theory of pro- | |
5817 portions. The proof may have taken one of three different | |
5818 shapes. | |
5819 <FIG> | |
5820 <p>(1) If <I>ABC</I> is a triangle right- | |
5821 angled at <I>A</I>, and <I>AD</I> is perpen- | |
5822 dicular to <I>BC</I>, the triangles <I>DBA, | |
5823 DAC</I> are both similar to the tri- | |
5824 angle <I>ABC</I>. | |
5825 <p>It follows from the theorems of | |
5826 Eucl. VI. 4 and 17 that | |
5827 <MATH><I>BA</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BD.BC</I></MATH>, | |
5828 <MATH><I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>CD.BC</I></MATH>, | |
5829 whence, by addition, <MATH><I>BA</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BC</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
5830 <p>It will be observed that this proof is <I>in substance</I> identical | |
5831 with that of Eucl. I. 47, the difference being that the latter | |
5832 uses the relations between parallelograms and triangles on | |
5833 the same base and between the same parallels instead of | |
5834 proportions. The probability is that it was this particular | |
5835 proof by proportions which suggested to Euclid the method | |
5836 of I. 47; but the transformation of the proof depending on | |
5837 proportions into one based on Book I only (which was abso- | |
5838 lutely required under Euclid's arrangement of the <I>Elements</I>) | |
5839 was a stroke of genius. | |
5840 <p>(2) It would be observed that, in the similar triangles | |
5841 <I>DBA, DAC, ABC</I>, the corresponding sides opposite to the | |
5842 right angle in each case are <I>BA, AC, BC</I>. | |
5843 <p>The triangles therefore are in the duplicate ratios of these | |
5844 sides, and so are the squares on the latter. | |
5845 <p>But of the triangles two, namely <I>DBA, DAC</I>, make up the | |
5846 third, <I>ABC</I>. | |
5847 <pb n=149><head>THE ‘THEOREM OF PYTHAGORAS’</head> | |
5848 <p>The same must therefore be the case with the squares, or | |
5849 <MATH><I>BA</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BC</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
5850 <p>(3) The method of VI. 31 might have been followed | |
5851 exactly, with squares taking the place of any similar recti- | |
5852 lineal figures. Since the triangles <I>DBA, ABC</I> are similar, | |
5853 <MATH><I>BD</I>:<I>AB</I>=<I>AB</I>:<I>BC</I></MATH>, | |
5854 or <I>BD, AB, BC</I> are three proportionals, whence | |
5855 <MATH><I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>BC</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BD</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BD</I>:<I>BC</I></MATH>. | |
5856 <p>Similarly, <MATH><I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>BC</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>CD</I>:<I>BC</I></MATH>. | |
5857 <p>Therefore <MATH>(<I>BA</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>):<I>BC</I><SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>BD</I>+<I>DC</I>):<I>BC</I>. [V. 24] | |
5858 =1</MATH>. | |
5859 <p>If, on the other hand, the proposition was originally proved | |
5860 by the methods of Euclid, Books I, II alone (which, as I have | |
5861 said, seems the less probable supposition), the suggestion of | |
5862 <FIG> | |
5863 Bretschneider and Hankel seems to be the best. According | |
5864 to this we are to suppose, first, a figure like that of Eucl. | |
5865 II. 4, representing a larger square, of side (<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>), divided | |
5866 into two smaller squares of sides <I>a, b</I> respectively, and | |
5867 two complements, being two equal rectangles with <I>a, b</I> as | |
5868 sides. | |
5869 <p>Then, dividing each complementary rectangle into two | |
5870 equal triangles, we dispose the four triangles round another | |
5871 square of side <I>a</I>+<I>b</I> in the manner shown in the second figure. | |
5872 <p>Deducting the four triangles from the original square in | |
5873 each case we get, in the first figure, two squares <I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP> and <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> | |
5874 and, in the second figure, one square on <I>c</I>, the diagonal of the | |
5875 rectangle (<I>a, b</I>) or the hypotenuse of the right-angled triangle | |
5876 in which <I>a, b</I> are the sides about the right angle. It follows | |
5877 that <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
5878 <pb n=150><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
5879 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Application of areas and geometrical algebra.</I></C> | |
5880 <p>We have seen that, in connexion with the story of the | |
5881 sacrifice of an ox, Plutarch attributes to Pythagoras himself | |
5882 the discovery of the problem of the application of an area | |
5883 or, as he says in another place, the problem ‘Given two | |
5884 figures, to “apply” a third figure which shall be equal to the | |
5885 one, and similar to the other (of the given figures).’ The | |
5886 latter problem (= Eucl. VI. 25) is, strictly speaking, not so | |
5887 much a case of <I>applying</I> an area as of <I>constructing</I> a figure, | |
5888 because the base is not given in length; but it depends | |
5889 directly upon the simplest case of ‘application of areas’, | |
5890 namely the problem, solved in Eucl. I. 44, 45, of applying | |
5891 to a given straight line as base a parallelogram containing | |
5892 a given angle and equal in area to a given triangle or | |
5893 rectilineal figure. The method of application of areas is | |
5894 fundamental in Greek geometry and requires detailed notice. | |
5895 We shall see that in its general form it is equivalent to the | |
5896 geometrical solution of a mixed quadratic equation, and it is | |
5897 therefore an essential part of what has been appropriately | |
5898 called <I>geometrical algebra</I>. | |
5899 <p>It is certain that the theory of application of areas | |
5900 originated with the Pythagoreans, if not with Pythagoras | |
5901 himself. We have this on the authority of Eudemus, quoted | |
5902 in the following passage of Proclus: | |
5903 <p>‘These things, says Eudemus, are ancient, being discoveries | |
5904 of the Muse of the Pythagoreans, I mean the <I>application of | |
5905 areas</I> (<G>parabolh\ tw=n xwri/wn</G>), their <I>exceeding</I> (<G>u(perbolh/</G>) and | |
5906 their <I>falling short</I> (<G>e)/lleiyis</G>). It was from the Pythagoreans | |
5907 that later geometers [i.e. Apollonius of Perga] took the | |
5908 names, which they then transferred to the so-called <I>conic</I> | |
5909 lines (curves), calling one of these a <I>parabola</I> (application), | |
5910 another a <I>hyperbola</I> (exceeding), and the third an <I>ellipse</I> | |
5911 (falling short), whereas those god-like men of old saw the | |
5912 things signified by these names in the construction, in a plane, | |
5913 of areas upon a given finite straight line. For, when you | |
5914 have a straight line set out, and lay the given area exactly | |
5915 alongside the whole of the straight line, they say that you | |
5916 <I>apply</I> the said area; when, however, you make the length of | |
5917 the area greater than the straight line, it is said to <I>exceed</I>, | |
5918 and, when you make it less, in which case after the area has | |
5919 been drawn there is some part of the straight line extending | |
5920 <pb n=151><head>APPLICATION OF AREAS</head> | |
5921 beyond it, it is said to <I>fall short</I>. Euclid, too, in the sixth | |
5922 book speaks in this way both of exceeding and falling short; | |
5923 but in this place (I. 44) he needed the <I>application</I> simply, as | |
5924 he sought to apply to a given straight line an area equal | |
5925 to a given triangle, in order that we might have in our | |
5926 power, not only the <I>construction</I> (<G>su/stasis</G>) of a parallelogram | |
5927 equal to a given triangle, but also the application of it to | |
5928 a limited straight line.’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, pp. 419. 15-420. 12.</note> | |
5929 <p>The general form of the problem involving <I>application</I> | |
5930 with <I>exceeding</I> or <I>falling short</I> is the following: | |
5931 <p>‘To apply to a given straight line a rectangle (or, more | |
5932 generally, a parallelogram) equal to a given rectilineal figure, | |
5933 and (1) <I>exceeding</I> or (2) <I>falling short</I> by a square figure (or, | |
5934 in the more general case, by a parallelogram similar to a given | |
5935 parallelogram).’ | |
5936 <p>The most general form, shown by the words in brackets, | |
5937 is found in Eucl. VI. 28, 29, which are equivalent to the | |
5938 geometrical solution of the quadratic equations | |
5939 <MATH><I>ax</I>±(<I>b</I>/<I>c</I>)<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>C</I>/<I>m</I></MATH>, | |
5940 and VI. 27 gives the condition of possibility of a solution | |
5941 when the sign is negative and the parallelogram <I>falls short</I>. | |
5942 This general case of course requires the use of proportions; | |
5943 but the simpler case where the area applied is a rectangle, | |
5944 and the form of the portion which overlaps or falls short | |
5945 is a square, can be solved by means of Book II only. The | |
5946 proposition II. 11 is the geometrical solution of the particular | |
5947 quadratic equation | |
5948 <MATH><I>a</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>x</I>)=<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
5949 or <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>ax</I>=<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
5950 The propositions II. 5 and 6 are in the form of theorems. | |
5951 Taking, e.g., the figure of the former proposition, and sup- | |
5952 posing <MATH><I>AB</I>=<I>a</I>, <I>BD</I>=<I>x</I></MATH>, we have | |
5953 <MATH><I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=rectangle <I>AH</I> | |
5954 =gnomon <I>NOP</I></MATH>. | |
5955 If, then, the area of the gnomon is given (= <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>, say, for any | |
5956 area can be transformed into the equivalent square by means | |
5957 of the problems of Eucl. I. 45 and II. 14), the solution of the | |
5958 equation <MATH><I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> | |
5959 <pb n=152><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
5960 would be, in the language of application of areas, ‘To a given | |
5961 straight line (<I>a</I>) to apply a rectangle which shall be equal | |
5962 to a given square (<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>) and shall fall short by a square figure.’ | |
5963 <FIG> | |
5964 <p>As the Pythagoreans solved the somewhat similar equation | |
5965 in II. 11, they cannot have failed to solve this one, as well as | |
5966 the equations corresponding to II. 6. For in the present case | |
5967 it is only necessary to draw <I>CQ</I> at right angles to <I>AB</I> from | |
5968 its middle point <I>C</I>, to make <I>CQ</I> equal to <I>b</I>, and then, with | |
5969 centre <I>Q</I> and radius equal to <I>CB</I>, or 1/2<I>a</I>, to draw a circle | |
5970 cutting <I>QC</I> produced in <I>R</I> and <I>CB</I> in <I>D</I> (<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> must be not | |
5971 greater than 1/2<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>; otherwise a solution is impossible). | |
5972 <p>Then the determination of the point <I>D</I> constitutes the | |
5973 solution of the quadratic. | |
5974 <p>For, by the proposition II. 5, | |
5975 <MATH><I>AD.DB</I>+<I>CD</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>CB</I><SUP>2</SUP> | |
5976 =<I>QD</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>QC</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>CD</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>; | |
5977 therefore <MATH><I>AD.DB</I>=<I>QC</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
5978 or <MATH><I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
5979 <p>Similarly II. 6 enables us to solve the equations | |
5980 <MATH><I>ax</I>+<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
5981 and <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>ax</I>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>; | |
5982 <FIG> | |
5983 the first equation corresponding to <I>AB</I>=<I>a</I>, <I>BD</I>=<I>x</I> and the | |
5984 second to <I>AB</I>=<I>a</I>, <I>AD</I>=<I>x</I>, in the figure of the proposition. | |
5985 <p>The application of the theory to conics by Apollonius will | |
5986 be described when we come to deal with his treatise. | |
5987 <p>One great feature of Book II of Euclid's <I>Elements</I> is the | |
5988 use of the <I>gnomon</I> (Props. 5 to 8), which is undoubtedly | |
5989 Pythagorean and is connected, as we have seen, with the | |
5990 <pb n=153><head>APPLICATION OF AREAS</head> | |
5991 application of areas. The whole of Book II, with the latter | |
5992 section of Book I from Prop. 42 onwards, may be said to deal | |
5993 with the transformation of areas into equivalent areas of | |
5994 different shape or composition by means of ‘application’ | |
5995 and the use of the theorem of I. 47. Eucl. II. 9 and 10 are | |
5996 special cases which are very useful in geometry generally, but | |
5997 were also employed by the Pythagoreans for the specific purpose | |
5998 of proving the property of ‘side-’ and ‘diameter-’ numbers, | |
5999 the object of which was clearly to develop a series of closer | |
6000 and closer approximations to the value of √2 (see p. 93 <I>ante</I>). | |
6001 <p>The <I>geometrical algebra</I>, therefore, as we find it in Euclid, | |
6002 Books I and II, was Pythagorean. It was of course confined | |
6003 to problems not involving expressions above the second degree. | |
6004 Subject to this, it was an effective substitute for modern | |
6005 algebra. The product of two linear factors was a rect- | |
6006 angle, and Book II of Euclid made it possible to <I>multiply</I> | |
6007 two factors with any number of linear terms in each; the | |
6008 compression of the result into a single product (rectangle) | |
6009 followed by means of the <I>application</I>-theorem (Eucl. I. 44). | |
6010 That theorem itself corresponds to <I>dividing</I> the product of | |
6011 any two linear factors by a third linear expression. To trans- | |
6012 form any area into a square, we have only to turn the area | |
6013 into a rectangle (as in Eucl. I. 45), and then find a square | |
6014 equal to that rectangle by the method of Eucl. II. 14; the | |
6015 latter problem then is equivalent to the <I>extraction of the square | |
6016 root</I>. And we have seen that the theorems of Eucl. II. 5, 6 | |
6017 enable mixed quadratic equations of certain types to be solved | |
6018 so far as their roots are real. In cases where a quadratic | |
6019 equation has one or both roots negative, the Greeks would | |
6020 transform it into one having a positive root or roots (by the | |
6021 equivalent of substituting -<I>x</I> for <I>x</I>); thus, where one root is | |
6022 positive and one negative, they would solve the problem in | |
6023 two parts by taking two cases. | |
6024 <p>The other great engine of the Greek geometrical algebra, | |
6025 namely the method of proportions, was not in its full extent | |
6026 available to the Pythagoreans because their theory of pro- | |
6027 portion was only applicable to commensurable magnitudes | |
6028 (Eudoxus was the first to establish the general theory, applic- | |
6029 able to commensurables and incommensurables alike, which | |
6030 we find in Eucl. V, VI). Yet it cannot be doubted that they | |
6031 <pb n=154><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
6032 used the method quite freely before the discovery of the irra- | |
6033 tional showed them that they were building on an insecure | |
6034 and inadequate foundation. | |
6035 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>The irrational.</I></C> | |
6036 <p>To return to the sentence about Pythagoras in the summary | |
6037 of Proclus already quoted more than once (pp. 84, 90, 141). | |
6038 Even if the reading <G>a)lo/gwn</G> were right and Proclus really | |
6039 meant to attribute to Pythagoras the discovery of ‘the theory, | |
6040 or study, of irrationals’, it would be necessary to consider the | |
6041 authority for this statement, and how far it is supported by | |
6042 other evidence. We note that it occurs in a relative sentence | |
6043 <G>o(\s dh\</G> . . ., which has the appearance of being inserted in paren- | |
6044 thesis by the compiler of the summary rather than copied from | |
6045 his original source; and the shortened form of the first part | |
6046 of the same summary published in the <I>Variae collectiones</I> of | |
6047 Hultsch's Heron, and now included by Heiberg in Heron's | |
6048 <I>Definitions</I>,<note>Heron, vol. iv, ed. Heib., p. 108.</note> contains no such parenthesis. Other authorities | |
6049 attribute the discovery of the theory of the irrational not to | |
6050 Pythagoras but to the Pythagoreans. A scholium to Euclid, | |
6051 Book X, says that | |
6052 <p>‘the Pythagoreans were the first to address themselves to the | |
6053 investigation of commensurability, having discovered it as the | |
6054 result of their observation of numbers; for, while the unit is | |
6055 a common measure of all numbers, they were unable to find | |
6056 a common measure of all magnitudes, . . . because all magni- | |
6057 tudes are divisible <I>ad infinitum</I> and never leave a magnitude | |
6058 which is too small to admit of further division, but that | |
6059 remainder is equally divisible <I>ad infinitum</I>,’ | |
6060 <p>and so on. The scholiast adds the legend that | |
6061 <p>‘the first of the Pythagoreans who made public the investiga- | |
6062 tion of these matters perished in a shipwreck’.<note>Euclid, ed. Heib., vol. v, pp. 415, 417.</note> | |
6063 <p>Another commentary on Eucl. X discovered by Woepcke in | |
6064 an Arabic translation and believed, with good reason, to be | |
6065 part of the commentary of Pappus, says that the theory of | |
6066 irrational magnitudes ‘had its origin in the school of Pytha- | |
6067 goras’. Again, it is impossible that Pythagoras himself should | |
6068 have discovered a ‘theory’ or ‘study’ of irrationals in any | |
6069 <pb n=155><head>THE IRRATIONAL</head> | |
6070 proper sense. We are told in the <I>Theaetetus</I><note>Plato, <I>Theaetetus</I>, 147 D sq.</note> that Theodorus | |
6071 of Cyrene (a pupil of Protagoras and the teacher of Plato) | |
6072 proved the irrationality of √3, √5, &c., up to √17, and this | |
6073 must have been at a date not much, if anything, earlier than | |
6074 400 B.C.; while it was Theaetetus who, inspired by Theodorus's | |
6075 investigation of these particular ‘roots’ (or surds), was the | |
6076 first to generalize the theory, seeking terms to cover all such | |
6077 incommensurables; this is confirmed by the continuation of | |
6078 the passage from Pappus's commentary, which says that the | |
6079 theory was | |
6080 <p>‘considerably developed by Theaetetus the Athenian, who | |
6081 gave proof, in this part of mathematics as in others, of ability | |
6082 which has been justly admired . . . As for the exact dis- | |
6083 tinctions of the above-named magnitudes and the rigorous | |
6084 demonstrations of the propositions to which this theory gives | |
6085 rise, I believe that they were chiefly established by this | |
6086 mathematician’. | |
6087 <p>It follows from all this that, if Pythagoras discovered any- | |
6088 thing about irrationals, it was not any ‘theory’ of irrationals | |
6089 but, at the most, some particular case of incommensurability. | |
6090 Now the passage which states that Theodorus proved that | |
6091 √3, √5, &c. are incommensurable says nothing of √2. The | |
6092 reason is, no doubt, that the incommensurability of √2 had | |
6093 been proved earlier, and everything points to the probability | |
6094 that this was the first case to be discovered. But, if Pytha- | |
6095 goras discovered even this, it is difficult to see how the theory | |
6096 that number is the essence of all existing things, or that all | |
6097 things are made of number, could have held its ground for | |
6098 any length of time. The evidence suggests the conclusion | |
6099 that geometry developed itself for some time on the basis of | |
6100 the numerical theory of proportion which was inapplicable to | |
6101 any but commensurable magnitudes, and that it received an | |
6102 unexpected blow later by reason of the discovery of the irra- | |
6103 tional. The inconvenience of this state of things, which | |
6104 involved the restriction or abandonment of the use of propor- | |
6105 tions as a method pending the discovery of the generalized | |
6106 theory by Eudoxus, may account for the idea of the existence | |
6107 of the irrational having been kept secret, and of punishment | |
6108 having overtaken the first person who divulged it. | |
6109 <pb n=156><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
6110 <p>If then it was not Pythagoras but some Pythagorean who | |
6111 discovered the irrationality of √2, at what date are we to | |
6112 suppose the discovery to have been made? A recent writer<note>H. Vogt in <I>Bibliotheca mathematica</I>, x<SUB>3</SUB>, 1910, pp. 97-155 (cf. ix<SUB>3</SUB>, | |
6113 p. 190 sq.).</note> | |
6114 on the subject holds that it was the <I>later</I> Pythagoreans who | |
6115 made the discovery, not much before 410 B.C. It is impos- | |
6116 sible, he argues, that fifty or a hundred years would elapse | |
6117 between the discovery of the irrationality of √2 and the like | |
6118 discovery by Theodorus (about 410 or 400 B.C.) about the other | |
6119 surds √3, √5, &c. It is difficult to meet this argument | |
6120 except by the supposition that, in the interval, the thoughts | |
6121 of geometers had been taken up by other famous problems, | |
6122 such as the quadrature of the circle and the duplication of the | |
6123 cube (itself equivalent to finding √<SUP>3</SUP>2). Another argument is | |
6124 based on the passage in the <I>Laws</I> where the Athenian stranger | |
6125 speaks of the shameful ignorance of the generality of Greeks, | |
6126 who are not aware that it is not all geometrical magnitudes | |
6127 that are commensurable with one another; the speaker adds | |
6128 that it was only ‘late’ (<G>o)ye/ pote</G>) that he himself learnt the | |
6129 truth.<note>Plato, <I>Laws</I>, 819 D-820 C.</note> Even if we knew for certain whether ‘late’ means | |
6130 ‘late in the day’ or ‘late in life’, the expression would not | |
6131 help much towards determining the date of the first discovery | |
6132 of the irrationality of √2; for the language of the passage is | |
6133 that of rhetorical exaggeration (Plato speaks of men who are | |
6134 unacquainted with the existence of the irrational as more | |
6135 comparable to swine than to human beings). Moreover, the | |
6136 irrational appears in the <I>Republic</I> as something well known, | |
6137 and precisely with reference to √2; for the expressions ‘the | |
6138 rational diameter of (the square the side of which is) 5’ | |
6139 [= the approximation √(49) or 7] and the ‘irrational | |
6140 (<G>a)/rrhtos</G>) diameter of 5’ [= √(50)] are used without any word | |
6141 of explanation.<note>Plato, <I>Republic</I>, vii. 546 D.</note> | |
6142 <p>Further, we have a well-authenticated title of a work by | |
6143 Democritus (born 470 or 460 B.C.), <G>peri\ a)lo/gwn grammw=n kai\ | |
6144 nastw=n ab</G>, ‘two books on irrational lines and solids’ (<G>nasto/n</G> | |
6145 is <G>plh=res</G>, ‘full’, as opposed to <G>keno/n</G>. ‘void’, and Democritus | |
6146 called his ‘first bodies’ <G>nasta/</G>). Of the contents of this work | |
6147 we are not informed; the recent writer already mentioned | |
6148 <pb n=157><head>THE IRRATIONAL</head> | |
6149 suggests that <G>a)/logos</G> does not here mean irrational or incom- | |
6150 mensurable at all, but that the book was an attempt to con- | |
6151 nect the atomic theory with continuous magnitudes (lines) | |
6152 through ‘indivisible lines’ (cf. the Aristotelian treatise <I>On | |
6153 indivisible lines</I>), and that Democritus meant to say that, | |
6154 since any two lines are alike made up of an infinite number | |
6155 of the (indivisible) elements, they cannot be said to have any | |
6156 expressible ratio to one another, that is, he would regard them | |
6157 as ‘having no ratio’! It is, however, impossible to suppose | |
6158 that a mathematician of the calibre of Democritus could have | |
6159 denied that any two lines can have a ratio to one another; | |
6160 moreover, on this view, since no two straight lines would have | |
6161 a ratio to one another, <G>a)/logoi grammai/</G> would not be a <I>class</I> of | |
6162 lines, but <I>all</I> lines, and the title would lose all point. But | |
6163 indeed, as we shall see, it is also on other grounds inconceiv- | |
6164 able that Democritus should have been an upholder of ‘indi- | |
6165 visible lines’ at all. I do not attach any importance to the | |
6166 further argument used in support of the interpretation in | |
6167 question, namely that <G>a)/logos</G> in the sense of ‘irrational’ is | |
6168 not found in any other writer before Aristotle, and that | |
6169 Plato uses the words <G>a)/rrhtos</G> and <G>a)su/mmetros</G> only. The | |
6170 latter statement is not even strictly true, for Plato does in | |
6171 fact use the word <G>a)/logoi</G> specifically of <G>grammai/</G> in the passage | |
6172 of the <I>Republic</I> where he speaks of youths not being <G>a)/logoi | |
6173 w(/sper grammai/</G>, ‘irrational like lines’.<note>Plato, <I>Republic</I>, 534 D.</note> Poor as the joke is, | |
6174 it proves that <G>a)/logoi grammai/</G> was a recognized technical | |
6175 term, and the remark looks like a sly reference to the very | |
6176 treatise of Democritus of which we are speaking. I think | |
6177 there is no reason to doubt that the book was on ‘irrationals’ | |
6178 in the technical sense. We know from other sources that | |
6179 Democritus was already on the track of infinitesimals in | |
6180 geometry; and nothing is more likely than that he would | |
6181 write on the kindred subject of irrationals. | |
6182 <p>I see therefore no reason to doubt that the irrationality | |
6183 of √2 was discovered by some Pythagorean at a date appre- | |
6184 ciably earlier than that of Democritus; and indeed the simple | |
6185 proof of it indicated by Aristotle and set out in the propo- | |
6186 sition interpolated at the end of Euclid's Book X seems | |
6187 appropriate to an early stage in the development of geometry. | |
6188 <pb n=158><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
6189 <C>(<G>e</G>) <I>The five regular solids.</I></C> | |
6190 <p>The same parenthetical sentence in Proclus which attributes | |
6191 to Pythagoras the discovery of the theory of irrationals | |
6192 (or proportions) also states that he discovered the ‘putting | |
6193 together (<G>su/stasis</G>) of the cosmic figures’ (the five regular | |
6194 solids). As usual, there has been controversy as to the sense | |
6195 in which this phrase is to be taken, and as to the possibility | |
6196 of Pythagoras having done what is attributed to him, in any | |
6197 sense of the words. I do not attach importance to the | |
6198 argument that, whereas Plato, presumably ‘Pythagorizing’, | |
6199 assigns the first four solids to the four elements, earth, fire, | |
6200 air, and water, Empedocles and not Pythagoras was the | |
6201 first to declare these four elements to be the material princi- | |
6202 ples from which the universe was evolved; nor do I think | |
6203 it follows that, because the elements are four, only the first | |
6204 four solids had been discovered at the time when the four | |
6205 elements came to be recognized, and that the dodecahedron | |
6206 must therefore have been discovered later. I see no reason | |
6207 why all five should not have been discovered by the early | |
6208 Pythagoreans before any question of identifying them with | |
6209 the elements arose. The fragment of Philolaus, indeed, says | |
6210 that | |
6211 <p>‘there are five bodies in the sphere, the fire, water, earth, | |
6212 and air in the sphere, and the vessel of the sphere itself | |
6213 making the fifth’,<note>Stobaeus, <I>Ecl.</I> I, proem. 3 (p. 18. 5 Wachsmuth); Diels, <I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, | |
6214 p. 314. The Greek of the last phrase is <G>kai\ o(\ ta=s sfai/ras o(lka/s, pe/mpton</G>, | |
6215 but <G>o(lka/s</G> is scarcely an appropriate word, and von Wilamowitz (<I>Platon</I>, | |
6216 vol. ii, 1919, pp. 91-2) proposes <G>o( ta=s sfai/ras o(lko/s</G>, taking <G>o(lko/s</G> (which | |
6217 implies ‘winding’) as <I>volumen.</I> We might then translate by ‘the spherical | |
6218 envelope’.</note> | |
6219 <p>but as this is only to be understood of the <I>elements</I> in the | |
6220 sphere of the universe, not of the solid figures, in accordance | |
6221 with Diels's translation, it would appear that Plato in the | |
6222 <I>Timaeus</I><note><I>Timaeus</I>, 53 C-55 C.</note> is the earliest authority for the allocation, and | |
6223 it may very well be due to Plato himself (were not the solids | |
6224 called the ‘Platonic figures’?), although put into the mouth | |
6225 of a Pythagorean. At the same time, the fact that the | |
6226 <I>Timaeus</I> is fundamentally Pythagorean may have induced | |
6227 Aëtius's authority (probably Theophrastus) to conclude too | |
6228 <pb n=159><head>THE FIVE REGULAR SOLIDS</head> | |
6229 hastily that ‘here, too, Plato Pythagorizes’, and to say dog- | |
6230 matically on the faith of this that | |
6231 <p>‘<I>Pythagoras</I>, seeing that there are five solid figures, which | |
6232 are also called the mathematical figures, says that the earth | |
6233 arose from the cube, fire from the pyramid, air from the | |
6234 octahedron, water from the icosahedron, and the sphere of | |
6235 the universe from the dodecahedron.’<note>Aët. ii. 6. 5 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 306. 3-7).</note> | |
6236 <p>It may, I think, be conceded that Pythagoras or the early | |
6237 Pythagoreans would hardly be able to ‘construct’ the five | |
6238 regular solids in the sense of a complete theoretical construc- | |
6239 tion such as we find in Eucl. XIII; and it is possible that | |
6240 Theaetetus was the first to give these constructions, whether | |
6241 <G>e)/graye</G> in Suidas's notice means that ‘he was the first to | |
6242 <I>construct</I>’ or ‘to <I>write upon</I> the five solids so called’. But | |
6243 there is no reason why the Pythagoreans should not have | |
6244 ‘put together’ the five figures in the manner in which Plato | |
6245 puts them together in the <I>Timaeus</I>, namely, by bringing | |
6246 a certain number of angles of equilateral triangles, squares, | |
6247 or pentagons severally together at one point so as to make | |
6248 a solid angle, and then completing all the solid angles in that | |
6249 way. That the early Pythagoreans should have discovered | |
6250 the five regular solids in this elementary way agrees well | |
6251 with what we know of their having put angles of certain | |
6252 regular figures round a point and shown that only three | |
6253 kinds of such angles would fill up the space in one plane | |
6254 round the point.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, pp. 304. 11-305. 3.</note> How elementary the construction still was | |
6255 in Plato's hands may be inferred from the fact that he argues | |
6256 that only three of the elements are transformable into one | |
6257 another because only three of the solids are made from | |
6258 equilateral triangles; these triangles, when present in suffi- | |
6259 cient numbers in given regular solids, can be separated again | |
6260 and redistributed so as to form regular solids of a different | |
6261 number of faces, as if the solids were really hollow shells | |
6262 bounded by the triangular faces as planes or laminae (Aris- | |
6263 totle criticizes this in <I>De caelo</I>, iii. 1)! We may indeed treat | |
6264 Plato's elementary method as an indication that this was | |
6265 actually the method employed by the earliest Pythagoreans. | |
6266 <pb n=160><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
6267 <p>Putting together squares three by three, forming eight | |
6268 solid angles, and equilateral triangles three by three, four by | |
6269 four, or five by five, forming four, six, or twelve solid angles | |
6270 respectively, we readily form a cube, a tetrahedron, an octa- | |
6271 hedron, or an icosahedron, but the fifth regular solid, the | |
6272 dodecahedron, requires a new element, the regular pentagon. | |
6273 True, if we form the angle of an icosahedron by putting | |
6274 together five equilateral triangles, the bases of those triangles | |
6275 when put together form a regular pentagon; but Pythagoras | |
6276 or the Pythagoreans would require a theoretical construction. | |
6277 What is the evidence that the early Pythagoreans could have | |
6278 constructed and did construct pentagons? That they did | |
6279 construct them seems established by the story of Hippasus, | |
6280 <p>‘who was a Pythagorean but, owing to his being the first | |
6281 to publish and write down the (construction of the) sphere | |
6282 with (<G>e)k</G>, from) the twelve pentagons, perished by shipwreck | |
6283 for his impiety, but received credit for the discovery, whereas | |
6284 it really belonged to HIM (<G>e)kei/nou tou= a)ndro/s</G>), for it is thus | |
6285 that they refer to Pythagoras, and they do not call him by | |
6286 his name.’<note>Iambl. <I>Vit. Pyth.</I> 88, <I>de c. math. scient.</I> c. 25, p. 77. 18-24.</note> | |
6287 <p>The connexion of Hippasus's name with the subject can | |
6288 hardly be an invention, and the story probably points to | |
6289 a positive achievement by him, while of course the Pytha- | |
6290 goreans' jealousy for the Master accounts for the reflection | |
6291 upon Hippasus and the moral. Besides, there is evidence for | |
6292 the very early existence of dodecahedra in actual fact. In | |
6293 1885 there was discovered on Monte Loffa (Colli Euganei, | |
6294 near Padua) a regular dodecahedron of Etruscan origin, which | |
6295 is held to date from the first half of the first millennium B.C.<note>F. Lindemann, ‘Zur Geschichte der Polyeder und der Zahlzeichen’ | |
6296 (<I>Sitzungsber. der K. Bay. Akad. der Wiss.</I> xxvi. 1897, pp. 625-768).</note> | |
6297 Again, it appears that there are extant no less than twenty-six | |
6298 objects of dodecahedral form which are of Celtic origin.<note>L. Hugo in <I>Comptes rendus</I> of the Paris Acad. of Sciences, lxiii, 1873, | |
6299 pp. 420-1; lxvii, 1875, pp. 433, 472; lxxxi, 1879, p. 332.</note> It | |
6300 may therefore be that Pythagoras or the Pythagoreans had | |
6301 seen dodecahedra of this kind, and that their merit was to | |
6302 have treated them as mathematical objects and brought | |
6303 them into their theoretical geometry. Could they then have | |
6304 <pb n=161><head>THE FIVE REGULAR SOLIDS</head> | |
6305 constructed the regular pentagon? The answer must, I think, | |
6306 be yes. If <I>ABCDE</I> be a regular pentagon, and <I>AC, AD, CE</I> | |
6307 be joined, it is easy to prove, from the (Pythagorean) proposi- | |
6308 tions about the sum of the internal angles of a polygon and | |
6309 <FIG> | |
6310 the sum of the angles of a triangle, that each of the angles | |
6311 <I>BAC, DAE, ECD</I> is 2/5ths of a right angle, whence, in the | |
6312 triangle <I>ACD</I>, the angle <I>CAD</I> is 2/5ths of a right angle, and | |
6313 each of the base angles <I>ACD, ADC</I> is 4/5ths of a right angle | |
6314 or double of the vertical angle <I>CAD</I>; and from these facts | |
6315 it easily follows that, if <I>CE</I> and <I>AD</I> meet in <I>F, CDF</I> is an | |
6316 isosceles triangle equiangular, and therefore similar, to <I>ACD</I>, | |
6317 and also that <MATH><I>AF</I> = <I>FC</I> = <I>CD.</I></MATH> Now, since the triangles | |
6318 <I>ACD, CDF</I> are similar, | |
6319 <MATH><I>AC</I>:<I>CD</I> = <I>CD</I>:<I>DF</I></MATH>, | |
6320 or <MATH><I>AD</I>:<I>AF</I> = <I>AF</I>:<I>FD</I></MATH>; | |
6321 that is, if <I>AD</I> is given, the length of <I>AF</I>, or <I>CD</I>, is found by | |
6322 dividing <I>AD</I> at <I>F</I> in ‘extreme and mean ratio’ by Eucl. II. 11. | |
6323 This last problem is a particular case of the problem of | |
6324 ‘application of areas’, and therefore was obviously within | |
6325 the power of the Pythagoreans. This method of constructing | |
6326 a pentagon is, of course, that taught in Eucl. IV. 10, 11. If | |
6327 further evidence is wanted of the interest of the early Pytha- | |
6328 goreans in the regular pentagon, it is furnished by the fact, | |
6329 attested by Lucian and the scholiast to the <I>Clouds</I> of Aristo- | |
6330 phanes, that the ‘triple interwoven triangle, the pentagram’, | |
6331 i. e. the star-pentagon, was used by the Pythagoreans as a | |
6332 symbol of recognition between the members of the same school, | |
6333 and was called by them Health.<note>Lucian, <I>Pro lapsu in salut.</I> § 5 (vol. i, pp. 447-8, Jacobitz); schol. on | |
6334 <I>Clouds</I> 609.</note> Now it will be seen from the | |
6335 separate diagram of the star-pentagon above that it actually | |
6336 <pb n=162><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
6337 shows the equal sides of the five isosceles triangles of the type | |
6338 referred to and also the points at which they are divided in | |
6339 extreme and mean ratio. (I should perhaps add that the | |
6340 pentagram is said to be found on the vase of Aristonophus | |
6341 found at Caere and supposed to belong to the seventh | |
6342 century B.C., while the finds at Mycenae include ornaments of | |
6343 pentagonal form.) | |
6344 <p>It would be easy to conclude that the dodecahedron is in- | |
6345 scribable in a sphere, and to find the centre of it, without | |
6346 constructing both in the elaborate manner of Eucl. XIII. 17 | |
6347 and working out the relation between an edge of the dodeca- | |
6348 hedron and the radius of the sphere, as is there done: an | |
6349 investigation probably due to Theaetetus. It is right to | |
6350 mention here the remark in scholium No. 1 to Eucl. XIII | |
6351 that the book is about | |
6352 <p>‘the five so-called Platonic figures, which, however, do not | |
6353 belong to Plato, three of the five being due to the Pytha- | |
6354 goreans, namely the cube, the pyramid, and the dodeca- | |
6355 hedron, while the octahedron and icosahedron are due to | |
6356 Theaetetus’.<note>Heiberg's Euclid, vol. v, p. 654.</note> | |
6357 <p>This statement (taken probably from Geminus) may per- | |
6358 haps rest on the fact that Theaetetus was the first to write | |
6359 at any length about the two last-mentioned solids, as he was | |
6360 probably the first to construct all five theoretically and in- | |
6361 vestigate fully their relations to one another and the circum- | |
6362 scribing spheres. | |
6363 <C>(<G>z</G>) <I>Pythagorean astronomy.</I></C> | |
6364 <p>Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans occupy an important place | |
6365 in the history of astronomy. (1) Pythagoras was one of the first | |
6366 to maintain that the universe and the earth are spherical | |
6367 in form. It is uncertain what led Pythagoras to conclude | |
6368 that the earth is a sphere. One suggestion is that he inferred | |
6369 it from the roundness of the shadow cast by the earth in | |
6370 eclipses of the moon. But it is certain that Anaxagoras was | |
6371 the first to suggest this, the true, explanation of eclipses. | |
6372 The most likely supposition is that Pythagoras's ground was | |
6373 purely mathematical, or mathematico-aesthetical; that is, he | |
6374 <pb n=163><head>PYTHAGOREAN ASTRONOMY</head> | |
6375 attributed spherical shape to the earth (as to the universe) | |
6376 for the simple reason that the sphere is the most beautiful | |
6377 of solid figures. For the same reason Pythagoras would | |
6378 surely hold that the sun, the moon, and the other heavenly | |
6379 bodies are also spherical in shape. (2) Pythagoras is credited | |
6380 with having observed the identity of the Morning and the | |
6381 Evening Stars. (3) It is probable that he was the first to | |
6382 state the view (attributed to Alcmaeon and ‘some of the | |
6383 mathematicians’) that the planets as well as the sun and | |
6384 moon have a motion of their own from west to east opposite | |
6385 to and independent of the daily rotation of the sphere of the | |
6386 fixed stars from east to west.<note>Aët. ii. 16. 2, 3 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 132. 15).</note> Hermesianax, one of the older | |
6387 generation of Alexandrine poets (about 300 B.C.), is quoted as | |
6388 saying: | |
6389 <p>‘What inspiration laid forceful hold on Pythagoras when | |
6390 he discovered the subtle geometry of (the heavenly) spirals | |
6391 and compressed in a small sphere the whole of the circle which | |
6392 the aether embraces.’<note>See Athenaeus, xiii. 599 A.</note> | |
6393 <p>This would seem to imply the construction of a sphere | |
6394 on which were represented the circles described by the sun, | |
6395 moon and planets together with the daily revolution of the | |
6396 heavenly sphere; but of course Hermesianax is not altogether | |
6397 a trustworthy authority. | |
6398 <p>It is improbable that Pythagoras himself was responsible | |
6399 for the astronomical system known as the Pythagorean, in | |
6400 which the earth was deposed from its place at rest in the | |
6401 centre of the universe, and became a ‘planet’, like the sun, | |
6402 the moon and the other planets, revolving about the central | |
6403 fire. For Pythagoras the earth was still at the centre, while | |
6404 about it there moved (<I>a</I>) the sphere of the fixed stars revolv- | |
6405 ing daily from east to west, the axis of rotation being a | |
6406 straight line through the centre of the earth, (<I>b</I>) the sun, | |
6407 moon and planets moving in independent circular orbits in | |
6408 a sense opposite to that of the daily rotation, i.e. from west | |
6409 to east. | |
6410 <p>The later Pythagorean system is attributed by Aëtius | |
6411 (probably on the authority of Theophrastus) to Philolaus, and | |
6412 <pb n=164><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
6413 may be described thus. The universe is spherical in shape | |
6414 and finite in size. Outside it is infinite void which enables | |
6415 the universe to breathe, as it were. At the centre is the | |
6416 central fire, the Hearth of the Universe, called by various | |
6417 names, the Tower or Watch-tower of Zeus, the Throne of | |
6418 Zeus, the House of Zeus, the Mother of the Gods, the Altar, | |
6419 Bond and Measure of Nature. In this central fire is located | |
6420 the governing principle, the force which directs the movement | |
6421 and activity of the universe. In the universe there revolve | |
6422 in circles about the central fire the following bodies. Nearest | |
6423 to the central fire revolves the counter-earth, which always | |
6424 accompanies the earth, the orbit of the earth coming next to | |
6425 that of the counter-earth; next to the earth, reckoning in | |
6426 order from the centre outwards, comes the moon, next to the | |
6427 moon the sun, next to the sun the five planets, and last of | |
6428 all, outside the orbits of the five planets, the sphere of the | |
6429 fixed stars. The counter-earth, which accompanies the earth | |
6430 and revolves in a smaller orbit, is not seen by us because | |
6431 the hemisphere of the earth on which we live is turned away | |
6432 from the counter-earth (the analogy of the moon which | |
6433 always turns one side towards us may have suggested this); | |
6434 this involves, incidentally, a rotation of the earth about its | |
6435 axis completed in the same time as it takes the earth to | |
6436 complete a revolution about the central fire. As the latter | |
6437 revolution of the earth was held to produce day and night, | |
6438 it is a natural inference that the earth was supposed to | |
6439 complete one revolution round the central fire in a day and | |
6440 a night, or in twenty-four hours. This motion on the part of | |
6441 the earth with our hemisphere always turned outwards would, | |
6442 of course, be equivalent, as an explanation of phenomena, | |
6443 to a rotation of the earth about a fixed axis, but for the | |
6444 parallax consequent on the earth describing a circle in space | |
6445 with radius greater than its own radius; this parallax, if we | |
6446 may trust Aristotle,<note>Arist. <I>De caelo</I>, ii. 13, 293 b 25-30.</note> the Pythagoreans boldly asserted to be | |
6447 negligible. The superfluous thing in this system is the | |
6448 introduction of the counter-earth. Aristotle says in one | |
6449 place that its object was to bring up the number of the | |
6450 moving bodies to ten, the perfect number according to | |
6451 <pb n=165><head>PYTHAGOREAN ASTRONOMY</head> | |
6452 the Pythagoreans<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> A. 5, 986 a 8-12.</note>; but he hints at the truer explanation in | |
6453 another passage where he says that eclipses of the moon | |
6454 were considered to be due sometimes to the interposition | |
6455 of the earth, sometimes to the interposition of the counter- | |
6456 earth (to say nothing of other bodies of the same sort | |
6457 assumed by ‘some’ in order to explain why there appear | |
6458 to be more lunar eclipses than solar)<note>Arist. <I>De caelo</I>, ii. 13, 293 b 21-5.</note>; we may therefore | |
6459 take it that the counter-earth was invented for the purpose | |
6460 of explaining eclipses of the moon and their frequency. | |
6461 <C>Recapitulation.</C> | |
6462 <p>The astronomical systems of Pythagoras and the Pytha- | |
6463 goreans illustrate the purely mathematical character of their | |
6464 physical speculations; the heavenly bodies are all spheres, | |
6465 the most perfect of solid figures, and they move in circles; | |
6466 there is no question raised of <I>forces</I> causing the respective | |
6467 movements; astronomy is pure mathematics, it is geometry, | |
6468 combined with arithmetic and harmony. The capital dis- | |
6469 covery by Pythagoras of the dependence of musical intervals | |
6470 on numerical proportions led, with his successors, to the | |
6471 doctrine of the ‘harmony of the spheres’. As the ratio | |
6472 2:1 between the lengths of strings of the same substance | |
6473 and at the same tension corresponds to the octave, the | |
6474 ratio 3:2 to the fifth, and the ratio 4:3 to the fourth, it | |
6475 was held that bodies moving in space produce sounds, that | |
6476 those which move more quickly give a higher note than those | |
6477 which move more slowly, while those move most quickly which | |
6478 move at the greatest distance; the sounds therefore pro- | |
6479 duced by the heavenly bodies, depending on their distances | |
6480 (i.e. the size of their orbits), combine to produce a harmony; | |
6481 ‘the whole heaven is number and harmony’.<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> A. 5, 986 a 2.</note> | |
6482 <p>We have seen too how, with the Pythagoreans, the theory | |
6483 of numbers, or ‘arithmetic’, goes hand in hand with geometry; | |
6484 numbers are represented by dots or lines forming geometrical | |
6485 figures; the species of numbers often take their names from | |
6486 their geometrical analogues, while their properties are proved | |
6487 by geometry. The Pythagorean mathematics, therefore, is all | |
6488 one science, and their science is all mathematics. | |
6489 <pb n=166><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY</head> | |
6490 <p>It is this identification of mathematics (and of geometry | |
6491 in particular) with science in general, and their pursuit of it | |
6492 for its own sake, which led to the extraordinary advance of | |
6493 the subject in the Pythagorean school. It was the great merit | |
6494 of Pythagoras himself (apart from any particular geometrical | |
6495 or arithmetical theorems which he discovered) that he was the | |
6496 first to take this view of mathematics; it is characteristic of | |
6497 him that, as we are told, ‘geometry was called by Pythagoras | |
6498 <I>inquiry</I> or <I>science</I>’ (<G>e)kalei=to de\ h( gewmetri/a pro\s *puqago/rou | |
6499 i(stori/a</G>).<note>Iambl. <I>Vit. Pyth.</I> 89.</note> Not only did he make geometry a liberal educa- | |
6500 tion; he was the first to attempt to explore it down to its | |
6501 first principles; as part of the scientific basis which he sought | |
6502 to lay down he ‘used definitions’. A point was, according to | |
6503 the Pythagoreans, a ‘unit having position’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 95. 21.</note>; and, if their | |
6504 method of regarding a line, a surface, a solid, and an angle | |
6505 does not amount to a definition, it at least shows that they | |
6506 had reached a clear idea of the <I>differentiae</I>, as when they said | |
6507 that 1 was a point, 2 a line, 3 a triangle, and 4 a pyramid. | |
6508 A surface they called <G>xroia/</G>, ‘colour’; this was their way of | |
6509 describing the superficial appearance, the idea being, as | |
6510 Aristotle says, that the colour is either in the limiting surface | |
6511 (<G>pe/ras</G>) or is the <G>pe/ras</G>,<note>Arist. <I>De sensu</I>, 3, 439 a 31.</note> so that the meaning intended to be | |
6512 conveyed is precisely that intended by Euclid's definition | |
6513 (XI. Def. 2) that ‘the limit of a solid is a surface’. An angle | |
6514 they called <G>glwxi/s</G>, a ‘point’ (as of an arrow) made by a line | |
6515 broken or bent back at one point.<note>Heron, Def. 15.</note> | |
6516 <p>The positive achievements of the Pythagorean school in | |
6517 geometry, and the immense advance made by them, will be | |
6518 seen from the following summary. | |
6519 <p>1. They were acquainted with the properties of parallel | |
6520 lines, which they used for the purpose of establishing by | |
6521 a general proof the proposition that the sum of the three | |
6522 angles of any triangle is equal to two right angles. This | |
6523 latter proposition they again used to establish the well-known | |
6524 theorems about the sums of the exterior and interior angles, | |
6525 respectively, of any polygon. | |
6526 <p>2. They originated the subject of equivalent areas, the | |
6527 transformation of an area of one form into another of different | |
6528 <pb n=167><head>RECAPITULATION</head> | |
6529 form and, in particular, the whole method of <I>application of | |
6530 areas</I>, constituting a <I>geometrical algebru</I>, whereby they effected | |
6531 the equivalent of the algebraical processes of addition, sub- | |
6532 traction, multiplication, division, squaring, extraction of the | |
6533 square root, and finally the complete solution of the mixed | |
6534 quadratic equation <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>±<I>px</I>±<I>q</I> = 0</MATH>, so far as its roots are real. | |
6535 Expressed in terms of Euclid, this means the whole content of | |
6536 Book I. 35-48 and Book II. The method of <I>application of | |
6537 areas</I> is one of the most fundamental in the whole of later | |
6538 Greek geometry; it takes its place by the side of the powerful | |
6539 method of proportions; moreover, it is the starting point of | |
6540 Apollonius's theory of conics, and the three fundamental | |
6541 terms, <I>parabole, ellipsis</I>, and <I>hyperbole</I> used to describe the | |
6542 three separate problems in ‘application’ were actually em- | |
6543 ployed by Apollonius to denote the three conics, names | |
6544 which, of course, are those which we use to-day. Nor was | |
6545 the use of the geometrical algebra for solving <I>numerical</I> | |
6546 problems unknown to the Pythagoreans; this is proved by | |
6547 the fact that the theorems of Eucl. II. 9, 10 were invented | |
6548 for the purpose of finding successive integral solutions of the | |
6549 indeterminate equations | |
6550 <MATH>2<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP> = ± 1</MATH>. | |
6551 <p>3. They had a theory of proportion pretty fully developed. | |
6552 We know nothing of the form in which it was expounded; | |
6553 all we know is that it took no account of incommensurable | |
6554 magnitudes. Hence we conclude that it was a numerical | |
6555 theory, a theory on the same lines as that contained in | |
6556 Book VII of Euclid's <I>Elements.</I> | |
6557 <p>They were aware of the properties of similar figures. | |
6558 This is clear from the fact that they must be assumed | |
6559 to have solved the problem, which was, according to | |
6560 Plutarch, attributed to Pythagoras himself, of describing a | |
6561 figure which shall be similar to one given figure and equal in | |
6562 area to another given figure This implies a knowledge of | |
6563 the proposition that similar figures (triangles or polygons) are | |
6564 to one another in the duplicate ratio of corresponding sides | |
6565 (Eucl. VI. 19, 20). As the problem is solved in Eucl. VI. 25, | |
6566 we assume that, subject to the qualification that their | |
6567 theorems about similarity, &c., were only established of figures | |
6568 <pb n=168><head>PYTHAGOREAN GEOMETRY.</head> | |
6569 in which corresponding elements are commensurable, they had | |
6570 theorems corresponding to a great part of Eucl., Book VI. | |
6571 <p>Again, they knew how to cut a straight line in extreme and | |
6572 mean ratio (Eucl. VI. 30); this problem was presumably | |
6573 solved by the method used in Eucl. II. 11, rather than by that | |
6574 of Eucl. VI. 30, which depends on the solution of a problem | |
6575 in the application of areas more general than the methods of | |
6576 Book II enable us to solve, the problem namely of Eucl. | |
6577 VI. 29. | |
6578 <p>4. They had discovered, or were aware of the existence of, | |
6579 the five regular solids. These they may have constructed | |
6580 empirically by putting together squares, equilateral triangles, | |
6581 and pentagons. This implies that they could construct a | |
6582 regular pentagon and, as this construction depends upon the | |
6583 construction of an isosceles triangle in which each of the base | |
6584 angles is double of the vertical angle, and this again on the | |
6585 cutting of a line in extreme and mean ratio, we may fairly | |
6586 assume that this was the way in which the construction of | |
6587 the regular pentagon was actually evolved. It would follow | |
6588 that the solution of problems by <I>analysis</I> was already prac- | |
6589 tised by the Pythagoreans, notwithstanding that the discovery | |
6590 of the analytical method is attributed by Proclus to Plato. | |
6591 As the particular construction is practically given in Eucl. IV. | |
6592 10, 11, we may assume that the content of Eucl. IV was also | |
6593 partly Pythagorean. | |
6594 <p>5. They discovered the existence of the irrational in the | |
6595 sense that they proved the incommensurability of the diagonal | |
6596 of a square with reference to its side; in other words, they | |
6597 proved the irrationality of √2. As a proof of this is referred | |
6598 to by Aristotle in terms which correspond to the method | |
6599 used in a proposition interpolated in Euclid, Book X, we | |
6600 may conclude that this proof is ancient, and therefore that it | |
6601 was probably the proof used by the discoverers of the proposi- | |
6602 tion. The method is to prove that, if the diagonal of a square | |
6603 is commensurable with the side, then the same number must | |
6604 be both odd and even; here then we probably have an early | |
6605 Pythagorean use of the method of <I>reductio ad absurdum.</I> | |
6606 <p>Not only did the Pythagoreans discover the irrationality | |
6607 of √2; they showed, as we have seen, how to approximate | |
6608 as closely as we please to its numerical value. | |
6609 <pb n=169><head>RECAPITULATION</head> | |
6610 <p>After the discovery of this one case of irrationality, it | |
6611 would be obvious that propositions theretofore proved by | |
6612 means of the numerical theory of proportion, which was | |
6613 inapplicable to incommensurable magnitudes, were only par- | |
6614 tially proved. Accordingly, pending the discovery of a theory | |
6615 of proportion applicable to incommensurable as well as com- | |
6616 mensurable magnitudes, there would be an inducement to | |
6617 substitute, where possible, for proofs employing the theory of | |
6618 proportions other proofs independent of that theory. This | |
6619 substitution is carried rather far in Euclid, Books I-IV; it | |
6620 does not follow that the Pythagoreans remodelled their proofs | |
6621 to the same extent as Euclid felt bound to do. | |
6622 <pb> | |
6623 <C>VI</C> | |
6624 <C>PROGRESS IN THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO | |
6625 PLATO'S TIME</C> | |
6626 <p>IN tracing the further progress in the Elements which took | |
6627 place down to the time of Plato, we do not get much assistance | |
6628 from the summary of Proclus. The passage in which he | |
6629 states the succession of geometers from Pythagoras to Plato | |
6630 and his contemporaries runs as follows: | |
6631 <p>‘After him [Pythagoras] Anaxagoras of Clazomenae dealt | |
6632 with many questions in geometry, and so did Oenopides of | |
6633 Chios, who was a little younger than Anaxagoras; Plato | |
6634 himself alludes, in the <I>Rivals,</I> to both of them as having | |
6635 acquired a reputation for mathematics. After them came | |
6636 Hippocrates of Chios, the discoverer of the quadrature of | |
6637 the lune, and Theodorus of Cyrene, both of whom became | |
6638 distinguished geometers; Hippocrates indeed was the first | |
6639 of whom it is recorded that he actually compiled Elements. | |
6640 Plato, who came next to them, caused mathematics in general | |
6641 and geometry in particular to make a very great advance, | |
6642 owing to his own zeal for these studies; for every one knows | |
6643 that he even filled his writings with mathematical discourses | |
6644 and strove on every occasion to arouse enthusiasm for mathe- | |
6645 matics in those who took up philosophy. At this time too | |
6646 lived Leodamas of Thasos, Archytas of Taras, and Theaetetus | |
6647 of Athens, by whom the number of theorems was increased | |
6648 and a further advance was made towards a more scientific | |
6649 grouping of them.’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 65. 21-66. 18.</note> | |
6650 <p>It will be seen that we have here little more than a list of | |
6651 names of persons who advanced, or were distinguished in, | |
6652 geometry. There is no mention of specific discoveries made | |
6653 by particular geometers, except that the work of Hippocrates | |
6654 on the squaring of certain lunes is incidentally alluded to, | |
6655 rather as a means of identifying Hippocrates than as a de- | |
6656 tail relevant to the subject in hand. It would appear that | |
6657 <pb n=171><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
6658 the whole summary was directed to the one object of trac- | |
6659 ing progress in the Elements, particularly with reference | |
6660 to improvements of method in the direction of greater | |
6661 generality and more scientific order and treatment; hence | |
6662 only those writers are here mentioned who contributed to this | |
6663 development. Hippocrates comes into the list, not because | |
6664 of his lunes, but because he was a distinguished geometer | |
6665 and was the first to write Elements. Hippias of Elis, on the | |
6666 other hand, though he belongs to the period covered by the | |
6667 extract, is omitted, presumably because his great discovery, | |
6668 that of the curve known as the <I>quadratrix,</I> does not belong | |
6669 to elementary geometry; Hippias is, however, mentioned in | |
6670 two other places by Proclus in connexion with the quadratrix,<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 272. 7, p. 356. 11.</note> | |
6671 and once more as authority for the geometrical achievements | |
6672 of Ameristus (or Mamercus or Mamertius).<note><I>Ib.,</I> p. 65. 14.</note> Less justice is | |
6673 done to Democritus, who is neither mentioned here nor else- | |
6674 where in the commentary; the omission here of the name | |
6675 of Democritus is one of the arguments for the view that | |
6676 this part of the summary is not quoted from the <I>History | |
6677 of Geometry</I> by Eudemus (who would not have been likely to | |
6678 omit so accomplished a mathematician as Democritus), but | |
6679 is the work either of an intermediary or of Proclus himself, | |
6680 based indeed upon data from Eudemus's history, but limited to | |
6681 particulars relevant to the object of the commentary, that | |
6682 is to say, the elucidation of Euclid and the story of the growth | |
6683 of the Elements. | |
6684 <p>There are, it is true, elsewhere in Proclus's commentary | |
6685 a very few cases in which particular propositions in Euclid, | |
6686 Book I, are attributed to individual geometers, e.g. those | |
6687 which Thales is said to have discovered. Two propositions | |
6688 presently to be mentioned are in like manner put to the | |
6689 account of Oenopides; but except for these details about | |
6690 Oenopides we have to look elsewhere for evidence of the | |
6691 growth of the Elements in the period now under notice. | |
6692 Fortunately we possess a document of capital importance, | |
6693 from this point of view, in the fragment of Eudemus on | |
6694 Hippocrates's quadrature of lunes preserved in Simplicius's | |
6695 commentary on the <I>Physics</I> of Aristotle.<note>Simpl. <I>in Arist. Phys.</I> pp. 54-69 Diels.</note> This fragment will | |
6696 <pb n=172><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
6697 be described below. Meantime we will take the names men- | |
6698 tioned by Proclus in their order. | |
6699 <p>ANAXAGORAS (about 500-428 B.C.) was born at Clazomenae | |
6700 in the neighbourhood of Smyrna. He neglected his posses- | |
6701 sions, which were considerable, in order to devote himself | |
6702 to science. Some one once asked him what was the object | |
6703 of being born, to which he replied, ‘The investigation of sun, | |
6704 moon and heaven.’ He was apparently the first philosopher | |
6705 to take up his abode at Athens, where he enjoyed the friend- | |
6706 ship of Pericles. When Pericles became unpopular shortly | |
6707 before the outbreak of the Peloponnesian War, he was attacked | |
6708 through his friends, and Anaxagoras was accused of impiety | |
6709 for holding that the sun was a red-hot stone and the moon | |
6710 earth. According to one account he was fined five talents | |
6711 and banished; another account says that he was kept in | |
6712 prison and that it was intended to put him to death, but | |
6713 that Pericles obtained his release; he went and lived at | |
6714 Lampsacus till his death. | |
6715 <p>Little or nothing is known of Anaxagoras's achievements | |
6716 in mathematics proper, though it is credible enough that | |
6717 he was a good mathematician. But in astronomy he made | |
6718 one epoch-making discovery, besides putting forward some | |
6719 remarkably original theories about the evolution of the | |
6720 universe. We owe to him the first clear recognition of the | |
6721 fact that the moon does not shine by its own light but | |
6722 receives its light from the sun; this discovery enabled him | |
6723 to give the true explanation of lunar and solar eclipses, | |
6724 though as regards the former (perhaps in order to explain | |
6725 their greater frequency) he erroneously supposed that there | |
6726 were other opaque and invisible bodies ‘below the moon’ | |
6727 which, as well as the earth, sometimes by their interposition | |
6728 caused eclipses of the moon. A word should be added about | |
6729 his cosmology on account of the fruitful ideas which it con- | |
6730 tained. According to him the formation of the world began | |
6731 with a vortex set up, in a portion of the mixed mass in which | |
6732 ‘all things were together’, by Mind (<G>nou=s</G>). This rotatory | |
6733 movement began in the centre and then gradually spread, | |
6734 taking in wider and wider circles. The first effect was to | |
6735 separate two great masses, one consisting of the rare, hot, | |
6736 light, dry, called the ‘aether’, the other of the opposite | |
6737 <pb n=173><head>ANAXAGORAS</head> | |
6738 categories and called ‘air’. The aether took the outer, the | |
6739 air the inner place. From the air were next separated clouds, | |
6740 water, earth and stones. The dense, the moist, the dark and | |
6741 cold, and all the heaviest things, collected in the centre as the | |
6742 result of the circular motion, and it was from these elements | |
6743 when consolidated that the earth was formed; but after this, | |
6744 in consequence of the violence of the whirling motion, the | |
6745 surrounding fiery aether tore stones away from the earth and | |
6746 kindled them into stars. Taking this in conjunction with | |
6747 the remark that stones ‘rush outwards more than water’, | |
6748 we see that Anaxagoras conceived the idea of a <I>centrifugal</I> | |
6749 force as well as that of concentration brought about by the | |
6750 motion of the vortex, and that he assumed a series of pro- | |
6751 jections or ‘whirlings-off’ of precisely the same kind as the | |
6752 theory of Kant and Laplace assumed for the formation of | |
6753 the solar system. At the same time he held that one of the | |
6754 heavenly bodies might break away and fall (this may account | |
6755 for the story that he prophesied the fall of the meteoric stone | |
6756 at Aegospotami in 468/7 B.C.), a <I>centripetal</I> tendency being | |
6757 here recognized. | |
6758 <p>In mathematics we are told that Anaxagoras ‘while in | |
6759 prison wrote (or drew, <G>e)/grafe</G>) the squaring of the circle’.<note>Plutarch, <I>De exil.</I> 17, 607 F.</note> | |
6760 But we have no means of judging what this amounted to. | |
6761 Rudio translates <G>e)/grafe</G> as ‘zeichnete’, ‘drew’, observing that | |
6762 he probably knew the Egyptian rule for squaring, and simply | |
6763 drew on the sand a square as nearly as he could equal to the | |
6764 area of a circle.<note>Rudio, <I>Der Bericht des Simplicius über die Quadraturen des Antiphon | |
6765 und Hippokrates,</I> 1907, p. 92, 93.</note> It is clear to me that this cannot be right, | |
6766 but that the word means ‘wrote upon’ in the sense that he | |
6767 tried to work out theoretically the problem in question. For | |
6768 the same word occurs (in the passive) in the extract from | |
6769 Eudemus about Hippocrates: ‘The squarings of the lunes ... | |
6770 were first written (or proved) by Hippocrates and were found | |
6771 to be correctly expounded’,<note>Simpl. <I>in Phys.,</I> p. 61. 1-3 Diels; Rudio, <I>op. cit.,</I> pp. 46. 22-48. 4.</note> where the context shows that | |
6772 <G>e)gra/fhsan</G> cannot merely mean ‘were drawn’. Besides, | |
6773 <G>tetragwnismo/s</G>, <I>squaring,</I> is a process or operation, and you | |
6774 cannot, properly speaking, ‘draw’ a process, though you can | |
6775 ‘describe’ it or prove its correctness. | |
6776 <pb n=174><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
6777 <p>Vitruvius tells us that one Agatharchus was the first to paint | |
6778 stage-scenes at Athens, at the time when Aeschylus was | |
6779 having his tragedies performed, and that he left a treatise on | |
6780 the subject which was afterwards a guide to Democritus and | |
6781 Anaxagoras, who discussed the same problem, namely that of | |
6782 painting objects on a plane surface in such a way as to make | |
6783 some of the things depicted appear to be in the background | |
6784 while others appeared to stand out in the foreground, so that | |
6785 you seemed, e.g., to have real buildings before you; in other | |
6786 words, Anaxagoras and Democritus both wrote treatises on | |
6787 perspective.<note>Vitruvius, <I>De architectura,</I> vii. praef. 11.</note> | |
6788 <p>There is not much to be gathered from the passage in | |
6789 the <I>Rivals</I> to which Proclus refers. Socrates, on entering the | |
6790 school of Dionysius, finds two lads disputing a certain point, | |
6791 something about Anaxagoras or Oenopides, he was not certain | |
6792 which; but they appeared to be drawing circles, and to be | |
6793 imitating certain inclinations by placing their hands at an | |
6794 angle.<note>Plato, <I>Erastae</I> 132 A, B.</note> Now this description suggests that what the lads | |
6795 were trying to represent was the circles of the equator and | |
6796 the zodiac or ecliptic; and we know that in fact Eudemus | |
6797 in his <I>History of Astronomy</I> attributed to Oenopides the dis- | |
6798 covery of ‘the cincture of the zodiac circle’,<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 198. 14.</note> which must mean | |
6799 the discovery of the obliquity of the ecliptic. It would prob- | |
6800 ably be unsafe to conclude that Anaxagoras was also credited | |
6801 with the same discovery, but it certainly seems to be suggested | |
6802 that Anaxagoras had to some extent touched the mathematics | |
6803 of astronomy. | |
6804 <p>OENOPIDES OF CHIOS was primarily an astronomer. This | |
6805 is shown not only by the reference of Eudemus just cited, but | |
6806 by a remark of Proclus in connexion with one of two proposi- | |
6807 tions in elementary geometry attributed to him.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 283. 7-8.</note> Eudemus | |
6808 is quoted as saying that he not only discovered the obliquity | |
6809 of the ecliptic, but also the period of a Great Year. Accord- | |
6810 ing to Diodorus the Egyptian priests claimed that it was from | |
6811 them that Oenopides learned that the sun moves in an inclined | |
6812 orbit and in a sense opposite to the motion of the fixed stars. | |
6813 It does not appear that Oenopides made any measurement of | |
6814 <pb n=175><head>OENOPIDES OF CHIOS</head> | |
6815 the obliquity of the ecliptic. The duration of the Great Year | |
6816 he is said to have put at 59 years, while he made the length | |
6817 of the year itself to be 365 22/59 days. His Great Year clearly | |
6818 had reference to the sun and moon only; he merely sought to | |
6819 find the least integral number of complete years which would | |
6820 contain an exact number of lunar months. Starting, probably, | |
6821 with 365 days as the length of a year and 29 1/2 days as the | |
6822 length of a lunar month, approximate values known before | |
6823 his time, he would see that twice 29 1/2, or 59, years would con- | |
6824 tain twice 365, or 730, lunar months. He may then, from his | |
6825 knowledge of the calendar, have obtained 21,557 as the num- | |
6826 ber of days in 730 months, for 21,557 when divided by 59 gives | |
6827 365 22/59 as the number of days in the year. | |
6828 <p>Of Oenopides's geometry we have no details, except that | |
6829 Proclus attributes to him two propositions in Eucl. Bk. I. Of | |
6830 I. 12 (‘to draw a perpendicular to a given straight line from | |
6831 a point outside it’) Proclus says: | |
6832 <p>‘This problem was first investigated by Oenopides, who | |
6833 thought it useful for astronomy. He, however, calls the per- | |
6834 pendicular in the archaic manner (a straight line drawn) | |
6835 <I>gnomon-wise</I> (<G>kata\ gnw/mona</G>), because the gnomon is also at | |
6836 right angles to the horizon.’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 283. 7-8.</note> | |
6837 <p>On I. 23 (‘on a given straight line and at a given point on | |
6838 it to construct a rectilineal angle equal to a given rectilineal | |
6839 angle’) Proclus remarks that this problem is ‘rather the dis- | |
6840 covery of Oenopides, as Eudemus says’.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 333. 5.</note> It is clear that the | |
6841 geometrical reputation of Oenopides could not have rested on | |
6842 the mere solution of such simple problems as these. Nor, of | |
6843 course, could he have been the first to draw a perpendicular in | |
6844 practice; the point may be that he was the first to solve the | |
6845 problem by means of the ruler and compasses only, whereas | |
6846 presumably, in earlier days, perpendiculars would be drawn | |
6847 by means of a set square or a right-angled triangle originally | |
6848 constructed, say, with sides proportional to 3, 4, 5. Similarly | |
6849 Oenopides may have been the first to give the theoretical, | |
6850 rather than the practical, construction for the problem of I. 23 | |
6851 which we find in Euclid. It may therefore be that Oenopides's | |
6852 significance lay in improvements of method from the point of | |
6853 view of theory; he may, for example, have been the first to | |
6854 <pb n=176><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
6855 lay down the restriction of the means permissible in construc- | |
6856 tions to the ruler and compasses which became a canon of | |
6857 Greek geometry for all ‘plane’ constructions, i.e. for all | |
6858 problems involving the equivalent of the solution of algebraical | |
6859 equations of degree not higher than the second. | |
6860 <p>DEMOCRITUS, as mathematician, may be said to have at last | |
6861 come into his own. In the <I>Method</I> of Archimedes, happily | |
6862 discovered in 1906, we are told that Democritus was the first | |
6863 to state the important propositions that the volume of a cone | |
6864 is one third of that of a cylinder having the same base and | |
6865 equal height, and that the volume of a pyramid is one third of | |
6866 that of a prism having the same base and equal height; that is | |
6867 to say, Democritus enunciated these propositions some fifty | |
6868 years or more before they were first scientifically proved by | |
6869 Eudoxus. | |
6870 <p>Democritus came from Abdera, and, according to his own | |
6871 account, was young when Anaxagoras was old. Apollodorus | |
6872 placed his birth in Ol. 80 (= 460-457 B.C.), while according | |
6873 to Thrasyllus he was born in Ol. 77. 3 (= 470/69 B.C.), being | |
6874 one year older than Socrates. He lived to a great age, 90 | |
6875 according to Diodorus, 104, 108, 109 according to other | |
6876 authorities. He was indeed, as Thrasyllus called him, | |
6877 <G>pe/ntaqlos</G> in philosophy<note>Diog. L. ix. 37 (<I>Vors.</I> ii<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 11. 24-30).</note>; there was no subject to which he | |
6878 did not notably contribute, from mathematics and physics on | |
6879 the one hand to ethics and poetics on the other; he even went | |
6880 by the name of ‘Wisdom’ (<G>*sofi/a</G>).<note>Clem. <I>Strom.</I> vi. 32 (<I>Vors.</I> ii<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 16. 28).</note> Plato, of course, ignores | |
6881 him throughout his dialogues, and is said to have wished to | |
6882 burn all his works; Aristotle, on the other hand, pays | |
6883 handsome tribute to his genius, observing, e.g., that on the | |
6884 subject of change and growth no one save Democritus had | |
6885 observed anything except superficially; whereas Democritus | |
6886 seemed to have thought of everything.<note>Arist. <I>De gen. et corr.</I> i. 2, 315 a 35.</note> He could say | |
6887 of himself (the fragment is, it is true, considered by Diels | |
6888 to be spurious, while Gomperz held it to be genuine), ‘Of | |
6889 all my contemporaries I have covered the most ground in | |
6890 my travels, making the most exhaustive inquiries the while; | |
6891 I have seen the most climates and countries and listened to | |
6892 <pb n=177><head>DEMOCRITUS</head> | |
6893 the greatest number of learned men’.<note>Clement, <I>Strom.</I> i. 15, 69 (<I>Vors.</I> ii<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 123. 3).</note> His travels lasted for | |
6894 five years, and he is said to have visited Egypt, Persia and | |
6895 Babylon, where he consorted with the priests and magi; some | |
6896 say that he went to India and Aethiopia also. Well might | |
6897 he undertake the compilation of a geographical survey of | |
6898 the earth as, after Anaximander, Hecataeus of Miletus and | |
6899 Damastes of Sigeum had done. In his lifetime his fame was | |
6900 far from world-wide: ‘I came to Athens’, he says, ‘and no | |
6901 one knew me.’<note>Diog. L. ix. 36 (<I>Vors.</I> ii<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 11. 22).</note> | |
6902 <p>A long list of his writings is preserved in Diogenes Laertius, | |
6903 the authority being Thrasyllus. In astronomy he wrote, | |
6904 among other works, a book <I>On the Planets,</I> and another <I>On | |
6905 the Great Year or Astronomy</I> including a <I>parapegma</I><note>The <I>parapegma</I> was a posted record, a kind of almanac, giving, for | |
6906 a series of years, the movements of the sun, the dates of the phases of | |
6907 the moon, the risings and settings of certain stars, besides <G>e)pishmasi/ai</G> | |
6908 or weather indications; many details from Democritus's <I>parapegma</I> | |
6909 are preserved in the Calendar at the end of Geminus's <I>Isagoge</I> and in | |
6910 Ptolemy.</note> (or | |
6911 calendar). Democritus made the order of the heavenly bodies, | |
6912 reckoning outwards from the earth, the following: Moon, | |
6913 Venus, Sun, the other planets, the fixed stars. Lucretius<note>Lucretius, v. 621 sqq.</note> has | |
6914 preserved an interesting explanation which he gave of the | |
6915 reason why the sun takes a year to describe the full circle of | |
6916 the zodiac, while the moon completes its circle in a month. | |
6917 The nearer any body is to the earth (and therefore the farther | |
6918 from the sphere of the fixed stars) the less swiftly can it be | |
6919 carried round by the revolution of the heaven. Now the | |
6920 moon is nearer than the sun, and the sun than the signs of | |
6921 the zodiac; therefore the moon seems to get round faster than | |
6922 the sun because, while the sun, being lower and therefore | |
6923 slower than the signs, is left behind by them, the moon,. | |
6924 being still lower and therefore slower still, is still more left | |
6925 behind. Democritus's Great Year is described by Censorinus<note><I>De die natali,</I> 18. 8.</note> | |
6926 as 82 (LXXXII) years including 28 intercalary months, the | |
6927 latter number being the same as that included by Callippus in | |
6928 his cycle of 76 years; it is therefore probable that LXXXII | |
6929 is an incorrect reading for LXXVII (77). | |
6930 <p>As regards his mathematics we have first the statement in | |
6931 <pb n=178><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
6932 the continuation of the fragment of doubtful authenticity | |
6933 already quoted that | |
6934 <p>‘in the putting together of lines, with the necessary proof, no | |
6935 one has yet surpassed me, not even the so-called <I>harpedon- | |
6936 aptae</I> (rope-stretchers) of Egypt’. | |
6937 <p>This does not tell us much, except that it indicates that | |
6938 the ‘rope-stretchers’, whose original function was land- | |
6939 measuring or practical geometry, had by Democritus's time | |
6940 advanced some way in theoretical geometry (a fact which the | |
6941 surviving documents, such as the book of Ahmes, with their | |
6942 merely practical rules, would not have enabled us to infer). | |
6943 However, there is no reasonable doubt that in geometry | |
6944 Democritus was fully abreast of the knowledge of his day; | |
6945 this is fully confirmed by the titles of treatises by him and | |
6946 from other sources. The titles of the works classed as mathe- | |
6947 matical are (besides the astronomical works above mentioned): | |
6948 <p>1. <I>On a difference of opinion</I> (<G>gnw/mhs</G>: <I>v. l.</I> <G>gnw/monos</G>, gno- | |
6949 mon), <I>or on the contact of a circle and a sphere;</I> | |
6950 <p>2. <I>On Geometry;</I> | |
6951 <p>3. <I>Geometricorum</I> (?I, II); | |
6952 <p>4. <I>Numbers;</I> | |
6953 <p>5. <I>On irrational lines and solids</I> (<G>nastw=n</G>, atoms?); | |
6954 <p>6. <G>*)ekpeta/smata</G>. | |
6955 <p>As regards the first of these works I think that the | |
6956 attempts to extract a sense out of Cobet's reading <G>gnw/monos</G> | |
6957 (on a difference of a gnomon) have failed, and that <G>gnw/mhs</G> | |
6958 (Diels) is better. But ‘On a difference of opinion’ seems | |
6959 scarcely determinative enough, if this was really an alternative | |
6960 title to the book. We know that there were controversies in | |
6961 ancient times about the nature of the ‘angle of contact’ (the | |
6962 ‘angle’ formed, at the point of contact, between an arc of | |
6963 a circle and the tangent to it, which angle was called by the | |
6964 special name <I>hornlike,</I> <G>keratoeidh/s</G>), and the ‘angle’ comple- | |
6965 mentary to it (the ‘angle of a semicircle’).<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, pp. 121. 24-122. 6.</note> The question was | |
6966 whether the ‘hornlike angle’ was a magnitude comparable | |
6967 with the rectilineal angle, i.e. whether by being multiplied | |
6968 a sufficient number of times it could be made to exceed a | |
6969 <pb n=179><head>DEMOCRITUS</head> | |
6970 given rectilineal angle. Euclid proved (in III. 16) that the | |
6971 ‘angle of contact’ is less than any rectilineal angle, thereby | |
6972 setting the question at rest. This is the only reference in | |
6973 Euclid to this angle and the ‘angle <I>of</I> a semicircle’, although | |
6974 he defines the ‘angle <I>of</I> a segment’ in III, Def. 7, and has | |
6975 statements about the angles <I>of</I> segments in III. 31. But we | |
6976 know from a passage of Aristotle that before his time ‘angles | |
6977 <I>of</I> segments’ came into geometrical text-books as elements in | |
6978 figures which could be used in the proofs of propositions<note>Arist. <I>Anal. Pr.</I> i. 24, 41 b 13-22.</note>; | |
6979 thus e.g. the equality of the two angles <I>of</I> a segment | |
6980 (assumed as known) was used to prove the theorem of | |
6981 Eucl. I. 5. Euclid abandoned the use of all such angles in | |
6982 proofs, and the references to them above mentioned are only | |
6983 survivals. The controversies doubtless arose long before his | |
6984 time, and such a question as the nature of the contact of | |
6985 a circle with its tangent would probably have a fascination | |
6986 for Democritus, who, as we shall see, broached other questions | |
6987 involving infinitesimals. As, therefore, the questions of the | |
6988 nature of the contact of a circle with its tangent and of the | |
6989 character of the ‘hornlike’ angle are obviously connected, | |
6990 I prefer to read <G>gwni/hs</G> (‘of an angle’) instead of <G>gnw/mhs</G>; this | |
6991 would give the perfectly comprehensible title, ‘<I>On a difference | |
6992 in an angle, or on the contact of a circle and a sphere</I>’. We | |
6993 know from Aristotle that Protagoras, who wrote a book on | |
6994 mathematics, <G>peri\ tw=n maqhma/twn</G>, used against the geometers | |
6995 the argument that no such straight lines and circles as | |
6996 they assume exist in nature, and that (e.g.) a material circle | |
6997 does not in actual fact touch a ruler at one point only<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> B. 2, 998 a 2.</note>; and | |
6998 it seems probable that Democritus's work was directed against | |
6999 this sort of attack on geometry. | |
7000 <p>We know nothing of the contents of Democritus's book | |
7001 <I>On Geometry</I> or of his <I>Geometrica.</I> One or other of these | |
7002 works may possibly have contained the famous dilemma about | |
7003 sections of a cone parallel to the base and very close together, | |
7004 which Plutarch gives on the authority of Chrysippus.<note>Plutarch, <I>De comm. not. adv. Stoicos,</I> xxxix. 3.</note> | |
7005 <p>‘If’, said Democritus, ‘a cone were cut by a plane parallel | |
7006 to the base [by which is clearly meant a plane indefinitely | |
7007 <pb n=180><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7008 near to the base], what must we think of the surfaces forming | |
7009 the sections? Are they equal or unequal? For, if they are | |
7010 unequal, they will make the cone irregular as having many | |
7011 indentations, like steps, and unevennesses; but, if they are | |
7012 equal, the sections will be equal, and the cone will appear to | |
7013 have the property of the cylinder and to be made up of equal, | |
7014 not unequal, circles, which is very absurd.’ | |
7015 <p>The phrase ‘<I>made up</I> of equal ... circles’ shows that | |
7016 Democritus already had the idea of a solid being the sum of | |
7017 an infinite number of parallel planes, or indefinitely thin | |
7018 laminae, indefinitely near together: a most important an- | |
7019 ticipation of the same thought which led to such fruitful | |
7020 results in Archimedes. This idea may be at the root of the | |
7021 argument by which Democritus satisfied himself of the truth | |
7022 of the two propositions attributed to him by Archimedes, | |
7023 namely that a cone is one third part of the cylinder, and | |
7024 a pyramid one third of the prism, which has the same base | |
7025 and equal height. For it seems probable that Democritus | |
7026 would notice that, if two pyramids having the same height | |
7027 and equal triangular bases are respectively cut by planes | |
7028 parallel to the base and dividing the heights in the same | |
7029 ratio, the corresponding sections of the two pyramids are | |
7030 equal, whence he would infer that the pyramids are equal as | |
7031 being the sum of the same infinite number of equal plane | |
7032 sections or indefinitely thin laminae. (This would be a par- | |
7033 ticular anticipation of Cavalieri's proposition that the areal or | |
7034 solid content of two figures is equal if two sections of them | |
7035 taken at the same height, whatever the height may be, always | |
7036 give equal straight lines or equal surfaces respectively.) And | |
7037 Democritus would of course see that the three pyramids into | |
7038 which a prism on the same base and of equal height with the | |
7039 original pyramid is divided (as in Eucl. XII. 7) satisfy this | |
7040 test of equality, so that the pyramid would be one third part | |
7041 of the prism. The extension to a pyramid with a polygonal | |
7042 base would be easy. And Democritus may have stated the | |
7043 proposition for the cone (of course without an absolute proof) | |
7044 as a natural inference from the result of increasing indefinitely | |
7045 the number of sides in a regular polygon forming the base of | |
7046 a pyramid. | |
7047 <p>Tannery notes the interesting fact that the order in the list | |
7048 <pb n=181><head>DEMOCRITUS</head> | |
7049 of Democritus's works of the treatises <I>On Geometry, Geometrica, | |
7050 Numbers,</I> and <I>On irrational lines and solids</I> corresponds to | |
7051 the order of the separate sections of Euclid's <I>Elements,</I> Books | |
7052 I-VI (plane geometry), Books VII-IX (on numbers), and | |
7053 Book X (on irrationals). With regard to the work <I>On irra- | |
7054 tional lines and solids</I> it is to be observed that, inasmuch as | |
7055 his investigation of the cone had brought Democritus con- | |
7056 sciously face to face with infinitesimals, there is nothing | |
7057 surprising in his having written on irrationals; on the con- | |
7058 trary, the subject is one in which he would be likely to take | |
7059 special interest. It is useless to speculate on what the treatise | |
7060 actually contained; but of one thing we may be sure, namely | |
7061 that the <G>a)/logoi grammai/</G>, ‘irrational lines’, were not <G>a)/tomoi | |
7062 grammai/</G>, ‘<I>indivisible</I> lines’.<note>On this cf. O. Apelt, <I>Beiträge zur Geschichte der griechischen Philo- | |
7063 sophie,</I> 1891, p. 265 sq.</note> Democritus was too good a | |
7064 mathematician to have anything to do with such a theory. | |
7065 We do not know what answer he gave to his puzzle about the | |
7066 cone; but his statement of the dilemma shows that he was | |
7067 fully alive to the difficulties connected with the conception of | |
7068 the continuous as illustrated by the particular case, and he | |
7069 cannot have solved it, in a sense analogous to his physical | |
7070 theory of atoms, by assuming indivisible lines, for this would | |
7071 have involved the inference that the consecutive parallel | |
7072 sections of the cone are <I>unequal,</I> in which case the surface | |
7073 would (as he said) be discontinuous, forming steps, as it were. | |
7074 Besides, we are told by Simplicius that, according to Demo- | |
7075 critus himself, his atoms were, in a mathematical sense | |
7076 divisible further and in fact <I>ad infinitum,</I><note>Simpl. <I>in Phys.,</I> p. 83. 5.</note> while the scholia | |
7077 to Aristotle's <I>De caelo</I> implicitly deny to Democritus any | |
7078 theory of indivisible lines: ‘of those who have maintained | |
7079 the existence of indivisibles, some, as for example Leucippus | |
7080 and Democritus, believe in indivisible bodies, others, like | |
7081 Xenocrates, in indivisible lines’.<note>Scholia in Arist., p. 469 b 14, Brandis.</note> | |
7082 <p>With reference to the <G>*)ekpeta/smata</G> it is to be noted that | |
7083 this word is explained in Ptolemy's <I>Geography</I> as the projec- | |
7084 tion of the armillary sphere upon a plane.<note>Ptolemy, <I>Geogr.</I> vii. 7.</note> This work and | |
7085 that <I>On irrational lines</I> would hardly belong to elementary | |
7086 geometry. | |
7087 <pb n=182><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7088 <p>HIPPIAS OF ELIS, the famous sophist already mentioned (pp. 2, | |
7089 23-4), was nearly contemporary with Socrates and Prodicus, | |
7090 and was probably born about 460 B.C. Chronologically, there- | |
7091 fore, his place would be here, but the only particular discovery | |
7092 attributed to him is that of the curve afterwards known as | |
7093 the <I>quadratrix,</I> and the <I>quadratrix</I> does not come within the | |
7094 scope of the <I>Elements.</I> It was used first for trisecting any | |
7095 rectilineal angle or, more generally, for dividing it in any | |
7096 ratio whatever, and secondly for squaring the circle, or rather | |
7097 for finding the length of any arc of a circle; and these prob- | |
7098 lems are not what the Greeks called ‘plane’ problems, i.e. | |
7099 they cannot be solved by means of the ruler and compasses. | |
7100 It is true that some have denied that the Hippias who | |
7101 invented the <I>quadratrix</I> can have been Hippias of Elis; | |
7102 Blass<note>Fleckeisen's <I>Jahrbuch,</I> cv, p. 28.</note> and Apelt<note><I>Beiträge zur Gesch. d. gr. Philosophie,</I> p. 379.</note> were of this opinion, Apelt arguing that at | |
7103 the time of Hippias geometry had not got far beyond the | |
7104 theorem of Pythagoras. To show how wide of the mark this | |
7105 last statement is we have only to think of the achievements | |
7106 of Democritus. We know, too, that Hippias the sophist | |
7107 specialized in mathematics, and I agree with Cantor and | |
7108 Tannery that there is no reason to doubt that it was he who | |
7109 discovered the <I>quadratrix.</I> This curve will be best described | |
7110 when we come to deal with the problem of squaring the circle | |
7111 (Chapter VII); here we need only remark that it implies the | |
7112 proposition that the lengths of arcs in a circle are proportional | |
7113 to the angles subtended by them at the centre (Eucl. VI. 33). | |
7114 <p>The most important name from the point of view of this | |
7115 chapter is HIPPOCRATES OF CHIOS. He is indeed the first | |
7116 person of whom it is recorded that he compiled a book of | |
7117 Elements. This is lost, but Simplicius has preserved in his | |
7118 commentary on the <I>Physics</I> of Aristotle a fragment from | |
7119 Eudemus's <I>History of Geometry</I> giving an account of Hippo- | |
7120 crates's quadratures of certain ‘lunules’ or lunes.<note>Simpl. <I>in Phys.,</I> pp. 60. 22-68. 32, Diels.</note> This is one | |
7121 of the most precious sources for the history of Greek geometry | |
7122 before Euclid; and, as the methods, with one slight apparent | |
7123 exception, are those of the straight line and circle, we can | |
7124 form a good idea of the progress which had been made in the | |
7125 Elements up to Hippocrates's time. | |
7126 <pb n=183><head>HIPPOCRATES OF CHIOS</head> | |
7127 <p>It would appear that Hippocrates was in Athens during | |
7128 a considerable portion of the second half of the fifth century, | |
7129 perhaps from 450 to 430 B.C. We have quoted the story that | |
7130 what brought him there was a suit to recover a large sum | |
7131 which he had lost, in the course of his trading operations, | |
7132 through falling in with pirates; he is said to have remained | |
7133 in Athens on this account a long time, during which he con- | |
7134 sorted with the philosophers and reached such a degree of | |
7135 proficiency in geometry that he tried to discover a method of | |
7136 squaring the circle.<note>Philop. <I>in Phys.,</I> p. 31. 3, Vitelli.</note> This is of course an allusion to the | |
7137 quadratures of lunes. | |
7138 <p>Another important discovery is attributed to Hippocrates. | |
7139 He was the first to observe that the problem of doubling the | |
7140 cube is reducible to that of finding two mean proportionals in | |
7141 continued proportion between two straight lines.<note>Pseudo-Eratosthenes to King Ptolemy in Eutoc. on Archimedes (vol. | |
7142 iii, p. 88, Heib.).</note> The effect | |
7143 of this was, as Proclus says, that thenceforward people | |
7144 addressed themselves (exclusively) to the equivalent problem | |
7145 of finding two mean proportionals between two straight lines.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 213. 5.</note> | |
7146 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Hippocrates's quadrature of lunes.</I></C> | |
7147 <p>I will now give the details of the extract from Eudemus on | |
7148 the subject of Hippocrates's quadrature of lunes, which (as | |
7149 I have indicated) I place in this chapter because it belongs | |
7150 to elementary ‘plane’ geometry. Simplicius says he will | |
7151 quote Eudemus ‘word for word’ (<G>kata\ le/xin</G>) except for a few | |
7152 additions taken from Euclid's <I>Elements,</I> which he will insert | |
7153 for clearness' sake, and which are indeed necessitated by the | |
7154 summary (memorandum-like) style of Eudemus, whose form | |
7155 of statement is condensed, ‘in accordance with ancient prac- | |
7156 tice’. We have therefore in the first place to distinguish | |
7157 between what is textually quoted from Eudemus and what | |
7158 Simplicius has added. To Bretschneider<note>Bretschneider, <I>Die Geometrie und die Geometer vor Euklides,</I> 1870, | |
7159 pp. 100-21.</note> belongs the credit of | |
7160 having called attention to the importance of the passage of | |
7161 Simplicius to the historian of mathematics; Allman<note><I>Hermathena,</I> iv, pp. 180-228; <I>Greek Geometry from Thales to Euclid,</I> | |
7162 pp. 64-75.</note> was the | |
7163 first to attempt the task of distinguishing between the actual | |
7164 <pb n=184><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7165 extracts from Eudemus and Simplicius's amplifications; then | |
7166 came the critical text of Simplicius's commentary on the | |
7167 <I>Physics</I> edited by Diels (1882), who, with the help of Usener, | |
7168 separated out, and marked by spacing, the portions which they | |
7169 regarded as Eudemus's own. Tannery,<note>Tannery, <I>Mémoires scientifiques,</I> vol. i, 1912, pp. 339-70, esp. pp. | |
7170 347-66.</note> who had contributed | |
7171 to the preface of Diels some critical observations, edited | |
7172 (in 1883), with a translation and notes, what he judged to be | |
7173 Eudemian (omitting the rest). Heiberg<note><I>Philologus,</I> 43, pp. 336-44.</note> reviewed the whole | |
7174 question in 1884; and finally Rudio,<note>Rudio, <I>Der Bericht des Simplicius über die Quadraturen des Antiphon | |
7175 und Hippokrates</I> (Teubner, 1907).</note> after giving in the | |
7176 <I>Bibliotheca Mathematica</I> of 1902 a translation of the whole | |
7177 passage of Simplicius with elaborate notes, which again he | |
7178 followed up by other articles in the same journal and elsewhere | |
7179 in 1903 and 1905, has edited the Greek text, with a transla- | |
7180 tion, introduction, notes, and appendices, and summed up the | |
7181 whole controversy. | |
7182 <p>The occasion of the whole disquisition in Simplicius's com- | |
7183 mentary is a remark by Aristotle that there is no obligation | |
7184 on the part of the exponent of a particular subject to refute | |
7185 a fallacy connected with it unless the author of the fallacy | |
7186 has based his argument on the admitted principles lying at | |
7187 the root of the subject in question. ‘Thus’, he says, ‘it is for | |
7188 the geometer to refute the (supposed) quadrature of a circle by | |
7189 means of segments (<G>tmhma/twn</G>), but it is not the business of the | |
7190 geometer to refute the argument of Antiphon.’<note>Arist. <I>Phys.</I> i. 2, 185 a 14-17.</note> Alexander | |
7191 took the remark to refer to Hippocrates's attempted quadra- | |
7192 ture by means of <I>lunes</I> (although in that case <G>tmh=ma</G> is used | |
7193 by Aristotle, not in the technical sense of a <I>segment,</I> but with | |
7194 the non-technical meaning of any portion cut out of a figure). | |
7195 This, probable enough in itself (for in another place Aristotle | |
7196 uses the same word <G>tmh=ma</G> to denote a <I>sector</I> of a circle<note>Arist. <I>De cuelo,</I> ii. 8, 290 a 4.</note>), is | |
7197 made practically certain by two other allusions in Aristotle, | |
7198 one to a proof that a circle together with certain lunes is | |
7199 equal to a rectilineal figure,<note><I>Anal. Pr.</I> ii. 25, 69 a 32.</note> and the other to ‘the (fallacy) of | |
7200 Hippocrates or the quadrature by means of the lunes’.<note><I>Soph. El.</I> 11, 171 b 15.</note> The | |
7201 <pb n=185><head>HIPPOCRATES'S QUADRATURE OF LUNES</head> | |
7202 two expressions separated by ‘or’ may no doubt refer not to | |
7203 one but to two different fallacies. But if ‘the quadrature by | |
7204 means of lunes’ is different from Hippocrates's quadratures of | |
7205 lunes, it must apparently be some quadrature like the second | |
7206 quoted by Alexander (not by Eudemus), and the fallacy attri- | |
7207 buted to Hippocrates must be the quadrature of a certain lune | |
7208 <I>plus</I> a circle (which in itself contains no fallacy at all). It seems | |
7209 more likely that the two expressions refer to one thing, and that | |
7210 this is the argument of Hippocrates's tract taken as a whole. | |
7211 <p>The passage of Alexander which Simplicius reproduces | |
7212 before passing to the extract from Eudemus contains two | |
7213 simple cases of quadrature, of a lune, and of lunes <I>plus</I> a semi- | |
7214 circle respectively, with an erroneous inference from these | |
7215 cases that a circle is thereby squared. It is evident that this | |
7216 account does not represent Hippocrates's own argument, for he | |
7217 would not have been capable of committing so obvious an | |
7218 error; Alexander must have drawn his information, not from | |
7219 Eudemus, but from some other source. Simplicius recognizes | |
7220 this, for, after giving the alternative account extracted from | |
7221 Eudemus, he says that we must trust Eudemus's account rather | |
7222 than the other, since Eudemus was ‘nearer the times’ (of | |
7223 Hippocrates). | |
7224 <p>The two quadratures given by Alexander are as follows. | |
7225 <p>1. Suppose that <I>AB</I> is the diameter of a circle, <I>D</I> its centre, | |
7226 and <I>AC, CB</I> sides of a square | |
7227 inscribed in it. | |
7228 <p>On <I>AC</I> as diameter describe | |
7229 the semicircle <I>AEC.</I> Join <I>CD.</I> | |
7230 <FIG> | |
7231 <p>Now, since | |
7232 <MATH><I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>=2<I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
7233 and circles (and therefore semi- | |
7234 circles) are to one another as the squares on their diameters, | |
7235 <MATH>(semicircle <I>ACB</I>)=2(semicircle <I>AEC</I>)</MATH>. | |
7236 <p>But <MATH>(semicircle <I>ACB</I>)=2(quadrant <I>ADC</I>)</MATH>; | |
7237 therefore <MATH>(semicircle <I>AEC</I>)=(quadrant <I>ADC</I>)</MATH>. | |
7238 <p>If now we subtract the common part, the segment <I>AFC,</I> | |
7239 we have <MATH>(lune <I>AECF</I>)=▵<I>ADC</I></MATH>, | |
7240 and the lune is ‘squared’. | |
7241 <pb n=186><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7242 <p>2. Next take three consecutive sides <I>CE, EF, FD</I> of a regular | |
7243 hexagon inscribed in a circle of diameter <I>CD.</I> Also take <I>AB</I> | |
7244 equal to the radius of the circle and therefore equal to each of | |
7245 the sides. | |
7246 <p>On <I>AB, CE, EF, FD</I> as diameters describe semicircles (in | |
7247 the last three cases outwards with reference to the circle). | |
7248 <p>Then, since | |
7249 <MATH><I>CD</I><SUP>2</SUP>=4<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>CE</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>FD</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
7250 and circles are to one another as the squares on their | |
7251 diameters, | |
7252 <MATH>semicircle <I>CEFD</I>)=4 (semicircle <I>ALB</I>) | |
7253 =(sum of semicircles <I>ALB, CGE, EHF, FKD</I>)</MATH>. | |
7254 <FIG> | |
7255 <p>Subtracting from each side the sum of the small segments | |
7256 on <I>CE, EF, FD,</I> we have | |
7257 <MATH>(trapezium <I>CEFD</I>)=(sum of three lunes)+(semicircle <I>ALB</I>)</MATH>. | |
7258 <p>The author goes on to say that, subtracting the rectilineal | |
7259 figure equal to the three lunes (‘for a rectilineal figure was | |
7260 proved equal to a lune’), we get a rectilineal figure equal | |
7261 to the semicircle <I>ALB,</I> ‘and so the circle will have been | |
7262 squared’. | |
7263 <p>This conclusion is obviously false, and, as Alexander says, | |
7264 the fallacy is in taking what was proved only of the lune on | |
7265 the side of the inscribed square, namely that it can be squared, | |
7266 to be true of the lunes on the sides of an inscribed regular | |
7267 hexagon. It is impossible that Hippocrates (one of the ablest | |
7268 of geometers) could have made such a blunder. We turn there- | |
7269 fore to Eudemus's account, which has every appearance of | |
7270 beginning at the beginning of Hippocrates's work and pro- | |
7271 ceeding in his order. | |
7272 <pb n=187><head>HIPPOCRATES'S QUADRATURE OF LUNES</head> | |
7273 <p>It is important from the point of view of this chapter to | |
7274 preserve the phraseology of Eudemus, which throws light | |
7275 on the question how far the technical terms of Euclidean | |
7276 geometry were already used by Eudemus (if not by Hippo- | |
7277 crates) in their technical sense. I shall therefore translate | |
7278 literally so much as can safely be attributed to Eudemus | |
7279 himself, except in purely geometrical work, where I shall use | |
7280 modern symbols. | |
7281 <p>‘The quadratures of lunes, which were considered to belong | |
7282 to an uncommon class of propositions on account of the | |
7283 close relation (of lunes) to the circle, were first investigated | |
7284 by Hippocrates, and his exposition was thought to be in | |
7285 correct form<note><G>kata\ tro/pon</G> (‘werthvolle Abhandlung’, Heib.).</note>; we will therefore deal with them at length | |
7286 and describe them. He started with, and laid down as the | |
7287 first of the theorems useful for his purpose, the proposition | |
7288 that similar segments of circles have the same ratio to one | |
7289 another as the squares on their bases have [lit. as their bases | |
7290 in square, <G>duna/mei</G>]. And this he proved by first showing | |
7291 that the squares on the diameters have the same ratio as the | |
7292 circles. For, as the circles are to one another, so also are | |
7293 similar segments of them. For similar segments are those | |
7294 which are the same part of the circles respectively, as for | |
7295 instance a semicircle is similar to a semicircle, and a third | |
7296 part of a circle to a third part [here, Rudio argues, the word | |
7297 <I>segments</I>, <G>tmh/mata</G>, would seem to be used in the sense of | |
7298 <I>sectors</I>]. It is for this reason also (<G>dio\ kai\</G>) that similar | |
7299 segments contain equal angles [here ‘segments’ are certainly | |
7300 segments in the usual sense]. The angles of all semicircles | |
7301 are right, those of segments greater than a semicircle are less | |
7302 than right angles and are less in proportion as the segments | |
7303 are greater than semicircles, while those of segments less than | |
7304 a semicircle are greater than right angles and are greater in | |
7305 proportion as the segments are less than semicircles.’ | |
7306 <p>I have put the last sentences of this quotation in dotted | |
7307 brackets because it is matter of controversy whether they | |
7308 belong to the original extract from Eudemus or were added by | |
7309 Simplicius. | |
7310 <p>I think I shall bring out the issues arising out of this | |
7311 passage into the clearest relief if I take as my starting-point | |
7312 the interpretation of it by Rudio, the editor of the latest | |
7313 <pb n=188><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7314 edition of the whole extract. Whereas Diels, Usener, Tannery, | |
7315 and Heiberg had all seen in the sentences ‘For, as the circles | |
7316 are to one another . . . less than semicircles’ an addition by | |
7317 Simplicius, like the phrase just preceding (not quoted above), | |
7318 ‘a proposition which Euclid placed second in his twelfth book | |
7319 with the enunciation “Circles are to one another as the squares | |
7320 on their diameters”’, Rudio maintains that the sentences are | |
7321 wholly Eudemian, because ‘For, as the circles are to one | |
7322 another, so are the similar segments’ is obviously connected | |
7323 with the proposition that similar segments are as the squares | |
7324 on their bases a few lines back. Assuming, then, that the | |
7325 sentences are Eudemian, Rudio bases his next argument on | |
7326 the sentence defining similar segments, ‘For similar segments | |
7327 are those which are the same part of the circles: thus a semi- | |
7328 circle is similar to a semicircle, and a third part (of one circle) | |
7329 to a third part (of another circle)’. He argues that a ‘segment’ | |
7330 in the proper sense which is one third, one fourth, &c., of the | |
7331 circle is not a conception likely to have been introduced into | |
7332 Hippocrates's discussion, because it cannot be visualized by | |
7333 actual construction, and so would not have conveyed any clear | |
7334 idea. On the other hand, if we divide the four right angles | |
7335 about the centre of a circle into 3, 4, or <I>n</I> equal parts by | |
7336 means of 3, 4, or <I>n</I> radii, we have an obvious division of the | |
7337 circle into equal parts which would occur to any one; that is, | |
7338 any one would understand the expression one third or one | |
7339 fourth part of a circle if the parts were <I>sectors</I> and not | |
7340 segments. (The use of the word <G>tmh=ma</G> in the sense of sector | |
7341 is not impossible in itself at a date when mathematical | |
7342 terminology was not finally fixed; indeed it means ‘sector’ | |
7343 in one passage of Aristotle.<note>Arist. <I>De caelo</I>, ii. 8, 290 a 4.</note>) Hence Rudio will have it that | |
7344 ‘similar segments’ in the second and third places in our passage | |
7345 are ‘similar <I>sectors</I>’. But the ‘similar segments’ in the funda- | |
7346 mental proposition of Hippocrates enunciated just before are | |
7347 certainly segments in the proper sense; so are those in the | |
7348 next sentence which says that similar segments contain equal | |
7349 angles. There is, therefore, the very great difficulty that, | |
7350 under Rudio's interpretation, the word <G>tmh/mata</G> used in | |
7351 successive sentences means, first segments, then sectors, and | |
7352 then segments again. However, assuming this to be so, Rudio | |
7353 <pb n=189><head>HIPPOCRATES'S QUADRATURE OF LUNES</head> | |
7354 is able to make the argument hang together, in the following | |
7355 way. The next sentence says, ‘For this reason also (<G>dio\ kai\</G>) | |
7356 similar segments contain equal angles’; therefore this must be | |
7357 inferred from the fact that similar sectors are the same part | |
7358 of the respective circles. The intermediate steps are not given | |
7359 in the text; but, since the similar sectors are the same part | |
7360 of the circles, they contain equal angles, and it follows that the | |
7361 angles in the segments which form part of the sectors are | |
7362 equal, since they are the supplements of the halves of the | |
7363 angles of the sectors respectively (this inference presupposes | |
7364 that Hippocrates knew the theorems of Eucl. III. 20-22, which | |
7365 is indeed clear from other passages in the Eudemus extract). | |
7366 Assuming this to be the line of argument, Rudio infers that in | |
7367 Hippocrates's time similar segments were not defined as in | |
7368 Euclid (namely as segments containing equal angles) but were | |
7369 regarded as the segments belonging to ‘similar <I>sectors</I>’, which | |
7370 would thus be the prior conception. Similar sectors would | |
7371 be sectors having their angles equal. The sequence of ideas, | |
7372 then, leading up to Hippocrates's proposition would be this. | |
7373 Circles are to one another as the squares on their diameters or | |
7374 radii. Similar sectors, having their angles equal, are to one | |
7375 another as the whole circles to which they belong. (Euclid has | |
7376 not this proposition, but it is included in Theon's addition to | |
7377 VI. 33, and would be known long before Euclid's time.) | |
7378 Hence similar sectors are as the squares on the radii. But | |
7379 so are the triangles formed by joining the extremities of the | |
7380 bounding radii in each sector. Therefore (cf. Eucl. V. 19) | |
7381 the differences between the sectors and the corresponding | |
7382 triangles respectively, i.e. the corresponding <I>segments</I>, are in | |
7383 the same ratio as (1) the similar sectors, or (2) the similar | |
7384 triangles, and therefore are as the squares on the radii. | |
7385 <p>We could no doubt accept this version subject to three <I>ifs</I>, | |
7386 (1) if the passage is Eudemian, (2) if we could suppose | |
7387 <G>tmh/mata</G> to be used in different senses in consecutive sentences | |
7388 without a word of explanation, (3) if the omission of the step | |
7389 between the definition of similar ‘segments’ and the inference | |
7390 that the angles in similar segments are equal could be put | |
7391 down to Eudemus's ‘summary’ style. The second of these | |
7392 <I>ifs</I> is the crucial one; and, after full reflection, I feel bound | |
7393 to agree with the great scholars who have held that this | |
7394 <pb n=190><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7395 hypothesis is impossible; indeed the canons of literary criti- | |
7396 cism seem to exclude it altogether. If this is so, the whole | |
7397 of Rudio's elaborate structure falls to the ground. | |
7398 <p>We can now consider the whole question <I>ab initio.</I> First, | |
7399 are the sentences in question the words of Eudemus or of | |
7400 Simplicius? On the one hand, I think the-whole paragraph | |
7401 would be much more like the ‘summary’ manner of Eudemus | |
7402 if it stopped at ‘have the same ratio as the circles’, i.e. if the | |
7403 sentences were not there at all. Taken together, they are | |
7404 long and yet obscurely argued, while the last sentence is | |
7405 really otiose, and, I should have said, quite unworthy of | |
7406 Eudemus. On the other hand, I do not see that Simplicius | |
7407 had any sufficient motive for interpolating such an explana- | |
7408 tion: he might have added the words ‘for, as the circles are | |
7409 to one another, so also are similar segments of them’, but | |
7410 there was no need for him to define similar segments; <I>he</I> | |
7411 must have been familiar enough with the term and its | |
7412 meaning to take it for granted that his readers would know | |
7413 them too. I think, therefore, that the sentences, down to ‘the | |
7414 same part of the circles respectively’ at any rate, may be | |
7415 from Eudemus. In these sentences, then, can ‘segments’ mean | |
7416 segments in the proper sense (and not sectors) after all? | |
7417 The argument that it cannot rests on the assumption that the | |
7418 Greeks of Hippocrates's day would not be likely to speak of | |
7419 a segment which was one third of the whole circle if they | |
7420 did not see their way to visualize it by actual construction. | |
7421 But, though the idea would be of no use to <I>us</I>, it does not | |
7422 follow that their point of view would be the same as ours. | |
7423 On the contrary, I agree with Zeuthen that Hippocrates may | |
7424 well have said, of segments of circles which are in the same | |
7425 ratio as the circles, that they are ‘the same part’ of the circles | |
7426 respectively, for this is (in an incomplete form, it is true) the | |
7427 language of the definition of proportion in the only theory of | |
7428 proportion (the numerical) then known (cf. Eucl. VII. Def. 20, | |
7429 ‘Numbers are proportional when the first is the same multiple, | |
7430 or the same part, or the same parts, of the second that the | |
7431 third is of the fourth’, i.e. the two equal ratios are of one | |
7432 of the following forms <I>m</I>, 1/<I>n</I> or <I>m/n</I> where <I>m, n</I> are integers); | |
7433 the illustrations, namely the semicircles and the segments | |
7434 <pb n=191><head>HIPPOCRATES'S QUADRATURE OF LUNES</head> | |
7435 which are one third of the circles respectively, are from this | |
7436 point of view quite harmless. | |
7437 <p>Only the transition to the view of similar segments as | |
7438 segments ‘containing equal angles’ remains to be explained. | |
7439 And here we are in the dark, because we do not know how, for | |
7440 instance, Hippocrates would have <I>drawn</I> a segment in one | |
7441 given circle which should be ‘the same part’ of that circle | |
7442 that a given segment of another given circle is of that circle. | |
7443 (If e.g. he had used the proportionality of the parts into which | |
7444 the bases of the two similar segments divide the diameters | |
7445 of the circles which bisect them perpendicularly, he could, | |
7446 by means of the sectors to which the segments belong, have | |
7447 proved that the segments, like the sectors, are in the ratio | |
7448 of the circles, just as Rudio supposes him to have done; and | |
7449 the equality of the angles in the segments would have followed | |
7450 as in Rudio's proof.) | |
7451 <p>As it is, I cannot feel certain that the sentence <G>dio\ kai\ ktl</G>. | |
7452 ‘this is the reason why similar segments contain equal angles’ | |
7453 is not an addition by Simplicius. Although Hippocrates was | |
7454 fully aware of the fact, he need not have stated it in this | |
7455 place, and Simplicius may have inserted the sentence in order | |
7456 to bring Hippocrates's view of similar segments into relation | |
7457 with Euclid's definition. The sentence which follows about | |
7458 ‘angles of’ semicircles and ‘angles of’ segments, greater or | |
7459 less than semicircles, is out of place, to say the least, and can | |
7460 hardly come from Eudemus. | |
7461 <p>We resume Eudemus's account. | |
7462 <p>‘After proving this, he proceeded to show in what way it | |
7463 was possible to square a lune the outer circumference of which | |
7464 is that of a semicircle. This he effected by circumscribing | |
7465 a semicircle about an isosceles right-angled triangle and | |
7466 (circumscribing) about the base [=describing on the base] | |
7467 a segment of a circle similar to those cut off by the sides.’ | |
7468 [This is the problem of Eucl. III. 33, | |
7469 and involves the knowledge that similar | |
7470 segments contain equal angles.] | |
7471 <FIG> | |
7472 <p>‘Then, since the segment about the | |
7473 base is equal to the sum of those about | |
7474 the sides, it follows that, when the part | |
7475 of the triangle above the segment about the base is added | |
7476 to both alike, the lune will be equal to the triangle. | |
7477 <pb n=192><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7478 <p>‘Therefore the lune, having been proved equal to the triangle, | |
7479 can be squared. | |
7480 <p>‘In this way, assuming that the outer circumference of | |
7481 the lune is that of a semicircle, Hippocrates easily squared | |
7482 the lune. | |
7483 <p>‘Next after this he assumes (an outer circumference) greater | |
7484 than a semicircle (obtained) by constructing a trapezium in | |
7485 which three sides are equal to one another, while one, the | |
7486 greater of the parallel sides, is such that the square on it is | |
7487 triple of the square on each one of the other sides, and then | |
7488 comprehending the trapezium in a circle and circumscribing | |
7489 about (=describing on) its greatest side a segment similar | |
7490 to those cut off from the circle by | |
7491 the three equal sides.’ | |
7492 <FIG> | |
7493 <p>[Simplicius here inserts an easy | |
7494 proof that a circle <I>can</I> be circum- | |
7495 scribed about the trapezium.<note>Heiberg (<I>Philologus</I>, 43, p. 340) thinks that the words <G>kai\ o(/ti me\n | |
7496 perilhfqh/setai ku/klw| to\ trape/zion dei/xeis</G> [<G>ou(/tws</G>] <G>dixotomh/sas ta\s tou= trapezi/ou | |
7497 gwni/as</G> (‘Now, that the trapezium can be comprehended in a circle you | |
7498 can prove by bisecting the angles of the trapezium’) <I>may</I> (without <G>ou(/tws</G>— | |
7499 F omits it) be Eudemus's own. For <G>o(/ti me\n</G> ... forms a natural contrast | |
7500 to <G>o(/ti de\ mei=zon</G> . . . in the next paragraph. Also cf. p. 65. 9 Diels, <G>tou/twn | |
7501 ou=)n ou(/tws e)xo/ntwn to\ trape/zio/n fhmi e)f) ou(=</G> <I>EKBH</I> <G>perilh/yetai ku/klos</G>.</note>] | |
7502 <p>‘That the said segment [bounded | |
7503 by the outer circumference <I>BACD</I> | |
7504 in the figure] is greater than a | |
7505 semicircle is clear, if a diagonal | |
7506 be drawn in the trapezium. | |
7507 <p>‘For this diagonal [say <I>BC</I>], | |
7508 subtending two sides [<I>BA, AC</I>] of | |
7509 the trapezium, is such that the | |
7510 square on it is greater than double | |
7511 the square on one of the remain- | |
7512 ing sides.’ | |
7513 <p>[This follows from the fact that, <I>AC</I> being parallel to | |
7514 <I>BD</I> but less than it, <I>BA</I> and <I>DC</I> will meet, if produced, in | |
7515 a point <I>F.</I> Then, in the isosceles triangle <I>FAC</I>, the angle | |
7516 <I>FAC</I> is less than a right angle, so that the angle <I>BAC</I> is | |
7517 obtuse.] | |
7518 <p>‘Therefore the square on [<I>BD</I>] the greatest side of the trape- | |
7519 zium [=3 <I>CD</I><SUP>2</SUP> by hypothesis] is less than the sum of the | |
7520 squares on the diagonal [<I>BC</I>] and that one of the other sides | |
7521 <pb n=193><head>HIPPOCRATES'S QUADRATURE OF LUNES</head> | |
7522 [<I>CD</I>] which is subtended<note>Observe the curious use of <G>u(potei/nein</G>, stretch under, subtend. The | |
7523 third side of a triangle is said to be ‘subtended’ by the other two | |
7524 together.</note> by the said (greatest) side [<I>BD</I>] | |
7525 together with the diagonal [<I>BC</I>]’ [i.e. <MATH><I>BD</I><SUP>2</SUP><<I>BC</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>CD</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>]. | |
7526 <p>‘Therefore the angle standing on the greater side of the | |
7527 trapezium [∠<I>BCD</I>] is acute. | |
7528 <p>‘Therefore the segment in which the said angle is is greater | |
7529 than a semicircle. And this (segment) is the outer circum- | |
7530 ference of the lune.’ | |
7531 <p>[Simplicius observes that Eudemus has omitted the actual | |
7532 squaring of the lune, presumably as being obvious. We have | |
7533 only to supply the following. | |
7534 <p>Since <MATH><I>BD</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3<I>BA</I><SUP>2</SUP>, | |
7535 (segment on <I>BD</I>)=3 (segment on <I>BA</I>) | |
7536 =(sum of segments on <I>BA, AC, CD</I>)</MATH>. | |
7537 <p>Add to each side the area between <I>BA, AC, CD</I>, and the | |
7538 circumference of the segment on <I>BD</I>, and we have | |
7539 (trapezium <I>ABDC</I>)=(lune bounded by the two circumferences).] | |
7540 <FIG> | |
7541 <p>‘A case too where the outer circumference is less than | |
7542 a semicircle was solved by Hippocrates,<note>Literally ‘If (the outer circumference) were less than a semicircle, | |
7543 Hippocrates solved (<G>kateskeu/asen</G>, constructed) this (case).’</note> who gave the follow- | |
7544 ing preliminary construction. | |
7545 <p>‘<I>Let there be a circle with diameter AB, and let its centre | |
7546 be K.</I> | |
7547 <p>‘<I>Let CD bisect BK at right angles; and let the straight | |
7548 line EF be so placed between CD and the circumference that it | |
7549 verges towards B</I> [i.e. will, if produced, pass through <I>B</I>], <I>while | |
7550 its length is also such that the square on it is</I> 1 1/2 <I>times the square | |
7551 on</I> (<I>one of</I>) <I>the radii.</I> | |
7552 <pb n=194><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7553 <p>‘<I>Let EG be drawn parallel to AB, and let</I> (<I>straight lines</I>) | |
7554 <I>be drawn joining K to E and F.</I> | |
7555 <p>‘<I>Let the straight line [KF] joined to F and produced meet | |
7556 EG in G, and again let</I> (<I>straight lines</I>) <I>be drawn joining | |
7557 B to F, G.</I> | |
7558 <p>‘<I>It is then manifest that BF produced will pass through</I> | |
7559 [“fall on”] <I>E</I> [for by hypothesis <I>EF</I> verges towards <I>B</I>], <I>and | |
7560 BG will be equal to EK.</I>’ | |
7561 <p>[Simplicius proves this at length. The proof is easy. The | |
7562 triangles <I>FKC, FBC</I> are equal in all respects [Eucl. I. 4]. | |
7563 Therefore, <I>EG</I> being parallel to <I>KB</I>, the triangles <I>EDF, GDF</I> | |
7564 are equal in all respects [Eucl. I. 15, 29, 26]. Hence the | |
7565 trapezium is isosceles, and <MATH><I>BG</I>=<I>EK</I></MATH>. | |
7566 <p>‘<I>This being so, I say that the trapezium EKBG can be | |
7567 comprehended in a circle.</I>’ | |
7568 <p>[Let the segment <I>EKBG</I> circumscribe it.] | |
7569 <p>‘Next let a segment of a circle be circumscribed about the | |
7570 triangle <I>EFG</I> also; | |
7571 then manifestly each of the segments [on] <I>EF, FG</I> will be | |
7572 similar to each of the segments [on] <I>EK, KB, BG.</I>’ | |
7573 <p>[This is because all the segments contain equal angles, | |
7574 namely an angle equal to the supplement of <I>EGK.</I>] | |
7575 <p>‘This being so, the lune so formed, of which <I>EKBG</I> is the | |
7576 outer circumference, will be equal to the rectilineal figure made | |
7577 up of the three triangles <I>BFG, BFK, EKF.</I> | |
7578 <p>‘For the segments cut off from the rectilineal figure, on the | |
7579 inner side of the lune, by the straight lines <I>EF, FG</I>, are | |
7580 (together) equal to the segments outside the rectilineal figure | |
7581 cut off by the straight lines <I>EK, KB, BG</I>, since each of the | |
7582 inner segments is 1 1/2 times each of the outer, because, by | |
7583 hypothesis, <MATH><I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP>(=<I>FG</I><SUP>2</SUP>)=3/2<I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> | |
7584 [i.e. <MATH>2<I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3<I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP>, | |
7585 =<I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>KB</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>BG</I><SUP>2</SUP>]</MATH>. | |
7586 <p>‘If then | |
7587 <MATH>(lune)=(the three segmts.)+{(rect. fig.)-(the two segmts.)}</MATH>, | |
7588 the trapezium including the two segments but not the three, | |
7589 while the (sum of the) two segments is equal to the (sum | |
7590 of the) three, it follows that | |
7591 <MATH>(lune)=(rectilineal figure)</MATH>. | |
7592 <pb n=195><head>HIPPOCRATES'S QUADRATURE OF LUNES</head> | |
7593 <p>‘The fact that this lune (is one which) has its outer circum- | |
7594 ference less than a semicircle he proves by means of the fact | |
7595 that the angle [<I>EKG</I>] in the outer segment is obtuse. | |
7596 <p>‘And the fact that the angle <I>EKG</I> is obtuse he proves as | |
7597 follows.’ | |
7598 <p>[This proof is supposed to have been given by Eudemus in | |
7599 Hippocrates's own words, but unfortunately the text is con- | |
7600 fused. The argument seems to have been substantially as | |
7601 follows. | |
7602 <p><I>By hypothesis</I>, <MATH><I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3/2<I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
7603 <p><I>Also</I> <MATH><I>BK</I><SUP>2</SUP>>2<I>BF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> (this is assumed: we shall | |
7604 consider the ground later); | |
7605 <I>or</I> <MATH><I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP>>2<I>KF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
7606 <p><I>Therefore</I> <MATH><I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP>+1/2<I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP> | |
7607 ><I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>KF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
7608 <I>so that the angle EKF is obtuse, and the segment is less than | |
7609 a semicircle.</I> | |
7610 <p>How did Hippocrates prove that <MATH><I>BK</I><SUP>2</SUP>>2<I>BF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>? The manu- | |
7611 scripts have the phrase ‘because the angle at <I>F</I> is greater’ (where | |
7612 presumably we should supply <G>o)rqh=s</G>, ‘than a right angle’). | |
7613 But, if Hippocrates proved this, he must evidently have proved | |
7614 it by means of his hypothesis <MATH><I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3/2<I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, and this hypo- | |
7615 thesis leads more directly to the consequence that <MATH><I>BK</I><SUP>2</SUP>>2<I>KF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> | |
7616 than to the fact that the angle at <I>F</I> is greater than a right | |
7617 angle. | |
7618 <p>We may supply the proof thus. | |
7619 <p>By hypothesis, <MATH><I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3/2<I>KB</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
7620 <p>Also, since <I>A, E, F, C</I> are concyclic, | |
7621 <MATH><I>EB.BF</I>=<I>AB.BC</I> | |
7622 =<I>KB</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
7623 or <MATH><I>EF.FB</I>+<I>BF</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>KB</I><SUP>2</SUP> | |
7624 =2/3<I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
7625 <p>It follows from the last relations that <I>EF</I>><I>FB</I>, and that | |
7626 <MATH><I>KB</I><SUP>2</SUP>>2<I>BF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
7627 <p>The most remarkable feature in the above proof is the | |
7628 assumption of the solution of the problem ‘<I>to place a straight</I> | |
7629 <pb n=196><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7630 <I>line [EF] of length such that the square on it is</I> 1 1/2 <I>times the | |
7631 square on AK between the circumference of the semicircle and | |
7632 CD in such a way that it will verge</I> (<G>neu/ein</G>) <I>towards B</I>’ [i.e. if | |
7633 produced, will pass through <I>B</I>]. This is a problem of a type | |
7634 which the Greeks called <G>neu/seis</G>, <I>inclinationes</I> or <I>vergings.</I> | |
7635 Theoretically it may be regarded as the problem of finding | |
7636 a length (<I>x</I>) such that, if <I>F</I> be so taken on <I>CD</I> that <I>BF</I>=<I>x</I>, | |
7637 <I>BF</I> produced will intercept between <I>CD</I> and the circumference | |
7638 of the semicircle a length <I>EF</I> equal to √3/2.<I>AK.</I> | |
7639 <p>If we suppose it done, we have | |
7640 <MATH><I>EB.BF</I>=<I>AB.BC</I>=<I>AK</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>; | |
7641 or <MATH><I>x</I>(<I>x</I>+√(3/2).<I>a</I>)=<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP> (where <I>AK</I>=<I>a</I>)</MATH>. | |
7642 <p>That is, the problem is equivalent to the solution of the | |
7643 quadratic equation | |
7644 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+√3/2.<I>ax</I>=<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
7645 <p>This again is the problem of ‘applying to a straight line | |
7646 of length √3/2.<I>a</I> a rectangle exceeding by a square figure and | |
7647 equal in area to <I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>’, and would theoretically be solved by the | |
7648 Pythagorean method based on the theorem of Eucl. II. 6. | |
7649 Undoubtedly Hippocrates could have solved the problem by | |
7650 this theoretical method; but he may, on this occasion, have | |
7651 used the purely mechanical method of marking on a ruler | |
7652 or straight edge a length equal to √3/2.<I>AK</I>, and then moving | |
7653 it till the points marked lay on the circumference and on <I>CD</I> | |
7654 respectively, while the straight edge also passed through <I>B.</I> | |
7655 This method is perhaps indicated by the fact that he first | |
7656 <I>places EF</I> (without producing it to <I>B</I>) and afterwards | |
7657 <I>joins BF.</I> | |
7658 <p>We come now to the last of Hippocrates's quadratures. | |
7659 Eudemus proceeds:] | |
7660 <p>‘Thus Hippocrates squared every<note>Tannery brackets <G>pa/nta</G> and <G>ei)/per kai/</G>. Heiberg thinks (<I>l.c</I>, p. 343) | |
7661 the <I>wording</I> is that of Simplicius reproducing the <I>content</I> of Eudemus. | |
7662 The wording of the sentence is important with reference to the questions | |
7663 (1) What was the paralogism with which Aristotle actually charged | |
7664 Hippocrates? and (2) What, if any, was the justification for the charge? | |
7665 Now the four quadratures as given by Eudemus are clever, and contain in | |
7666 themselves no fallacy at all. The supposed fallacy, then, can only have | |
7667 consisted in an assumption on the part of Hippocrates that, because he | |
7668 had squared one particular lune of each of three types, namely those | |
7669 which have for their outer circumferences respectively (1) a semicircle, | |
7670 (2) an are greater than a semicircle, (3) an are less than a semicircle, he | |
7671 had squared all possible lunes, and therefore also the lune included in his | |
7672 last quadrature, the squaring of which (had it been possible) would | |
7673 actually have enabled him to square the circle. The question is, did | |
7674 <05>ippocrates so delude himself? Heiberg thinks that, in the then | |
7675 state of logic, he may have done so. But it seems impossible to believe | |
7676 this of so good a mathematician; moreover, if Hippocrates had really | |
7677 thought that he had squared the circle, it is inconceivable that he | |
7678 would not have said so in express terms at the end of his fourth | |
7679 quadrature. | |
7680 <p>Another recent view is that of Björnbo (in Pauly-Wissowa, <I>Real-Ency- | |
7681 clopädie</I>, xvi, pp. 1787-99), who holds that Hippocrates realized | |
7682 perfectly the limits of what he had been able to do and knew that he had not | |
7683 squared the circle, but that he deliberately used language which, without | |
7684 being actually untrue, was calculated to mislead any one who read him | |
7685 into the belief that he had really solved the problem. This, too, seems | |
7686 incredible; for surely Hippocrates must have known that the first expert | |
7687 who read his tract would detect the fallacy at once, and that he was | |
7688 risking his reputation as a mathematician for no purpose. I prefer to | |
7689 think that he was merely trying to put what he had discovered in the | |
7690 most favourable light; but it must be admitted that the effect of his | |
7691 language was only to bring upon himself a charge which he might easily | |
7692 have avoided.</note> (sort of) lune, seeing | |
7693 that<note>Tannery brackets <G>pa/nta</G> and <G>ei)/per kai/</G>. Heiberg thinks (<I>l.c</I>, p. 343) | |
7694 the <I>wording</I> is that of Simplicius reproducing the <I>content</I> of Eudemus. | |
7695 The wording of the sentence is important with reference to the questions | |
7696 (1) What was the paralogism with which Aristotle actually charged | |
7697 Hippocrates? and (2) What, if any, was the justification for the charge? | |
7698 Now the four quadratures as given by Eudemus are clever, and contain in | |
7699 themselves no fallacy at all. The supposed fallacy, then, can only have | |
7700 consisted in an assumption on the part of Hippocrates that, because he | |
7701 had squared one particular lune of each of three types, namely those | |
7702 which have for their outer circumferences respectively (1) a semicircle, | |
7703 (2) an are greater than a semicircle, (3) an are less than a semicircle, he | |
7704 had squared all possible lunes, and therefore also the lune included in his | |
7705 last quadrature, the squaring of which (had it been possible) would | |
7706 actually have enabled him to square the circle. The question is, did | |
7707 <05>ippocrates so delude himself? Heiberg thinks that, in the then | |
7708 state of logic, he may have done so. But it seems impossible to believe | |
7709 this of so good a mathematician; moreover, if Hippocrates had really | |
7710 thought that he had squared the circle, it is inconceivable that he | |
7711 would not have said so in express terms at the end of his fourth | |
7712 quadrature. | |
7713 <p>Another recent view is that of Björnbo (in Pauly-Wissowa, <I>Real-Ency- | |
7714 clopädie</I>, xvi, pp. 1787-99), who holds that Hippocrates realized | |
7715 perfectly the limits of what he had been able to do and knew that he had not | |
7716 squared the circle, but that he deliberately used language which, without | |
7717 being actually untrue, was calculated to mislead any one who read him | |
7718 into the belief that he had really solved the problem. This, too, seems | |
7719 incredible; for surely Hippocrates must have known that the first expert | |
7720 who read his tract would detect the fallacy at once, and that he was | |
7721 risking his reputation as a mathematician for no purpose. I prefer to | |
7722 think that he was merely trying to put what he had discovered in the | |
7723 most favourable light; but it must be admitted that the effect of his | |
7724 language was only to bring upon himself a charge which he might easily | |
7725 have avoided.</note> (he squared) not only (1) the lune which has for its outer | |
7726 <pb n=197><head>HIPPOCRATES'S QUADRATURE OF LUNES</head> | |
7727 circumference the arc of a semicircle, but also (2) the lune | |
7728 in which the outer circumference is greater, and (3) the lune in | |
7729 which it is less, than a semicircle. | |
7730 <p>‘But he also squared the sum of a lune and a circle in the | |
7731 following manner. | |
7732 <p>‘<I>Let there be two circles about K as centre, such that the | |
7733 square on the diameter of the outer is</I> 6 <I>times the square on | |
7734 that of the inner.</I> | |
7735 <p>‘<I>Let a</I> (<I>regular</I>) <I>hexagon ABCDEF be inscribed in the | |
7736 inner circle, and let KA, KB, KC be joined from the centre | |
7737 and produced as far as the circumference of the outer circle. | |
7738 Let GH, HI, GI be joined.</I>’ | |
7739 <p>[Then clearly <I>GH, HI</I> are sides of a hexagon inscribed in | |
7740 the outer circle.] | |
7741 <p>‘<I>About GI</I> [i.e. on <I>GI</I>] <I>let a segment be circumscribed | |
7742 similar to the segment cut off by GH.</I> | |
7743 <p>‘<I>Then</I> <MATH><I>GI</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3<I>GH</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
7744 for <MATH><I>GI</I><SUP>2</SUP>+(side of outer hexagon)<SUP>2</SUP>=(diam. of outer circle)<SUP>2</SUP> | |
7745 =4<I>GH</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
7746 [The original states this in words without the help of the | |
7747 letters of the figure.] | |
7748 <p>‘<I>Also</I> <MATH><I>GH</I><SUP>2</SUP>=6<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
7749 <pb n=198><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7750 <p>‘<I>Therefore | |
7751 segment on GI</I> [<MATH>=2(segmt. on <I>GH</I>)+6(segmt. on <I>AB</I>)</MATH>] | |
7752 <MATH>=(<I>segmts. on GH, HI</I>)+(<I>all segmts. in | |
7753 inner circle</I>)</MATH>. | |
7754 <FIG> | |
7755 [‘Add to each side the area bounded by <I>GH, HI</I> and the | |
7756 arc <I>GI</I>;] | |
7757 <I>therefore</I> <MATH>(▵<I>GHI</I>)=(<I>lune GHI</I>)+(<I>all segmts. in inner circle</I>)</MATH>. | |
7758 <p>Adding to both sides the hexagon in the inner circle, we have | |
7759 <MATH>(▵ <I>GHI</I>)+(inner hexagon)=(lune <I>GHI</I>)+(inner circle)</MATH>. | |
7760 ‘Since, then, the sum of the two rectilineal figures can be | |
7761 squared, so can the sum of the circle and the lune in question.’ | |
7762 <p>Simplicius adds the following observations: | |
7763 <p>‘Now, so far as Hippocrates is concerned, we must allow | |
7764 that Eudemus was in a better position to know the facts, since | |
7765 he was nearer the times, being a pupil of Aristotle. But, as | |
7766 regards the “squaring of the circle by means of segments” | |
7767 which Aristotle reflected on as containing a fallacy, there are | |
7768 three possibilities, (1) that it indicates the squaring by means | |
7769 of lunes (Alexander was quite right in expressing the doubt | |
7770 implied by his words, “if it is the same as the squaring by | |
7771 means of lunes”), (2) that it refers, not to the proofs of | |
7772 Hippocrates, but some others, one of which Alexander actually | |
7773 reproduced, or (3) that it is intended to reflect on the squaring | |
7774 by Hippocrates of the circle <I>plus</I> the lune, which Hippocrates | |
7775 did in fact prove “by means of segments”, namely the three | |
7776 (in the greater circle) and those in the lesser circle. . . . On | |
7777 <pb n=199><head>HIPPOCRATES'S QUADRATURE OF LUNES</head> | |
7778 this third hypothesis the fallacy would lie in the fact that | |
7779 the sum of the circle and the lune is squared, and not the | |
7780 circle alone.’ | |
7781 <p>If, however, the reference of Aristotle was really to Hip- | |
7782 pocrates's last quadrature alone, Hippocrates was obviously | |
7783 misjudged; there is no fallacy in it, nor is Hippocrates likely | |
7784 to have deceived himself as to what his proof actually | |
7785 amounted to. | |
7786 <p>In the above reproduction of the extract from Eudemus | |
7787 I have marked by italics the passages where the writer follows | |
7788 the ancient fashion of describing points, lines, angles, &c., with | |
7789 reference to the letters in the figure: the ancient practice was | |
7790 to write <G>to\ shmei=on e)f) w=(=|</G> (or <G>e)f) ou=(</G>) <I>K</I>, the (point) <I>on which</I> (is) | |
7791 the letter <I>K</I>, instead of the shorter form <G>to\</G> <I>K</I> <G>shmei=on</G>, the | |
7792 point <I>K</I>, used by Euclid and later geometers; <G>h( e)f) h=(</G> <I>AB</I> | |
7793 (<G>eu)qei=a</G>), the straight line <I>on which</I> (are the letters <I>AB</I>, for | |
7794 <G>h(</G> <I>AB</I> (<G>eu)qei=a</G>), the straight line <I>AB</I>; <G>to\ tri/gwnon to\ e)f) ou=(</G> | |
7795 <I>EZH</I>, the triangle <I>on which</I> (are the letters) <I>EFG</I>, instead of | |
7796 <G>to\</G> <I>EZH</I> <G>tri/gwnon</G>, the triangle <I>EFG</I>; and so on. Some have | |
7797 assumed that, where the longer archaic form, instead of the | |
7798 shorter Euclidean, is used, Eudemus must be quoting Hippocrates | |
7799 <I>verbatim</I>; but this is not a safe criterion, because, e.g., Aristotle | |
7800 himself uses both forms of expression, and there are, on the | |
7801 other hand, some relics of the archaic form even in Archimedes. | |
7802 <p>Trigonometry enables us readily to find all the types of | |
7803 Hippocratean lunes that can | |
7804 be squared by means of the | |
7805 straight line and circle. Let | |
7806 <I>ACB</I> be the external circum- | |
7807 ference, <I>ADB</I> the internal cir- | |
7808 cumference of such a lune, | |
7809 <I>r, r</I>′ the radii, and <I>O, O</I>′ the | |
7810 centres of the two arcs, <G>q</G>, <G>q</G>′ | |
7811 the halves of the angles sub- | |
7812 tended by the arcs at the centres | |
7813 respectively. | |
7814 <FIG> | |
7815 <p>Now (area of lune) | |
7816 <MATH>=(difference of segments <I>ACB, ADB</I>) | |
7817 =(sector <I>OACB-▵AOB</I>)′-(sector <I>O′ADB-▵AO′B</I>) | |
7818 =<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP><G>q</G>-<I>r</I>′<SUP>2</SUP><G>q</G>′+1/2 (<I>r</I>′<SUP>2</SUP> sin2<G>q</G>′ - <I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP> sin2<G>q</G>)</MATH>. | |
7819 <pb n=200><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7820 <p>We also have | |
7821 <MATH><I>r</I> sin<G>q</G>=1/2<I>AB</I>=<I>r</I>′ sin<G>q</G>′ . . . . . . (1)</MATH> | |
7822 <p>In order that the lune may be squareable, we must have, in | |
7823 the first place, <MATH><I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP><G>q</G>=<I>r</I>′<SUP>2</SUP><G>q</G>′</MATH>. | |
7824 <p>Suppose that <MATH><G>q</G>=<I>m</I><G>q</G>′</MATH>, and it follows that | |
7825 <MATH><I>r</I>′=√<I>m.r.</I></MATH> | |
7826 <p>Accordingly the area becomes | |
7827 <MATH>1/2<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>(<I>m</I> sin2<G>q</G>′-sin2<I>m</I><G>q</G>′)</MATH>; | |
7828 and it remains only to solve the equation (1) above, which | |
7829 becomes <MATH>sin<I>m</I><G>q</G>′=√<I>m</I>.sin<G>q</G>′</MATH>. | |
7830 <p>This reduces to a quadratic equation only when <I>m</I> has one | |
7831 of the values 2, 3, 3/2, 5, 5/3. | |
7832 <p>The solutions of Hippocrates correspond to the first three | |
7833 values of <I>m.</I> But the lune is squareable by ‘plane’ methods | |
7834 in the other two cases also. Clausen (1840) gave the last four | |
7835 cases of the problem as new<note>Crelle, xxi, 1840, pp. 375-6.</note> (it was not then known that | |
7836 Hippocrates had solved more than the first); but, according | |
7837 to M. Simon<note><I>Geschichte der Math. im Altertum</I>, p. 174.</note>, all five cases were given much earlier in | |
7838 a dissertation by Martin Johan Wallenius of Åbo (Abveae, | |
7839 1766). As early as 1687 Tschirnhausen noted the existence | |
7840 of an infinite number of squareable portions of the first of | |
7841 Hippocrates's lunes. Vieta<note>Vieta, <I>Variorum de rebus mathematicis responsorum</I> lib. viii, 1593.</note> discussed the case in which <I>m</I>=4, | |
7842 which of course leads to a cubic equation. | |
7843 <p>(<G>b</G>) <I>Reduction of the problem of doubling the cube to | |
7844 the finding of two mean proportionals.</I> | |
7845 <p>We have already alluded to Hippocrates's discovery of the | |
7846 reduction of the problem of duplicating the cube to that of | |
7847 finding two mean proportionals in continued proportion. That | |
7848 is, he discovered that, if | |
7849 <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>x</I>=<I>x</I>:<I>y</I>=<I>y</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>, | |
7850 then <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>:<I>x</I><SUP>3</SUP>=<I>a</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>. This shows that he could work with | |
7851 compound ratios, although for him the theory of proportion | |
7852 must still have been the incomplete, <I>numerical</I>, theory | |
7853 developed by the Pythagoreans. It has been suggested that | |
7854 <pb n=201><head>ELEMENTS AS KNOWN TO HIPPOCRATES</head> | |
7855 the idea of the reduction of the problem of duplication may | |
7856 have occurred to him through analogy. The problem of | |
7857 doubling a square is included in that of finding <I>one</I> mean | |
7858 proportional between two lines; he might therefore have | |
7859 thought of what would be the effect of finding two mean | |
7860 proportionals. Alternatively he may have got the idea from | |
7861 the theory of numbers. Plato in the <I>Timaeus</I> has the pro- | |
7862 positions that between two square numbers there is one mean | |
7863 proportional number, but that two cube numbers are connected, | |
7864 not by one, but by two mean numbers in continued proportion.<note>Plato, <I>Timaeus</I>, 32 A, B.</note> | |
7865 These are the theorems of Eucl. VIII. 11, 12, the latter of | |
7866 which is thus enunciated: ‘Between two cube numbers there | |
7867 are two mean proportional numbers, and the cube has to the | |
7868 cube the ratio triplicate of that which the side has to the side.’ | |
7869 If this proposition was really Pythagorean, as seems prob- | |
7870 able enough, Hippocrates had only to give the geometrical | |
7871 adaptation of it. | |
7872 <p>(<G>g</G>) <I>The Elements as known to Hippocrates.</I> | |
7873 <p>We can now take stock of the advances made in the | |
7874 Elements up to the time when Hippocrates compiled a work | |
7875 under that title. We have seen that the Pythagorean geometry | |
7876 already contained the substance of Euclid's Books I and II, | |
7877 part of Book IV, and theorems corresponding to a great part | |
7878 of Book VI; but there is no evidence that the Pythagoreans | |
7879 paid much attention to the geometry of the circle as we find | |
7880 it, e.g., in Eucl., Book III. But, by the time of Hippocrates, | |
7881 the main propositions of Book III were also known and used, | |
7882 as we see from Eudemus's account of the quadratures of | |
7883 lunes. Thus it is assumed that ‘similar’ segments contain | |
7884 equal angles, and, as Hippocrates assumes that two segments | |
7885 of circles are similar when the obvious thing about the figure | |
7886 is that the angles at the circumferences which are the supple- | |
7887 ments of the angles in the segments are one and the same, | |
7888 we may clearly infer, as above stated, that Hippocrates knew | |
7889 the theorems of Eucl. III. 20-2. Further, he assumes the | |
7890 construction on a given straight line of a segment similar to | |
7891 another given segment (cf. Eucl. III. 33). The theorems of | |
7892 Eucl. III. 26-9 would obviously be known to Hippocrates, | |
7893 <pb n=202><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7894 as was that of III. 31 (that the angle in a semicircle is | |
7895 a right angle, and that, according as a segment is less or | |
7896 greater than a semicircle, the angle in it is obtuse or acute). | |
7897 He assumes the solution of the problem of circumscribing | |
7898 a circle about a triangle (Eucl. IV. 5), and the theorem that | |
7899 the side of a regular hexagon inscribed in a circle is equal | |
7900 to the radius (Eucl. IV. 15). | |
7901 <p>But the most remarkable fact of all is that, according to | |
7902 Eudemus, Hippocrates actually proved the theorem of Eucl. | |
7903 XII. 2, that <I>circles are to one another as the squares on their | |
7904 diameters</I>, afterwards using this proposition to prove that | |
7905 <I>similar segments are to one another as the squares on their | |
7906 bases.</I> Euclid of course proves XII. 2 by the <I>method of | |
7907 exhaustion</I>, the invention of which is attributed to Eudoxus | |
7908 on the ground of notices in Archimedes.<note>Prefaces to <I>On the Sphere and Cylinder</I>, i, and <I>Quadrature of the | |
7909 Parabola.</I></note> This method | |
7910 depends on the use of a certain lemma known as the Axiom | |
7911 of Archimedes, or, alternatively, a lemma similar to it. The | |
7912 lemma used by Euclid is his proposition X. 1, which is closely | |
7913 related to Archimedes's lemma in that the latter is practically | |
7914 used in the proof of it. Unfortunately we have no infor- | |
7915 mation as to the nature of Hippocrates's proof; if, however, | |
7916 it amounted to a genuine proof, as Eudemus seems to imply, | |
7917 it is difficult to see how it could have been effected other- | |
7918 wise than by some anticipation in essence of the method of | |
7919 exhaustion. | |
7920 <p>THEODORUS OF CYRENE, who is mentioned by Proclus along | |
7921 with Hippocrates as a celebrated geometer and is claimed by | |
7922 Iamblichus as a Pythagorean,<note>Iambl. <I>Vit. Pyth.</I> c. 36.</note> is only known to us from | |
7923 Plato's <I>Theaetetus.</I> He is said to have been Plato's teacher | |
7924 in mathematics,<note>Diog. L. ii. 103.</note> and it is likely enough that Plato, while on | |
7925 his way to or from Egypt, spent some time with Theodorus at | |
7926 Cyrene,<note>Cf. Diog. L. iii. 6.</note> though, as we gather from the <I>Theaetetus</I>, Theodorus | |
7927 had also been in Athens in the time of Socrates. We learn | |
7928 from the same dialogue that he was a pupil of Protagoras, and | |
7929 was distinguished not only in geometry but in astronomy, | |
7930 arithmetic, music, and all educational subjects.<note>Plato, <I>Theaetetus</I>, 161 B, 162 A; <I>ib.</I> 145 A, C, D.</note> The one notice | |
7931 <pb n=203><head>THEODORUS OF CYRENE</head> | |
7932 which we have of a particular achievement of his suggests that | |
7933 it was he who first carried the theory of irrationals beyond | |
7934 the first step, namely the discovery by the Pythagoreans | |
7935 of the irrationality of √2. According to the <I>Theaetetus</I>,<note><I>Theaetetus</I>, 147 D sq.</note> | |
7936 Theodorus | |
7937 <p>‘was proving<note><G>*peri\ duna/mew/n ti h(mi=n qeo/dwros o(/de e)/grafe, th=s te tri/podos pe/ri kai\ | |
7938 pente/podos [a)pofai/nwn] o(/ti mh/kei ou) su/mmetroi th= podiai/a|</G>. Certain writers | |
7939 (H. Vogt in particular) persist in taking <G>e)/grafe</G> in this sentence to mean | |
7940 <I>drew</I> or <I>constructed.</I> The idea is that Theodorus's exposition must have | |
7941 included two things, first the <I>construction</I> of straight lines representing | |
7942 √3, √5 ... (of course by means of the Pythagorean theorem, Eucl. I. 47), | |
7943 in order to show that these straight lines exist, and secondly the <I>proof</I> | |
7944 that each of them is incommensurable with 1; therefore, it is argued, | |
7945 <G>e)/grafe</G> must indicate the construction and <G>a)pofai/nwn</G> the proof. But in | |
7946 the first place it is impossible that <G>e)/grafe/ ti peri/</G>, ‘he wrote <I>something | |
7947 about</I>’ (roots), should mean ‘<I>constructed</I> each of the roots’. Moreover, if | |
7948 <G>a)pofai/nwn</G> is bracketed (as it is by Burnet), the supposed contrast between | |
7949 <G>e)/grafe</G> and <G>a)pofai/nwn</G> disappears, and <G>e)/grafe</G> <I>must</I> mean ‘proved’, in | |
7950 accordance with the natural meaning of <G>e)grafe/ ti</G>, because there is | |
7951 nothing else to govern <G>o(/ti mh/kei, ktl</G>. (‘that they are not commensurable | |
7952 in length ...’), which phrase is of course a closer description of <G>ti</G>. There | |
7953 are plenty of instances of <G>gra/fein</G> in the sense of ‘prove’. Aristotle says | |
7954 (<I>Topics</I>, <G>*q</G>. 3, 158 b 29) ‘It would appear that in mathematics too some | |
7955 things are difficult to prove (<G>ou) r(a|di/ws gra/fesqai</G>) owing to the want of | |
7956 a definition, e.g. that a straight line parallel to the side and cutting a plane | |
7957 figure (parallelogram) divides the straight line (side) and the area simi- | |
7958 larly’. Cf. Archimedes, <I>On the Sphere and Cylinder</I>, ii, Pref., ‘It happens | |
7959 that most of them are proved (<G>gra/fesqai</G>) by means of the theorems ...’; | |
7960 ‘Such of the theorems and problems as are proved (<G>gra/fetai</G>) by means of | |
7961 these theorems I have proved (or written out, <G>gra/yas</G>) and send you | |
7962 in this book’; <I>Quadrature of a Parabola</I>, Pref., ‘I have proved (<G>e)/grafon</G>) | |
7963 that every cone is one third of the cylinder with the same base and equal | |
7964 height by assuming a lemma similar to that aforesaid.’ | |
7965 <p>I do not deny that Theodorus <I>constructed</I> his ‘roots’; I have no doubt | |
7966 that he did; but this is not what <G>e)/grafe/ ti</G> means.</note> to us a certain thing about square roots | |
7967 (<G>duna/meis</G>), I mean (the square roots, i.e. sides) of three square | |
7968 feet and of five square feet, namely that these roots are not | |
7969 commensurable in length with the foot-length, and he went on | |
7970 in this way, taking all the separate cases up to the root of | |
7971 17 square feet, at which point, for some reason, he stopped’. | |
7972 <p>That is, he proved the irrationality of √3, √5 ... up to | |
7973 √17. It does not appear, however, that he had reached any | |
7974 definition of a surd in general or proved any general proposi- | |
7975 tion about all surds, for Theaetetus goes on to say: | |
7976 <p>‘The idea occurred to the two of us (Theaetetus and the | |
7977 younger Socrates), seeing that these square roots appeared | |
7978 <pb n=204><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
7979 to be unlimited in multitude, to try to arrive at one collective | |
7980 term by which we could designate all these roots . . . We | |
7981 divided number in general into two classes. The number | |
7982 which can be expressed as equal multiplied by equal (<G>i)/son | |
7983 i)sa/kis</G>) we likened to a square in form, and we called it | |
7984 square and equilateral (<G>i)so/pleuron</G>) . . . The intermediate | |
7985 number, such as three, five, and any number which cannot | |
7986 be expressed as equal multiplied by equal, but is either less | |
7987 times more or more times less, so that it is always contained | |
7988 by a greater and a less side, we likened to an oblong figure | |
7989 (<G>promh/kei sxh/mati</G>) and called an oblong number. . . . Such | |
7990 straight lines then as square the equilateral and plane number | |
7991 we defined as <I>length</I> (<G>mh=kos</G>), and such as square the oblong | |
7992 (we called) <I>square roots</I> (<G>duna/meis</G>) as not being commensurable | |
7993 with the others in length but only in the plane areas to which | |
7994 their squares are equal. And there is another distinction of | |
7995 the same sort with regard to solids.’ | |
7996 <p>Plato gives no hint as to how Theodorus proved the proposi- | |
7997 tions attributed to him, namely that √3, √5 ... √17 are | |
7998 all incommensurable with 1; there is therefore a wide field | |
7999 open for speculation, and several conjectures have been put | |
8000 forward. | |
8001 <p>(1) Hultsch, in a paper on Archimedes's approximations to | |
8002 square roots, suggested that Theodorus took the line of seeking | |
8003 successive approximations. Just as 7/5, the first approximation | |
8004 to √2, was obtained by putting 2=50/25, Theodorus might | |
8005 have started from 3=48/16, and found 7/4 or 1 1/2 1/4 as a first | |
8006 approximation, and then, seeing that <MATH>1 1/2 1/4 > √3 > 1 1/2</MATH>, might | |
8007 (by successive trials, probably) have found that | |
8008 <MATH>1 1/2 1/8 1/16 1/32 1/64 > √3 > 1 1/2 1/8 1/16 1/32 1/128</MATH>. | |
8009 But the method of finding closer and closer approximations, | |
8010 although it might afford a presumption that the true value | |
8011 cannot be exactly expressed in fractions, would leave Theodorus | |
8012 as far as ever from <I>proving</I> that √3 is incommensurable. | |
8013 <p>(2) There is no mention of √2 in our passage, and Theodorus | |
8014 probably omitted this case because the incommensurability | |
8015 of √2 and the traditional method of proving it were already | |
8016 known. The traditional proof was, as we have seen, a <I>reductio | |
8017 ad absurdum</I> showing that, if √2 is commensurable with 1, | |
8018 it will follow that the same number is both even and odd, | |
8019 i.e. both divisible and not divisible by 2. The same method | |
8020 <pb n=205><head>THEODORUS OF CYRENE</head> | |
8021 of proof can be adapted to the cases of √3, √5, &c., if 3, 5 ... | |
8022 are substituted for 2 in the proof; e.g. we can prove that, | |
8023 if √3 is commensurable with 1, then the same number will | |
8024 be both divisible and not divisible by 3. One suggestion, | |
8025 therefore, is that Theodorus may have applied this method | |
8026 to all the cases from √3 to √17. We can put the proof | |
8027 quite generally thus. Suppose that <I>N</I> is a non-square number | |
8028 such as 3, 5 ..., and, if possible, let <MATH>√<I>N</I>=<I>m/n</I></MATH>, where <I>m, n</I> | |
8029 are integers prime to one another. | |
8030 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>N</I>.<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>; | |
8031 therefore <I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP> is divisible by <I>N</I>, so that <I>m</I> also is a multiple | |
8032 of <I>N.</I> | |
8033 <p>Let <MATH><I>m</I>=<G>m</G>.<I>N</I>, . . . . . . . . (1)</MATH> | |
8034 and consequently <MATH><I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>N</I>.<G>m</G><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
8035 <p>Then in the same way we can prove that <I>n</I> is a multiple | |
8036 of <I>N</I>. | |
8037 <p>Let <MATH><I>n</I>=<G>n</G>.<I>N</I> . . . . . . . . (2)</MATH> | |
8038 <p>It follows from (1) and (2) that <I>m/n</I>=<G>m</G>/<G>n</G>, where <G>m</G><<I>m</I> | |
8039 and <G>n</G><<I>n</I>; therefore <I>m/n</I> is not in its lowest terms, which | |
8040 is contrary to the hypothesis. | |
8041 <p>The objection to this conjecture as to the nature of | |
8042 Theodorus's proof is that it is so easy an adaptation of the | |
8043 traditional proof regarding √2 that it would hardly be | |
8044 important enough to mention as a new discovery. Also it | |
8045 would be quite unnecessary to repeat the proof for every | |
8046 case up to √17; for it would be clear, long before √17 was | |
8047 reached, that it is generally applicable. The latter objection | |
8048 seems to me to have force. The former objection may or may | |
8049 not; for I do not feel sure that Plato is necessarily attributing | |
8050 any important new discovery to Theodorus. The object of | |
8051 the whole context is to show that a definition by mere | |
8052 enumeration is no definition; e.g. it is no definition of <G>e)pi- | |
8053 sth/mh</G> to enumerate particular <G>e)pisth=mai</G> (as shoemaking, | |
8054 carpentering, and the like); this is to put the cart before the | |
8055 horse, the general definition of <G>e)pisth/mh</G> being logically prior. | |
8056 Hence it was probably Theaetetus's generalization of the | |
8057 procedure of Theodorus which impressed Plato as being | |
8058 original and important rather than Theodorus's proofs them- | |
8059 selves. | |
8060 <pb n=206><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
8061 <p>(3) The third hypothesis is that of Zeuthen.<note>Zeuthen, ‘Sur la constitution des livres arithmétiques des Éléments | |
8062 d'Euclide et leur rapport à la question de l'irrationalité’ in <I>Oversigt over | |
8063 det kgl. Danske videnskabernes Selskabs Forhandlinger</I>, 1915, pp. 422 sq.</note> He starts | |
8064 with the assumptions (<I>a</I>) that the method of proof used by | |
8065 Theodorus must have been original enough to call for special | |
8066 notice from Plato, and (<I>b</I>) that it must have been of such | |
8067 a kind that the application of it to each surd required to be | |
8068 set out separately in consequence of the variations in the | |
8069 numbers entering into the proofs. Neither of these con- | |
8070 ditions is satisfied by the hypothesis of a mere adaptation to | |
8071 √3, √5 ... of the traditional proof with regard to √2. | |
8072 Zeuthen therefore suggests another hypothesis as satisfying | |
8073 both conditions, namely that Theodorus used the criterion | |
8074 furnished by the process of finding the greatest common | |
8075 measure as stated in the theorem of Eucl. X. 2. ‘If, when | |
8076 the lesser of two unequal magnitudes is continually subtracted | |
8077 in turn from the greater [this includes the subtraction | |
8078 from any term of the highest multiple of another that it | |
8079 contains], that which is left never measures the one before | |
8080 it, the magnitudes will be incommensurable’; that is, if two | |
8081 magnitudes are such that the process of finding their G. C. M. | |
8082 never comes to an end, the two magnitudes are incommensur- | |
8083 able. True, the proposition Eucl. X. 2 depends on the famous | |
8084 X. 1 (Given two unequal magnitudes, if from the greater | |
8085 there be subtracted more than the half (or the half), from the | |
8086 remainder more than the half (or the half), and so on, there | |
8087 will be left, ultimately, some magnitude less than the lesser | |
8088 of the original magnitudes), which is based on the famous | |
8089 postulate of Eudoxus (= Eucl. V, Def. 4), and therefore belongs | |
8090 to a later date. Zeuthen gets over this objection by pointing | |
8091 out that the necessity of X. 1 for a rigorous demonstration | |
8092 of X. 2 may not have been noticed at the time; Theodorus | |
8093 may have proceeded by intuition, or he may even have | |
8094 postulated the truth proved in X. 1. | |
8095 <p>The most obvious case in which incommensurability can be | |
8096 proved by using the process of finding the greatest common | |
8097 measure is that of the two segments of a straight line divided | |
8098 in extreme and mean ratio. For, if <I>AB</I> is divided in this way | |
8099 at <I>C</I>, we have only to mark off along <I>CA</I> (the greater segment) | |
8100 <pb n=207><head>THEODORUS OF CYRENE</head> | |
8101 a length <I>CD</I> equal to <I>CB</I> (the lesser segment), and <I>CA</I> is then | |
8102 divided at <I>D</I> in extreme and mean ratio, <I>CD</I> being the | |
8103 greater segment. (Eucl. XIII. 5 is the equivalent of this | |
8104 <FIG> | |
8105 proposition.) Similarly, <I>DC</I> is so divided if we set off <I>DE</I> | |
8106 along it equal to <I>DA</I>; and so on. This is precisely the | |
8107 process of finding the greatest common measure of <I>AC, CB</I>, | |
8108 the quotient being always unity; and the process never comes | |
8109 to an end. Therefore <I>AC, CB</I> are incommensurable. What | |
8110 is proved in this case is the irrationality of 1/2(√5-1). This | |
8111 of course shows incidentally that √5 is incommensurable | |
8112 with 1. It has been suggested, in view of the easiness of the | |
8113 above proof, that the irrational may first have been discovered | |
8114 with reference to the segments of a straight line cut in extreme | |
8115 and mean ratio, rather than with reference to the diagonal | |
8116 of a square in relation to its side. But this seems, on the | |
8117 whole, improbable. | |
8118 <p>Theodorus would, of course, give a geometrical form to the | |
8119 process of finding the G. C. M., after he had represented in | |
8120 a figure the particular surd which he was investigating. | |
8121 Zeuthen illustrates by two cases, √5 and √3. | |
8122 <p>We will take the former, which is the easier. The process | |
8123 of finding the G. C. M. (if any) of √5 and 1 is as follows: | |
8124 <table> | |
8125 <tr><td>1)</td><td>√5(2</td></tr> | |
8126 <tr><td></td><td align=center>2</td></tr> | |
8127 <tr><td></td><td>√5-2)</td><td>1</td><td>(4</td></tr> | |
8128 <tr><td></td><td></td><td>4(√5-2)</td></tr> | |
8129 <tr><td></td><td></td><td>(√5-2)<SUP>2</SUP></td></tr> | |
8130 </table> | |
8131 <p>[The explanation of the second division is this: | |
8132 <MATH>1=(√5-2) (√5+2)=4(√5-2) + (√5-2)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>.] | |
8133 <p>Since, then, the ratio of the last term (√5-2)<SUP>2</SUP> to the pre- | |
8134 ceding one, √5-2, is the same as the ratio of √5-2 to 1, | |
8135 the process will never end. | |
8136 <p>Zeuthen has a geometrical proof which is not difficult; but | |
8137 I think the following proof is neater and easier. | |
8138 <p>Let <I>ABC</I> be a triangle right-angled at <I>B</I>, such that <I>AB</I>=1, | |
8139 <I>BC</I>=2, and therefore <I>AC</I>=√5. | |
8140 <pb n=208><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
8141 <p>Cut off <I>CD</I> from <I>CA</I> equal to <I>CB</I>, and draw <I>DE</I> at right | |
8142 angles to <I>CA</I>. Then <I>DE</I>=<I>EB</I>. | |
8143 <p>Now <MATH><I>AD</I>=√5-2</MATH>, and by similar triangles | |
8144 <MATH><I>DE</I>=2<I>AD</I>=2(√5-2)</MATH>. | |
8145 <FIG> | |
8146 <p>Cut off from <I>EA</I> the portion <I>EF</I> equal to | |
8147 <I>ED</I>, and draw <I>FG</I> at right angles to <I>AE.</I> | |
8148 <p>Then <MATH><I>AF</I>=<I>AB</I> - <I>BF</I>=<I>AB</I> - 2<I>DE</I> | |
8149 = 1-4(√5-2) | |
8150 = (√5-2)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
8151 <p>Therefore <I>ABC, ADE, AFG</I> are diminishing | |
8152 similar triangles such that | |
8153 <MATH><I>AB</I>:<I>AD</I>:<I>AF</I>=1:(√5-2):(√5-2)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
8154 and so on. | |
8155 <p>Also <I>AB</I> > <I>FB</I>, i.e. 2 <I>DE</I> or 4<I>AD.</I> | |
8156 <p>Therefore the side of each triangle in the series is less than | |
8157 1/4 of the corresponding side of the preceding triangle. | |
8158 <p>In the case of √3 the process of finding the G. C. M. of | |
8159 √3 and 1 gives | |
8160 <MATH></MATH> | |
8161 the ratio of 1/2(√3-1)<SUP>2</SUP> to 1/2(√3-1)<SUP>3</SUP> being the same as that | |
8162 of 1 to (√3-1). | |
8163 <p>This case is more difficult to show in geometrical form | |
8164 because we have to make one more | |
8165 <FIG> | |
8166 division before recurrence takes place. | |
8167 <p>The cases √10 and √17 are exactly | |
8168 similar to that of √5. | |
8169 <p>The irrationality of √2 can, of course, | |
8170 be proved by the same method. If <I>ABCD</I> | |
8171 is a square, we mark off along the diagonal | |
8172 <I>AC</I> a length <I>AE</I> equal to <I>AB</I> and draw | |
8173 <I>EF</I> at right angles to <I>AC.</I> The same | |
8174 thing is then done with the triangle <I>CEF</I> | |
8175 <pb n=209><head>THEODORUS OF CYRENE</head> | |
8176 as with the triangle <I>ABC</I>, and so on. This could not have | |
8177 escaped Theodorus if his proof in the cases of √3, √5 ... | |
8178 took the form suggested by Zeuthen; but he was presumably | |
8179 content to accept the traditional proof with regard to √2. | |
8180 <p>The conjecture of Zeuthen is very ingenious, but, as he | |
8181 admits, it necessarily remains a hypothesis. | |
8182 <p>THEAETETUS<note>On Theaetetus the reader may consult a recent dissertation, <I>De Theae- | |
8183 teto Atheniensi mathematico</I>, by Eva Sachs (Berlin, 1914).</note> (about 415-369 B. C.) made important contribu- | |
8184 tions to the body of the Elements. These related to two | |
8185 subjects in particular, (<I>a</I>) the theory of irrationals, and (<I>b</I>) the | |
8186 five regular solids. | |
8187 <p>That Theaetetus actually succeeded in generalizing the | |
8188 theory of irrationals on the lines indicated in the second part | |
8189 of the passage from Plato's dialogue is confirmed by other | |
8190 evidence. The commentary on Eucl. X, which has survived | |
8191 in Arabic and is attributed to Pappus, says (in the passage | |
8192 partly quoted above, p. 155) that the theory of irrationals | |
8193 <p>‘had its origin in the school of Pythagoras. It was con- | |
8194 siderably developed by Theaetetus the Athenian, who gave | |
8195 proof in this part of mathematics, as in others, of ability | |
8196 which has been justly admired. . . . As for the exact dis- | |
8197 tinctions of the above-named magnitudes and the rigorous | |
8198 demonstrations of the propositions to which this theory gives | |
8199 rise, I believe that they were chiefly established by this | |
8200 mathematician. For Theaetetus had distinguished square | |
8201 roots<note>‘Square roots’. The word in Woepcke's translation is ‘puissances’, | |
8202 which indicates that the original word was <G>duna/meis</G>. This word is always | |
8203 ambiguous; it might mean ‘squares’, but I have translated it ‘square | |
8204 roots’ because the <G>du/namis</G> of Theaetetus's definition is undoubtedly the | |
8205 square root of a non-square number, a surd. The distinction in that case | |
8206 would appear to be between ‘square roots’ commensurable in length and | |
8207 square roots commensurable in square only; thus √3 and √12 are | |
8208 commensurable in length, while √3 and √7 are commensurable in | |
8209 square only. I do not see how <G>duna/meis</G> could here mean squares; for | |
8210 ‘squares commensurable in length’ is not an intelligible phrase, and it | |
8211 does not seem legitimate to expand it into ‘squares <on straight lines> | |
8212 commensurable in length’.</note> commensurable in length from those which are incom- | |
8213 mensurable, and had divided the well-known species of | |
8214 irrational lines after the different means, assigning the <I>medial</I> | |
8215 to geometry, the <I>binomial</I> to arithmetic, and the <I>apotome</I> to | |
8216 harmony, as is stated by Eudemus the Peripatetic.’<note>For an explanation of this see <I>The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements</I> | |
8217 vol. iii, p. 4.</note> | |
8218 <pb n=210><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
8219 <p>The irrationals called by the names here italicized are | |
8220 described in Eucl. X. 21, 36 and 73 respectively. | |
8221 <p>Again, a scholiast<note>X, No. 62 (Heiberg's Euclid, vol. v, p. 450).</note> on Eucl. X. 9 (containing the general | |
8222 theorem that squares which have not to one another the ratio | |
8223 of a square number to a square number have their sides | |
8224 incommensurable in length) definitely attributes the discovery | |
8225 of this theorem to Theaetetus. But, in accordance with the | |
8226 traditional practice in Greek geometry, it was necessary to | |
8227 prove the existence of such incommensurable ratios, and this | |
8228 is done in the porism to Eucl. X. 6 by a geometrical con- | |
8229 struction; the porism first states that, given a straight line <I>a</I> | |
8230 and any two numbers <I>m, n</I>, we can find a straight line <I>x</I> such | |
8231 that <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>x</I>=<I>m</I>:<I>n</I></MATH>; next it is shown that, if <I>y</I> be taken a mean | |
8232 proportional between <I>a</I> and <I>x</I>, then | |
8233 <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>a</I>:<I>x</I>=<I>m</I>:<I>n</I></MATH>; | |
8234 if, therefore, the ratio <I>m</I>:<I>n</I> is not a ratio of a square to | |
8235 a square, we have constructed an irrational straight line | |
8236 <I>a</I>√(<I>n</I>/<I>m</I>) and therefore shown that such a straight line | |
8237 exists. | |
8238 <p>The proof of Eucl. X. 9 formally depends on VIII. 11 alone | |
8239 (to the effect that between two square numbers there is one | |
8240 mean proportional number, and the square has to the square | |
8241 the duplicate ratio of that which the side has to the side); | |
8242 and VIII. 11 again depends on VII. 17 and 18 (to the effect | |
8243 that <MATH><I>ab</I>:<I>ac</I>=<I>b</I>:<I>c</I></MATH>, and <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>ac</I>:<I>bc</I></MATH>, propositions which are | |
8244 not identical). But Zeuthen points out that these propositions | |
8245 are an inseparable part of a whole theory established in | |
8246 Book VII and the early part of Book VIII, and that the | |
8247 real demonstration of X. 9 is rather contained in propositions | |
8248 of these Books which give a rigorous proof of the necessary | |
8249 and sufficient conditions for the rationality of the square | |
8250 roots of numerical fractions and integral numbers, notably | |
8251 VII. 27 and the propositions leading up to it, as well as | |
8252 VIII. 2. He therefore suggests that the theory established | |
8253 in the early part of Book VII was not due to the Pytha- | |
8254 goreans, but was an innovation made by Theaetetus with the | |
8255 direct object of laying down a scientific basis for his theory | |
8256 of irrationals, and that this, rather than the mere formulation | |
8257 <pb n=211><head>THEAETETUS</head> | |
8258 of the theorem of Eucl. X. 9, was the achievement which Plato | |
8259 intended to hold up to admiration. | |
8260 <p>This conjecture is of great interest, but it is, so far as | |
8261 I know, without any positive confirmation. On the other | |
8262 hand, there are circumstances which suggest doubts. For | |
8263 example, Zeuthen himself admits that Hippocrates, who re- | |
8264 duced the duplication of the cube to the finding of two mean | |
8265 proportionals, must have had a proposition corresponding to | |
8266 the very proposition VIII. 11 on which X. 9 formally depends. | |
8267 Secondly, in the extract from Simplicius about the squaring | |
8268 of lunes by Hippocrates, we have seen that the proportionality | |
8269 of similar segments of circles to the circles of which they form | |
8270 part is explained by the statement that ‘similar segments are | |
8271 those which are <I>the same part</I> of the circles’; and if we may | |
8272 take this to be a quotation by Eudemus from Hippocrates's | |
8273 own argument, the inference is that Hippocrates had a defini- | |
8274 tion of numerical proportion which was at all events near | |
8275 to that of Eucl. VII, Def. 20. Thirdly, there is the proof | |
8276 (presently to be given) by Archytas of the proposition that | |
8277 there can be no number which is a (geometric) mean between | |
8278 two consecutive integral numbers, in which proof it will | |
8279 be seen that several propositions of Eucl., Book VII, are | |
8280 pre-supposed; but Archytas lived (say) 430-365 B.C., and | |
8281 Theaetetus was some years younger. I am not, therefore, | |
8282 prepared to give up the view, which has hitherto found | |
8283 general acceptance, that the Pythagoreans already had a | |
8284 theory of proportion of a numerical kind on the lines, though | |
8285 not necessarily or even probably with anything like the | |
8286 fullness and elaboration, of Eucl., Book VII. | |
8287 <p>While Pappus, in the commentary quoted, says that Theae- | |
8288 tetus distinguished the well-known species of irrationals, and | |
8289 in particular the <I>medial</I>, the <I>binomial</I>, and the <I>apotome</I>, he | |
8290 proceeds thus: | |
8291 <p>‘As for Euclid, he set himself to give rigorous rules, which | |
8292 he established, relative to commensurability and incommen- | |
8293 surability in general; he made precise the definitions and | |
8294 distinctions between rational and irrational magnitudes, he | |
8295 set out a great number of orders of irrational magnitudes, | |
8296 and finally he made clear their whole extent.’ | |
8297 <p>As Euclid proves that there are thirteen irrational straight | |
8298 <pb n=212><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
8299 lines in all, we may perhaps assume that the subdivision of | |
8300 the three species of irrationals distinguished by Theaetetus | |
8301 into thirteen was due to Euclid himself, while the last words | |
8302 of the quotation seem to refer to Eucl. X. 115, where it is | |
8303 proved that from the <I>medial</I> straight line an unlimited number | |
8304 of other irrationals can be derived which are all different from | |
8305 it and from one another. | |
8306 <p>It will be remembered that, at the end of the passage of the | |
8307 <I>Theaetetus</I> containing the definition of ‘square roots’ or surds, | |
8308 Theaetetus says that ‘there is a similar distinction in the case | |
8309 of solids’. We know nothing of any further development | |
8310 of a theory of irrationals arising from solids; but Theaetetus | |
8311 doubtless had in mind a distinction related to VIII. 12 (the | |
8312 theorem that between two cube numbers there are two mean | |
8313 proportional numbers) in the same way as the definition of | |
8314 a ‘square root’ or surd is related to VIII. 11; that is to say, | |
8315 he referred to the incommensurable cube root of a non-cube | |
8316 number which is the product of three factors. | |
8317 <p>Besides laying the foundation of the theory of irrationals | |
8318 as we find it in Eucl., Book X, Theaetetus contributed no less | |
8319 substantially to another portion of the <I>Elements</I>, namely | |
8320 Book XIII, which is devoted (after twelve introductory | |
8321 propositions) to constructing the five regular solids, circum- | |
8322 scribing spheres about them, and finding the relation between | |
8323 the dimensions of the respective solids and the circumscribing | |
8324 spheres. We have already mentioned (pp. 159, 162) the tradi- | |
8325 tions that Theaetetus was the first to ‘construct’ or ‘write upon’ | |
8326 the five regular solids,<note>Suidas, <I>s. v.</I> <G>*qeai/thtos</G>.</note> and that his name was specially | |
8327 associated with the octahedron and the icosahedron.<note>Schol. 1 to Eucl. XIII (Euclid, ed. Heiberg, vol. v, p. 654).</note> There | |
8328 can be little doubt that Theaetetus's ‘construction’ of, or | |
8329 treatise upon, the regular solids gave the theoretical con- | |
8330 structions much as we find them in Euclid. | |
8331 <p>Of the mathematicians of Plato's time, two others are | |
8332 mentioned with Theaetetus as having increased the number | |
8333 of theorems in geometry and made a further advance towards | |
8334 a scientific grouping of them, LEODAMAS OF THASOS and | |
8335 ARCHYTAS OF TARAS. With regard to the former we are | |
8336 <pb n=213><head>ARCHYTAS</head> | |
8337 told that Plato ‘explained (<G>ei)shgh/sato</G>) to Leodamas of Thasos | |
8338 the method of inquiry by analysis’<note>Diog. L. iii. 24.</note>; Proclus's account is | |
8339 fuller, stating that the finest method for discovering lemmas | |
8340 in geometry is that ‘which by means of <I>analysis</I> carries the | |
8341 thing sought up to an acknowledged principle, a method | |
8342 which Plato, as they say, communicated to Leodamas, and | |
8343 by which the latter too is said to have discovered many | |
8344 things in geometry’.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 211. 19-23.</note> Nothing more than this is known of | |
8345 Leodamas, but the passages are noteworthy as having given | |
8346 rise to the idea that Plato <I>invented</I> the method of mathe- | |
8347 matical analysis, an idea which, as we shall see later on, seems | |
8348 nevertheless to be based on a misapprehension. | |
8349 <p>ARCHYTAS OF TARAS, a Pythagorean, the friend of Plato, | |
8350 flourished in the first half of the fourth century, say 400 to | |
8351 365 B.C. Plato made his acquaintance when staying in Magna | |
8352 Graecia, and he is said, by means of a letter, to have saved | |
8353 Plato from death at the hands of Dionysius. Statesman and | |
8354 philosopher, he was famed for every sort of accomplishment. | |
8355 He was general of the forces of his city-state for seven years, | |
8356 though ordinarily the law forbade any one to hold the post | |
8357 for more than a year; and he was never beaten. He is | |
8358 said to have been the first to write a systematic treatise on | |
8359 <I>mechanics</I> based on mathematical principles.<note>Diog. L. viii. 79-83.</note> Vitruvius men- | |
8360 tions that, like Archimedes, Ctesibius, Nymphodorus, and | |
8361 Philo of Byzantium, Archytas wrote on machines<note>Vitruvius, <I>De architectura</I>, Praef. vii. 14.</note>; two | |
8362 mechanical devices in particular are attributed to him, one | |
8363 a mechanical dove made of wood which would fly,<note>Gellius, x. 12. 8, after Favorinus (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 325. 21-9).</note> the | |
8364 other a rattle which, according to Aristotle, was found useful | |
8365 to ‘give to children to occupy them, and so prevent them | |
8366 from breaking things about the house (for the young are | |
8367 incapable of keeping still)’.<note>Aristotle, <I>Polítics</I>, E (<G>*q</G>). 6, 1340 b 26.</note> | |
8368 <p>We have already seen Archytas distinguishing the four | |
8369 mathematical sciences, geometry, arithmetic, sphaeric (or | |
8370 astronomy), and music, comparing the art of calculation with | |
8371 geometry in respect of its relative efficiency and conclusive- | |
8372 ness, and defining the three means in music, the arithmetic, | |
8373 <pb n=214><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
8374 the geometric, and the harmonic (a name substituted by | |
8375 Archytas and Hippasus for the older name ‘sub-contrary’). | |
8376 <p>From his mention of <I>sphaeric</I> in connexion with his state- | |
8377 ment that ‘the mathematicians have given us clear knowledge | |
8378 about the speed of the heavenly bodies and their risings and | |
8379 settings’ we gather that in Archytas's time astronomy was | |
8380 already treated mathematically, the properties of the sphere | |
8381 being studied so far as necessary to explain the movements | |
8382 in the celestial sphere. He discussed too the question whether | |
8383 the universe is unlimited in extent, using the following | |
8384 argument. | |
8385 <p>‘If I were at the outside, say at the heaven of the fixed | |
8386 stars, could I stretch my hand or my stick outwards or not? | |
8387 To suppose that I could not is absurd; and if I can stretch | |
8388 it out, that which is outside must be either body or space (it | |
8389 makes no difference which it is, as we shall see). We may | |
8390 then in the same way get to the outside of that again, and | |
8391 so on, asking on arrival at each new limit the same question; | |
8392 and if there is always a new place to which the stick may be | |
8393 held out, this clearly involves extension without limit. If | |
8394 now what so extends is body, the proposition is proved; but | |
8395 even if it is space, then, since space is that in which body | |
8396 is or can be, and in the case of eternal things we must treat | |
8397 that which potentially is as being, it follows equally that there | |
8398 must be body and space (extending) without limit.’<note>Simplicius <I>in Phys.</I>, p. 467. 26.</note> | |
8399 <p>In <I>geometry</I>, while Archytas doubtless increased the number | |
8400 of theorems (as Proclus says), only one fragment of his has | |
8401 survived, namely the solution of the problem of finding two | |
8402 mean proportionals (equivalent to the duplication of the cube) | |
8403 by a remarkable theoretical construction in three dimensions. | |
8404 As this, however, belongs to higher geometry and not to the | |
8405 Elements, the description of it will come more appropriately | |
8406 in another place (pp. 246-9). | |
8407 <p>In <I>music</I> he gave the numerical ratios representing the | |
8408 intervals of the tetrachord on three scales, the anharmonic, | |
8409 the chromatic, and the diatonic.<note>Ptol. <I>harm.</I> i. 13, p. 31 Wall.</note> He held that sound is due | |
8410 to impact, and that higher tones correspond to quicker motion | |
8411 communicated to the air, and lower tones to slower motion.<note>Porph. <I>in Ptol. harm.</I>, p. 236 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 232-3); Theon of Smyrna, | |
8412 p. 61. 11-17.</note> | |
8413 <pb n=215><head>ARCHYTAS</head> | |
8414 <p>Of the fragments of Archytas handed down to us the most | |
8415 interesting from the point of view of this chapter is a proof | |
8416 of the proposition that there can be no number which is | |
8417 a (geometric) mean between two numbers in the ratio known | |
8418 as <G>e)pimo/rios</G> or <I>superparticularis</I>, that is, (<I>n</I>+1):<I>n.</I> This | |
8419 proof is preserved by Boetius<note>Boetius, <I>De inst. mus.</I> iii. 11, pp. 285-6 Friedlein.</note>, and the noteworthy fact about | |
8420 it is that it is substantially identical with the proof of the | |
8421 same theorem in Prop. 3 of Euclid's tract on the <I>Sectio | |
8422 canonis.</I><note><I>Musici scriptores Graeci</I>, ed. Jan, p. 14; Heiberg and Menge's Euclid, | |
8423 vol. viii, p. 162.</note> I will quote Archytas's proof in full, in order to | |
8424 show the slight differences from the Euclidean form and | |
8425 notation. | |
8426 <p>Let <I>A, B</I> be the given ‘superparticularis proportio’ (<G>e)pi- | |
8427 mo/rion dia/sthma</G> in Euclid). [Archytas writes the smaller | |
8428 number first (instead of second, as Euclid does); we are then | |
8429 to suppose that <I>A, B</I> are integral numbers in the ratio of | |
8430 <I>n</I> to (<I>n</I>+1).] | |
8431 <p>Take <I>C, DE</I> the smallest numbers which are in the ratio | |
8432 of <I>A</I> to <I>B.</I> [Here <I>DE</I> means <I>D</I>+<I>E</I>; in this respect the | |
8433 notation differs from that of Euclid, who, as usual, takes | |
8434 a straight line <I>DF</I> divided into two parts at <I>G</I>, the parts | |
8435 <I>DG, GF</I> corresponding to the <I>D</I> and <I>E</I> respectively in | |
8436 Archytas's proof. The step of finding <I>C, DE</I> the smallest | |
8437 numbers in the same ratio as that of <I>A</I> to <I>B</I> presupposes | |
8438 Eucl. VII. 33 applied to two numbers.] | |
8439 <p>Then <I>DE</I> exceeds <I>C</I> by an aliquot part of itself and of <I>C</I> | |
8440 [cf. the definition of <G>e)pimo/rios a)riqmo/s</G> in Nicomachus, i. 19. 1]. | |
8441 <p>Let <I>D</I> be the excess [i.e. we suppose <I>E</I> equal to <I>C</I>]. | |
8442 <p>I say that <I>D</I> is not a number, but a unit. | |
8443 <p>For, if <I>D</I> is a number and an aliquot part of <I>DE</I>, it measures | |
8444 <I>DE</I>; therefore it measures <I>E</I>, that is, <I>C.</I> | |
8445 <p>Thus <I>D</I> measures both <I>C</I> and <I>DE</I>: which is impossible, | |
8446 since the smallest numbers which are in the same ratio as | |
8447 any numbers are prime to one another. [This presupposes | |
8448 Eucl. VII. 22.] | |
8449 <p>Therefore <I>D</I> is a unit; that is, <I>DE</I> exceeds <I>C</I> by a unit. | |
8450 <p>Hence no number can be found which is a mean between | |
8451 the two numbers <I>C, DE</I> [for there is no <I>integer</I> intervening]. | |
8452 <pb n=216><head>THE ELEMENTS DOWN TO PLATO'S TIME</head> | |
8453 <p>Therefore neither can any number be a mean between the | |
8454 original numbers <I>A, B</I>, which are in the same ratio as <I>C, DE</I> | |
8455 [cf. the more general proposition, Eucl. VIII. 8; the particular | |
8456 inference is a consequence of Eucl. VII. 20, to the effect that | |
8457 the least numbers of those which have the same ratio with | |
8458 them measure the latter the same number of times, the greater | |
8459 the greater and the less the less]. | |
8460 <p>Since this proof cites as known several propositions corre- | |
8461 sponding to propositions in Euclid, Book VII, it affords a strong | |
8462 presumption that there already existed, at least as early as | |
8463 the time of Archytas, a treatise of some sort on the Elements | |
8464 of Arithmetic in a form similar to the Euclidean, and con- | |
8465 taining many of the propositions afterwards embodied by | |
8466 Euclid in his arithmetical books. | |
8467 <C>Summary.</C> | |
8468 <p>We are now in a position to form an idea of the scope of | |
8469 the Elements at the stage which they had reached in Plato's | |
8470 time. The substance of Eucl. I-IV was practically complete. | |
8471 Book V was of course missing, because the theory of proportion | |
8472 elaborated in that book was the creation of Eudoxus. The | |
8473 Pythagoreans had a theory of proportion applicable to com- | |
8474 mensurable magnitudes only; this was probably a numerical | |
8475 theory on lines similar to those of Eucl., Book VII. But the | |
8476 theorems of Eucl., Book VI, in general, albeit insufficiently | |
8477 established in so far as they depended on the numerical theory | |
8478 of proportion, were known and used by the Pythagoreans. | |
8479 We have seen reason to suppose that there existed Elements | |
8480 of Arithmetic partly (at all events) on the lines of Eucl., | |
8481 Book VII, while some propositions of Book VIII (e.g. Props. | |
8482 11 and 12) were also common property. The Pythagoreans, | |
8483 too, conceived the idea of perfect numbers (numbers equal to | |
8484 the sum of all their divisors) if they had not actually shown | |
8485 (as Euclid does in IX. 36) how they are evolved. There can | |
8486 also be little doubt that many of the properties of plane and | |
8487 solid numbers and of similar numbers of both classes proved in | |
8488 Euclid, Books VIII and IX, were known before Plato's time. | |
8489 <p>We come next to Book X, and it is plain that the foundation | |
8490 of the whole had been well and truly laid by Theaetetus, and | |
8491 <pb n=217><head>SUMMARY</head> | |
8492 the main varieties of irrationals distinguished, though their | |
8493 classification was not carried so far as in Euclid. | |
8494 <p>The substance of Book XI. 1-19 must already have been in- | |
8495 cluded in the Elements (e.g. Eucl. XI. 19 is assumed in Archytas's | |
8496 construction for the two mean proportionals), and the whole | |
8497 theory of the section of Book XI in question would be required | |
8498 for Theaetetus's work on the five regular solids: XI. 21 must | |
8499 have been known to the Pythagoreans: while there is nothing | |
8500 in the latter portion of the book about parallelepipedal solids | |
8501 which (subject to the want of a rigorous theory of proportion) | |
8502 was not within the powers of those who were familiar with | |
8503 the theory of plane and solid numbers. | |
8504 <p>Book XII employs throughout the <I>method of exhaustion</I>, | |
8505 the orthodox form of which is attributed to Eudoxus, who | |
8506 grounded it upon a lemma known as Archimedes's Axiom or | |
8507 its equivalent (Eucl. X. 1). Yet even XII. 2, to the effect that | |
8508 circles are to one another as the square of their diameters, had | |
8509 already been anticipated by Hippocrates of Chios, while | |
8510 Democritus had discovered the truth of the theorems of | |
8511 XII. 7, Por., about the volume of a pyramid, and XII. 10, | |
8512 about the volume of a cone. | |
8513 <p>As in the case of Book X, it would appear that Euclid was | |
8514 indebted to Theaetetus for much of the substance of Book XIII, | |
8515 the latter part of which (Props. 12-18) is devoted to the | |
8516 construction of the five regular solids, and the inscribing of | |
8517 them in spheres. | |
8518 <p>There is therefore probably little in the whole compass of | |
8519 the <I>Elements</I> of Euclid, except the new theory of proportion due | |
8520 to Eudoxus and its consequences, which was not in substance | |
8521 included in the recognized content of geometry and arithmetic | |
8522 by Plato's time, although the form and arrangement of the | |
8523 subject-matter and the methods employed in particular cases | |
8524 were different from what we find in Euclid. | |
8525 <pb> | |
8526 <C>VII | |
8527 SPECIAL PROBLEMS</C> | |
8528 <p>SIMULTANEOUSLY with the gradual evolution of the Elements, | |
8529 the Greeks were occupying themselves with problems in | |
8530 higher geometry; three problems in particular, the squaring | |
8531 of the circle, the doubling of the cube, and the trisection of | |
8532 any given angle, were rallying-points for mathematicians | |
8533 during three centuries at least, and the whole course of Greek | |
8534 geometry was profoundly influenced by the character of the | |
8535 specialized investigations which had their origin in the attempts | |
8536 to solve these problems. In illustration we need only refer | |
8537 to the subject of conic sections which began with the use | |
8538 made of two of the curves for the finding of two mean pro- | |
8539 portionals. | |
8540 <p>The Greeks classified problems according to the means by | |
8541 which they were solved. The ancients, says Pappus, divided | |
8542 them into three classes, which they called <I>plane, solid</I>, and | |
8543 <I>linear</I> respectively. Problems were <I>plane</I> if they could be | |
8544 solved by means of the straight line and circle only, <I>solid</I> | |
8545 if they could be solved by means of one or more conic sections, | |
8546 and <I>linear</I> if their solution required the use of other curves | |
8547 still more complicated and difficult to construct, such as spirals, | |
8548 <I>quadratrices</I>, cochloids (conchoids) and cissoids, or again the | |
8549 various curves included in the class of ‘loci on surfaces’ (<G>to/poi | |
8550 pro\s e)pifanei/ais</G>), as they were called.<note>Pappus, iii, pp. 54-6, iv, pp. 270-2.</note> There was a corre- | |
8551 sponding distinction between loci: <I>plane</I> loci are straight | |
8552 lines or circles; <I>solid</I> loci are, according to the most strict | |
8553 classification, conics only, which arise from the sections of | |
8554 certain solids, namely cones; while <I>linear</I> loci include all | |
8555 <pb n=219><head>CLASSIFICATION OF PROBLEMS</head> | |
8556 higher curves.<note>Cf. Pappus, vii, p. 662, 10-15.</note> Another classification of loci divides them | |
8557 into <I>loci on lines</I> (<G>to/poi pro\s grammai=s</G>) and <I>loci on surfaces</I> | |
8558 (<G>to/poi pro\s e)pifanei/ais</G>).<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 394. 19.</note> The former term is found in | |
8559 Proclus, and seems to be used in the sense both of loci which | |
8560 <I>are</I> lines (including of course curves) and of loci which are | |
8561 spaces bounded by lines; e.g. Proclus speaks of ‘the whole | |
8562 space between the parallels’ in Eucl. I. 35 as being the locus | |
8563 of the (equal) parallelograms ‘on the same base and in the | |
8564 same parallels’.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 395. 5.</note> Similarly <I>loci on surfaces</I> in Proclus may | |
8565 be loci which <I>are</I> surfaces; but Pappus, who gives lemmas | |
8566 to the two books of Euclid under that title, seems to imply | |
8567 that they were curves drawn on surfaces, e.g. the cylindrical | |
8568 helix.<note>Pappus, iv, p. 258 sq.</note> | |
8569 <p>It is evident that the Greek geometers came very early | |
8570 to the conclusion that the three problems in question were not | |
8571 <I>plane</I>, but required for their solution either higher curves | |
8572 than circles or constructions more mechanical in character | |
8573 than the mere use of the ruler and compasses in the sense of | |
8574 Euclid's Postulates 1-3. It was probably about 420 B.C. that | |
8575 Hippias of Elis invented the curve known as the <I>quadratrix</I> | |
8576 for the purpose of trisecting any angle, and it was in the first | |
8577 half of the fourth century that Archytas used for the dupli- | |
8578 cation of the cube a solid construction involving the revolution | |
8579 of plane figures in space, one of which made a <I>tore</I> or anchor- | |
8580 ring with internal diameter <I>nil.</I> There are very few records | |
8581 of illusory attempts to do the impossible in these cases. It is | |
8582 practically only in the case of the squaring of the circle that | |
8583 we read of abortive efforts made by ‘plane’ methods, and none | |
8584 of these (with the possible exception of Bryson's, if the | |
8585 accounts of his argument are correct) involved any real | |
8586 fallacy. On the other hand, the bold pronouncement of | |
8587 Antiphon the Sophist that by inscribing in a circle a series | |
8588 of regular polygons each of which has twice as many sides | |
8589 as the preceding one, we shall use up or exhaust the area of | |
8590 the circle, though it was in advance of his time and was | |
8591 condemned as a fallacy on the technical ground that a straight | |
8592 line cannot coincide with an arc of a circle however short | |
8593 its length, contained an idea destined to be fruitful in the | |
8594 <pb n=220><head>SPECIAL PROBLEMS</head> | |
8595 hands of later and abler geometers, since it gives a method | |
8596 of approximating, with any desired degree of accuracy, to the | |
8597 area of a circle, and lies at the root of the <I>method of exhaustion</I> | |
8598 as established by Eudoxus. As regards Hippocrates's quadra- | |
8599 ture of lunes, we must, notwithstanding the criticism of | |
8600 Aristotle charging him with a paralogism, decline to believe | |
8601 that he was under any illusion as to the limits of what his | |
8602 method could accomplish, or thought that he had actually | |
8603 squared the circle. | |
8604 <C>The squaring of the circle.</C> | |
8605 <p>There is presumably no problem which has exercised such | |
8606 a fascination throughout the ages as that of rectifying or | |
8607 squaring the circle; and it is a curious fact that its attraction | |
8608 has been no less (perhaps even greater) for the non-mathe- | |
8609 matician than for the mathematician. It was naturally the | |
8610 kind of problem which the Greeks, of all people, would take | |
8611 up with zest the moment that its difficulty was realized. The | |
8612 first name connected with the problem is Anaxagoras, who | |
8613 is said to have occupied himself with it when in prison.<note>Plutarch, <I>De exil.</I> 17, p. 607 F.</note> | |
8614 The Pythagoreans claimed that it was solved in their school, | |
8615 ‘as is clear from the demonstrations of Sextus the Pythagorean, | |
8616 who got his method of demonstration from early tradition’<note>Iambl. ap. Simpl. <I>in Categ.</I>, p. 192, 16-19 K., 64 b 11 Brandis.</note>; | |
8617 but Sextus, or rather Sextius, lived in the reign of Augustus | |
8618 or Tiberius, and, for the usual reasons, no value can be | |
8619 attached to the statement. | |
8620 <p>The first serious attempts to solve the problem belong to | |
8621 the second half of the fifth century B.C. A passage of | |
8622 Aristophanes's <I>Birds</I> is quoted as evidence of the popularity | |
8623 of the problem at the time (414 B.C.) of its first representation. | |
8624 Aristophanes introduces Meton, the astronomer and discoverer | |
8625 of the Metonic cycle of 19 years, who brings with him a ruler | |
8626 and compasses, and makes a certain construction ‘in order that | |
8627 your circle may become square’.<note>Aristophanes, <I>Birds</I> 1005.</note> This is a play upon words, | |
8628 because what Meton really does is to divide a circle into four | |
8629 quadrants by two diameters at right angles to one another; | |
8630 the idea is of streets radiating from the agora in the centre | |
8631 <pb n=221><head>THE SQUARING OF THE CIRCLE</head> | |
8632 of a town; the word <G>tetra/gwnos</G> then really means ‘with four | |
8633 (right) angles’ (at the centre), and not ‘square’, but the word | |
8634 conveys a laughing allusion to the problem of squaring all | |
8635 the same. | |
8636 <p>We have already given an account of Hippocrates's quadra- | |
8637 tures of lunes. These formed a sort of <I>prolusio</I>, and clearly | |
8638 did not purport to be a solution of the problem; Hippocrates | |
8639 was aware that ‘plane’ methods would not solve it, but, as | |
8640 a matter of interest, he wished to show that, if circles could | |
8641 not be squared by these methods, they could be employed | |
8642 to find the area of <I>some</I> figures bounded by arcs of circles, | |
8643 namely certain lunes, and even of the sum of a certain circle | |
8644 and a certain lune. | |
8645 <p>ANTIPHON of Athens, the Sophist and a contemporary of | |
8646 Socrates, is the next person to claim attention. We owe | |
8647 to Aristotle and his commentators our knowledge of Anti- | |
8648 phon's method. Aristotle observes that a geometer is only | |
8649 concerned to refute any fallacious arguments that may be | |
8650 propounded in his subject if they are based upon the admitted | |
8651 principles of geometry; if they are not so based, he is not | |
8652 concerned to refute them: | |
8653 <p>‘thus it is the geometer's business to refute the quadrature by | |
8654 means of segments, but it is not his business to refute that | |
8655 of Antiphon’.<note>Arist. <I>Phys.</I> i. 2, 185 a 14-17.</note> | |
8656 <FIG> | |
8657 <p>As we have seen, the quadrature ‘by means of segments’ is | |
8658 probably Hippocrates's quad- | |
8659 rature of lunes. Antiphon's | |
8660 method is indicated by Themis- | |
8661 tius<note>Them. <I>in Phys.</I>, p. 4. 2 sq., Schenkl.</note> and Simplicius.<note>Simpl. <I>in Phys.</I>, p. 54. 20-55. 24, Diels.</note> Suppose | |
8662 there is any regular polygon | |
8663 inscribed in a circle, e.g. a square | |
8664 or an equilateral triangle. (Ac- | |
8665 cording to Themistius, Antiphon | |
8666 began with an equilateral triangle, | |
8667 and this seems to be the authentic | |
8668 version; Simplicius says he in- | |
8669 scribed some one of the regular polygons which can be inscribed | |
8670 <pb n=222><head>THE SQUARING OF THE CIRCLE</head> | |
8671 in a circle, ‘suppose, if it so happen, that the inscribed polygon | |
8672 is a square’.) On each side of the inscribed triangle or square | |
8673 as base describe an isosceles triangle with its vertex on the | |
8674 arc of the smaller segment of the circle subtended by the side. | |
8675 This gives a regular inscribed polygon with double the number | |
8676 of sides. Repeat the construction with the new polygon, and | |
8677 we have an inscribed polygon with four times as many sides as | |
8678 the original polygon had. Continuing the process, | |
8679 <p>‘Antiphon thought that in this way the area (of the circle) | |
8680 would be used up, and we should some time have a polygon | |
8681 inscribed in the circle the sides of which would, owing to their | |
8682 smallness, coincide with the circumference of the circle. And, | |
8683 as we can make a square equal to any polygon ... we shall | |
8684 be in a position to make a square equal to a circle.’ | |
8685 <p>Simplicius tells us that, while according to Alexander the | |
8686 geometrical principle hereby infringed is the truth that a circle | |
8687 touches a straight line in one point (only), Eudemus more | |
8688 correctly said it was the principle that magnitudes are divisible | |
8689 without limit; for, if the area of the circle is divisible without | |
8690 limit, the process described by Antiphon will never result in | |
8691 using up the whole area, or in making the sides of the polygon | |
8692 take the position of the actual circumference of the circle. | |
8693 But the objection to Antiphon's statement is really no more than | |
8694 verbal; Euclid uses exactly the same construction in XII. 2, | |
8695 only he expresses the conclusion in a different way, saying | |
8696 that, if the process be continued far enough, the small seg- | |
8697 ments left over will be together less than any assigned area. | |
8698 Antiphon in effect said the same thing, which again we express | |
8699 by saying that the circle is the <I>limit</I> of such an inscribed | |
8700 polygon when the number of its sides is indefinitely increased. | |
8701 Antiphon therefore deserves an honourable place in the history | |
8702 of geometry as having originated the idea of <I>exhausting</I> an | |
8703 area by means of inscribed regular polygons with an ever | |
8704 increasing number of sides, an idea upon which, as we said, | |
8705 Eudoxus founded his epoch-making <I>method of exhaustion.</I> | |
8706 The practical value of Antiphon's construction is illustrated | |
8707 by Archimedes's treatise on the <I>Measurement of a Circle</I>, | |
8708 where, by constructing inscribed and circumscribed regular | |
8709 polygons with 96 sides, Archimedes proves that <MATH>3 1/7 > <G>p</G> > 3 10/71</MATH>, | |
8710 the lower limit, <MATH><G>p</G> > 3 10/71</MATH>, being obtained by calculating the | |
8711 <pb n=223><head>ANTIPHON AND BRYSON</head> | |
8712 perimeter of the <I>inscribed</I> polygon of 96 sides, which is | |
8713 constructed in Antiphon's manner from an inscribed equilateral | |
8714 triangle. The same construction starting from a square was | |
8715 likewise the basis of Vieta's expression for 2/<G>p</G>, namely | |
8716 <MATH>2/<G>p</G>=cos<G>p</G>/4.cos<G>p</G>/8.cos<G>p</G>/16 ... | |
8717 =√(1/2).√(1/2)(1+√(1/2)).√(1/2)(1+√(1/2)(1+√(1/2))) ... (<I>ad inf.</I>)</MATH> | |
8718 <p>BRYSON, who came a generation later than Antiphon, being | |
8719 a pupil of Socrates or of Euclid of Megara, was the author | |
8720 of another attempted quadrature which is criticized by | |
8721 Aristotle as ‘sophistic’ and ‘eristic’ on the ground that it | |
8722 was based on principles not special to geometry but applicable | |
8723 equally to other subjects.<note>Arist. <I>An. Post.</I> i. 9, 75 b 40.</note> The commentators give accounts | |
8724 of Bryson's argument which are substantially the same, except | |
8725 that Alexander speaks of <I>squares</I> inscribed and circumscribed | |
8726 to a circle<note>Alexander on <I>Soph. El.</I>, p. 90. 10-21, Wallies, 306 b 24 sq., Brandis.</note>, while Themistius and Philoponus speak of any | |
8727 polygons.<note>Them. on <I>An. Post.</I>, p. 19. 11-20, Wallies, 211 b 19, Brandis; Philop. on <I>An. Post.</I>, p. 111. 20-114. 17 W., 211 b 30, Brandis.</note> According to Alexander, Bryson inscribed a square | |
8728 in a circle and circumscribed another about it, while he also | |
8729 took a square intermediate between them (Alexander does not | |
8730 say how constructed); then he argued that, as the intermediate | |
8731 square is less than the outer and greater than the inner, while | |
8732 the circle is also less than the outer square and greater than | |
8733 the inner, and as <I>things which are greater and less than the | |
8734 same things respectively are equal</I>, it follows that the circle is | |
8735 equal to the intermediate square: upon which Alexander | |
8736 remarks that not only is the thing assumed applicable to | |
8737 other things besides geometrical magnitudes, e.g. to numbers, | |
8738 times, depths of colour, degrees of heat or cold, &c., but it | |
8739 is also false because (for instance) 8 and 9 are both less than | |
8740 10 and greater than 7 and yet they are not equal. As regards | |
8741 the intermediate square (or polygon), some have assumed that | |
8742 it was the arithmetic mean between the inscribed and circum- | |
8743 scribed figures, and others that it was the geometric mean. | |
8744 Both assumptions seem to be due to misunderstanding<note>Psellus (11th cent. A.D.) says, ‘there are different opinions as to the | |
8745 proper method of finding the area of a circle, but that which has found | |
8746 the most favour is to take the geometric mean between the inscribed and | |
8747 circumscribed squares’. I am not aware that he quotes Bryson as the | |
8748 authority for this method, and it gives the inaccurate value <MATH><G>p</G>=√8</MATH> or | |
8749 2.8284272 .... Isaac Argyrus (14th cent.) adds to his account of Bryson | |
8750 the following sentence: ‘For the circumscribed square <I>seems</I> to exceed | |
8751 the circle by the same amount as the inscribed square is exceeded by the | |
8752 circle.’</note>; for | |
8753 <pb n=224><head>THE SQUARING OF THE CIRCLE</head> | |
8754 the ancient commentators do not attribute to Bryson any such | |
8755 statement, and indeed, to judge by their discussions of different | |
8756 interpretations, it would seem that tradition was by no means | |
8757 clear as to what Bryson actually did say. But it seems | |
8758 important to note that Themistius states (1) that Bryson | |
8759 declared the circle to be greater than <I>all</I> inscribed, and less | |
8760 than <I>all</I> circumscribed, polygons, while he also says (2) that | |
8761 the assumed axiom is <I>true</I>, though not peculiar to geometry. | |
8762 This suggests a possible explanation of what otherwise seems | |
8763 to be an absurd argument. Bryson may have multiplied the | |
8764 number of the sides of both the inscribed and circumscribed | |
8765 regular polygons as Antiphon did with inscribed polygons; | |
8766 he may then have argued that, if we continue this process | |
8767 long enough, we shall have an inscribed and a circumscribed | |
8768 polygon differing so little in area that, if we can describe | |
8769 a polygon intermediate between them in area, the circle, which | |
8770 is also intermediate in area between the inscribed and circum- | |
8771 scribed polygons, must be equal to the intermediate polygon.<note>It is true that, according to Philoponus, Proclus had before him an | |
8772 explanation of this kind, but rejected it on the ground that it would | |
8773 mean that the circle must actually <I>be</I> the intermediate polygon and not | |
8774 only be equal to it, in which case Bryson's contention would be tanta- | |
8775 mount to Antiphon's, whereas according to Aristotle it was based on | |
8776 a quite different principle. But it is sufficient that the circle should | |
8777 be taken to be <I>equal</I> to any polygon that can be drawn intermediate | |
8778 between the two ultimate polygons, and this gets over Proclus's difficulty.</note> | |
8779 If this is the right explanation, Bryson's name by no means | |
8780 deserves to be banished from histories of Greek mathematics; | |
8781 on the contrary, in so far as he suggested the necessity of | |
8782 considering circumscribed as well as inscribed polygons, he | |
8783 went a step further than Antiphon; and the importance of | |
8784 the idea is attested by the fact that, in the regular method | |
8785 of exhaustion as practised by Archimedes, use is made of both | |
8786 inscribed and circumscribed figures, and this <I>compression</I>, as it | |
8787 were, of a circumscribed and an inscribed figure into one so | |
8788 that they ultimately coincide with one another, and with the | |
8789 <pb n=225><head>THE SQUARING OF THE CIRCLE</head> | |
8790 curvilinear figure to be measured, is particularly characteristic | |
8791 of Archimedes. | |
8792 <p>We come now to the real rectifications or quadratures of | |
8793 circles effected by means of higher curves, the construction | |
8794 of which is more ‘mechanical’ than that of the circle. Some | |
8795 of these curves were applied to solve more than one of the | |
8796 three classical problems, and it is not always easy to determine | |
8797 for which purpose they were originally destined by their | |
8798 inventors, because the accounts of the different authorities | |
8799 do not quite agree. Iamblichus, speaking of the quadrature | |
8800 of the circle, said that | |
8801 <p>‘Archimedes effected it by means of the spiral-shaped curve, | |
8802 Nicomedes by means of the curve known by the special name | |
8803 <I>quadratrix</I> (<G>tetragwni/zousa</G>), Apollonius by means of a certain | |
8804 curve which he himself calls “sister of the cochloid” but | |
8805 which is the same as Nicomedes's curve, and finally Carpus | |
8806 by means of a certain curve which he simply calls (the curve | |
8807 arising) “from a double motion”.’<note>Iambl. ap. Simpl. <I>in Categ.</I>, p. 192. 19-24 K., 64 b 13-18 Br.</note> | |
8808 <p>Pappus says that | |
8809 <p>‘for the squaring of the circle Dinostratus, Nicomedes and | |
8810 certain other and later geometers used a certain curve which | |
8811 took its name from its property; for those geometers called it | |
8812 <I>quadratrix.</I>’<note>Pappus, iv, pp. 250. 33-252. 3.</note> | |
8813 <p>Lastly, Proclus, speaking of the trisection of any angle, | |
8814 says that | |
8815 <p>‘Nicomedes trisected any rectilineal angle by means of the | |
8816 conchoidal curves, the construction, order and properties of | |
8817 which he handed down, being himself the discoverer of their | |
8818 peculiar character. Others have done the same thing by | |
8819 means of the <I>quadratrices</I> of Hippias and Nicomedes.... | |
8820 Others again, starting from the spirals of Archimedes, divided | |
8821 any given rectilineal angle in any given ratio.’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 272. 1-12.</note> | |
8822 <p>All these passages refer to the <I>quadratrix</I> invented by | |
8823 Hippias of Elis. The first two seem to imply that it was not | |
8824 used by Hippias himself for squaring the circle, but that it | |
8825 was Dinostratus (a brother of Menaechmus) and other later | |
8826 geometers who first applied it to that purpose; Iamblichus | |
8827 and Pappus do not even mention the name of Hippias. We | |
8828 might conclude that Hippias originally intended his curve to | |
8829 <pb n=226><head>THE SQUARING OF THE CIRCLE</head> | |
8830 be used for trisecting an angle. But this becomes more doubt- | |
8831 ful when the passages of Proclus are considered. Pappus's | |
8832 authority seems to be Sporus, who was only slightly older | |
8833 than Pappus himself (towards the end of the third century A.D.), | |
8834 and who was the author of a compilation called <G>*khri/a</G> con- | |
8835 taining, among other things, mathematical extracts on the | |
8836 quadrature of the circle and the duplication of the cube. | |
8837 Proclus's authority, on the other hand, is doubtless Geminus, | |
8838 who was much earlier (first century B.C.) Now not only | |
8839 does the above passage of Proclus make it possible that the | |
8840 name <I>quadratrix</I> may have been used by Hippias himself, | |
8841 but in another place Proclus (i.e. Geminus) says that different | |
8842 mathematicians have explained the properties of particular | |
8843 kinds of curves: | |
8844 <p>‘thus Apollonius shows in the case of each of the conic curves | |
8845 what is its property, and similarly Nicomedes with the | |
8846 conchoids, <I>Hippias with the quadratrices</I>, and Perseus with | |
8847 the spiric curves.’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 356. 6-12.</note> | |
8848 <p>This suggests that Geminus had before him a regular treatise | |
8849 by Hippias on the properties of the <I>quadratrix</I> (which may | |
8850 have disappeared by the time of Sporus), and that Nicomedes | |
8851 did not write any such general work on that curve; and, | |
8852 if this is so, it seems not impossible that Hippias himself | |
8853 discovered that it would serve to rectify, and therefore to | |
8854 square, the circle. | |
8855 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>The Quadratrix of Hippias.</I></C> | |
8856 <p>The method of constructing the curve is described by | |
8857 Pappus.<note>Pappus, iv, pp. 252 sq.</note> Suppose that <I>ABCD</I> is | |
8858 a square, and <I>BED</I> a quadrant of a | |
8859 circle with centre <I>A.</I> | |
8860 <FIG> | |
8861 <p>Suppose (1) that a radius of the | |
8862 circle moves uniformly about <I>A</I> from | |
8863 the position <I>AB</I> to the position <I>AD</I>, | |
8864 and (2) that <I>in the same time</I> the | |
8865 line <I>BC</I> moves uniformly, always | |
8866 parallel to itself and with its ex- | |
8867 tremity <I>B</I> moving along <I>BA</I>, from the position <I>BC</I> to the | |
8868 position <I>AD.</I> | |
8869 <pb n=227><head>THE QUADRATRIX OF HIPPIAS</head> | |
8870 <p>Then, in their ultimate positions, the moving straight line | |
8871 and the moving radius will both coincide with <I>AD</I>; and at | |
8872 any previous instant during the motion the moving line and | |
8873 the moving radius will by their intersection determine a point, | |
8874 as <I>F</I> or <I>L.</I> | |
8875 <p>The locus of these points is the <I>quadratrix.</I> | |
8876 <p>The property of the curve is that | |
8877 <MATH>∠<I>BAD</I>:∠<I>EAD</I>=(arc <I>BED</I>):(arc <I>ED</I>)=<I>AB</I>:<I>FH.</I></MATH> | |
8878 <p>In other words, if <G>f</G> is the angle <I>FAD</I> made by any radius | |
8879 vector <I>AF</I> with <I>AD</I>, <G>r</G> the length of <I>AF</I>, and <G>a</G> the length | |
8880 of the side of the square, | |
8881 <MATH>(<G>r</G> sin<G>f</G>)/<G>a</G>=<G>f</G>/(1/2)<G>p</G></MATH>. | |
8882 <p>Now clearly, when the curve is once constructed, it enables | |
8883 us not only to <I>trisect</I> the angle <I>EAD</I> but also to <I>divide it in | |
8884 any given ratio.</I> | |
8885 <p>For let <I>FH</I> be divided at <I>F</I>′ in the given ratio. Draw <I>F</I>′<I>L</I> | |
8886 parallel to <I>AD</I> to meet the curve in <I>L</I>: join <I>AL</I>, and produce | |
8887 it to meet the circle in <I>N.</I> | |
8888 <p>Then the angles <I>EAN, NAD</I> are in the ratio of <I>FF</I>′ to <I>F</I>′<I>H</I>, | |
8889 as is easily proved. | |
8890 <p>Thus the quadratrix lends itself quite readily to the division | |
8891 of any angle in a given ratio. | |
8892 <p>The application of the <I>quadratrix</I> to the rectification of the | |
8893 circle is a more difficult matter, because it requires us to | |
8894 know the position of <I>G</I>, the point where the quadratrix | |
8895 intersects <I>AD.</I> This difficulty was fully appreciated in ancient | |
8896 times, as we shall see. | |
8897 <p>Meantime, assuming that the quadratrix intersects <I>AD</I> | |
8898 in <I>G</I>, we have to prove the proposition which gives the length | |
8899 of the arc of the quadrant <I>BED</I> and therefore of the circum- | |
8900 ference of the circle. This proposition is to the effect that | |
8901 <MATH>(arc of quadrant <I>BED</I>):<I>AB</I>=<I>AB</I>:<I>AG.</I></MATH> | |
8902 <p>This is proved by <I>reductio ad absurdum.</I> | |
8903 <p>If the former ratio is not equal to <I>AB</I>:<I>AG</I>, it must be | |
8904 equal to <I>AB</I>:<I>AK</I>, where <I>AK</I> is either (1) greater or (2) less | |
8905 than <I>AG.</I> | |
8906 <p>(1) Let <I>AK</I> be greater than <I>AG</I>; and with <I>A</I> as centre | |
8907 <pb n=228><head>THE SQUARING OF THE CIRCLE</head> | |
8908 and <I>AK</I> as radius, draw the quadrant <I>KFL</I> cutting the quad- | |
8909 ratrix in <I>F</I> and <I>AB</I> in <I>L.</I> | |
8910 <p>Join <I>AF</I>, and produce it to meet the circumference <I>BED</I> | |
8911 in <I>E</I>; draw <I>FH</I> perpendicular to <I>AD.</I> | |
8912 <FIG> | |
8913 <p>Now, by hypothesis, | |
8914 <MATH>(arc <I>BED</I>):<I>AB</I>=<I>AB</I>:<I>AK</I> | |
8915 =(arc <I>BED</I>):(arc <I>LFK</I>)</MATH>; | |
8916 therefore <MATH><I>AB</I>=(arc <I>LFK</I>)</MATH>. | |
8917 <p>But, by the property of the <I>quadra- | |
8918 trix</I>, | |
8919 <MATH><I>AB</I>:<I>FH</I>=(arc <I>BED</I>):(arc <I>ED</I>) | |
8920 =(arc <I>LFK</I>):(arc <I>FK</I>)</MATH>; | |
8921 and it was proved that <MATH><I>AB</I>=(arc <I>LFK</I>)</MATH>; | |
8922 therefore <MATH><I>FH</I>=(arc <I>FK</I>)</MATH>: | |
8923 which is absurd. Therefore <I>AK</I> is not greater than <I>AG.</I> | |
8924 <p>(2) Let <I>AK</I> be less than <I>AG.</I> | |
8925 <p>With centre <I>A</I> and radius <I>AK</I> draw the quadrant <I>KML.</I> | |
8926 <p>Draw <I>KF</I> at right angles to <I>AD</I> meeting the quadratrix | |
8927 in <I>F</I>; join <I>AF</I>, and let it meet the | |
8928 quadrants in <I>M, E</I> respectively. | |
8929 <FIG> | |
8930 <p>Then, as before, we prove that | |
8931 <MATH><I>AB</I>=(arc <I>LMK</I>)</MATH>. | |
8932 <p>And, by the property of the <I>quad- | |
8933 ratrix</I>, | |
8934 <MATH><I>AB</I>:<I>FK</I>=(arc <I>BED</I>):(arc <I>DE</I>) | |
8935 =(arc <I>LMK</I>):(arc <I>MK</I>)</MATH>. | |
8936 <p>Therefore, since <MATH><I>AB</I>=(arc <I>LMK</I>), | |
8937 <I>FK</I>=(arc <I>KM</I>)</MATH>: | |
8938 which is absurd. Therefore <I>AK</I> is not less than <I>AG.</I> | |
8939 <p>Since then <I>AK</I> is neither less nor greater than <I>AG</I>, it is | |
8940 equal to it, and | |
8941 <MATH>(arc <I>BED</I>):<I>AB</I>=<I>AB</I>:<I>AG.</I></MATH> | |
8942 <p>[The above proof is presumably due to Dinostratus (if not | |
8943 to Hippias himself), and, as Dinostratus was a brother of | |
8944 Menaechmus, a pupil of Eudoxus, and therefore probably | |
8945 <pb n=229><head>THE QUADRATRIX OF HIPPIAS</head> | |
8946 flourished about 350 B.C., that is to say, some time before | |
8947 Euclid, it is worth while to note certain propositions which | |
8948 are assumed as known. These are, in addition to the theorem | |
8949 of Eucl. VI. 33, the following: (1) the circumferences of | |
8950 circles are as their respective radii; (2) any arc of a circle | |
8951 is greater than the chord subtending it; (3) any arc of a | |
8952 circle less than a quadrant is less than the portion of the | |
8953 tangent at one extremity of the arc cut off by the radius | |
8954 passing through the other extremity. (2) and (3) are of | |
8955 course equivalent to the facts that, if <G>a</G> be the circular measure | |
8956 of an angle less than a right angle, sin <MATH><G>a</G> < <G>a</G> < tan <G>a</G></MATH>.] | |
8957 <p>Even now we have only rectified the circle. To square it | |
8958 we have to use the proposition (1) in Archimedes's <I>Measure- | |
8959 ment of a Circle</I>, to the effect that the area of a circle is equal | |
8960 to that of a right-angled triangle in which the perpendicular | |
8961 is equal to the radius, and the base to the circumference, | |
8962 of the circle. This proposition is proved by the method of | |
8963 exhaustion and may have been known to Dinostratus, who | |
8964 was later than Eudoxus, if not to Hippias. | |
8965 <p>The criticisms of Sporus,<note>Pappus, iv, pp. 252. 26-254. 22.</note> in which Pappus concurs, are | |
8966 worth quoting: | |
8967 <p>(1) ‘The very thing for which the construction is thought | |
8968 to serve is actually assumed in the hypothesis. For how is it | |
8969 possible, with two points starting from <I>B</I>, to make one of | |
8970 them move along a straight line to <I>A</I> and the other along | |
8971 a circumference to <I>D</I> in an equal time, unless you first know | |
8972 the ratio of the straight line <I>AB</I> to the circumference <I>BED</I>? | |
8973 In fact this ratio must also be that of the speeds of motion. | |
8974 For, if you employ speeds not definitely adjusted (to this | |
8975 ratio), how can you make the motions end at the same | |
8976 moment, unless this should sometime happen by pure chance? | |
8977 Is not the thing thus shown to be absurd? | |
8978 <p>(2) ‘Again, the extremity of the curve which they employ | |
8979 for squaring the circle, I mean the point in which the curve | |
8980 cuts the straight line <I>AD</I>, is not found at all. For if, in the | |
8981 figure, the straight lines <I>CB, BA</I> are made to end their motion | |
8982 together, they will then coincide with <I>AD</I> itself and will not | |
8983 cut one another any more. In fact they cease to intersect | |
8984 before they coincide with <I>AD</I>, and yet it was the intersection | |
8985 of these lines which was supposed to give the extremity of the | |
8986 <pb n=230><head>THE SQUARING OF THE CIRCLE</head> | |
8987 curve, where it met the straight line <I>AD.</I> Unless indeed any | |
8988 one should assert that the curve is conceived to be produced | |
8989 further, in the same way as we suppose straight lines to be | |
8990 produced, as far as <I>AD.</I> But this does not follow from the | |
8991 assumptions made; the point <I>G</I> can only be found by first | |
8992 assuming (as known) the ratio of the circumference to the | |
8993 straight line.’ | |
8994 <p>The second of these objections is undoubtedly sound. The | |
8995 point <I>G</I> can in fact only be found by applying the method | |
8996 of exhaustion in the orthodox Greek manner; e.g. we may | |
8997 first bisect the angle of the quadrant, then the half towards | |
8998 <I>AD</I>, then the half of that and so on, drawing each time | |
8999 from the points <I>F</I> in which the bisectors cut the quadratrix | |
9000 perpendiculars <I>FH</I> on <I>AD</I> and describing circles with <I>AF</I> | |
9001 as radius cutting <I>AD</I> in <I>K.</I> Then, if we continue this process | |
9002 long enough, <I>HK</I> will get smaller and smaller and, as <I>G</I> lies | |
9003 between <I>H</I> and <I>K</I>, we can approximate to the position of <I>G</I> as | |
9004 nearly as we please. But this process is the equivalent of | |
9005 approximating to <G>p</G>, which is the very object of the whole | |
9006 construction. | |
9007 <p>As regards objection (1) Hultsch has argued that it is not | |
9008 valid because, with our modern facilities for making instru- | |
9009 ments of precision, there is no difficulty in making the two | |
9010 uniform motions take the same time. Thus an accurate clock | |
9011 will show the minute hand describing an exact quadrant in | |
9012 a definite time, and it is quite practicable now to contrive a | |
9013 uniform rectilinear motion taking exactly the same time. | |
9014 I suspect, however, that the rectilinear motion would be the | |
9015 result of converting some one or more circular motions into | |
9016 rectilinear motions; if so, they would involve the use of an | |
9017 approximate value of <G>p</G>, in which case the solution would depend | |
9018 on the assumption of the very thing to be found. I am inclined, | |
9019 therefore, to think that both Sporus's objections are valid. | |
9020 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The Spiral of Archimedes.</I></C> | |
9021 <p>We are assured that Archimedes actually used the spiral | |
9022 for squaring the circle. He does in fact show how to rectify | |
9023 a circle by means of a polar subtangent to the spiral. The | |
9024 spiral is thus generated: suppose that a straight line with | |
9025 one extremity fixed starts from a fixed position (the initial | |
9026 <pb n=231><head>THE SPIRAL OF ARCHIMEDES</head> | |
9027 line) and revolves uniformly about the fixed extremity, while | |
9028 a point also moves uniformly along the moving straight line | |
9029 starting from the fixed extremity (the origin) at the com- | |
9030 mencement of the straight line's motion; the curve described | |
9031 is a spiral. | |
9032 <p>The polar equation of the curve is obviously <MATH><G>r</G>=<G>aq</G></MATH>. | |
9033 <p>Suppose that the tangent at any point <I>P</I> of the spiral is | |
9034 met at <I>T</I> by a straight line drawn from <I>O</I>, the origin or pole, | |
9035 perpendicular to the radius vector <I>OP</I>; then <I>OT</I> is the polar | |
9036 subtangent. | |
9037 <p>Now in the book <I>On Spirals</I> Archimedes proves generally | |
9038 the equivalent of the fact that, if <G>r</G> be the radius vector to | |
9039 the point <I>P</I>, | |
9040 <MATH><I>OT</I>=<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>/<G>a</G></MATH>. | |
9041 <p>If <I>P</I> is on the <I>n</I>th turn of the spiral, the moving straight | |
9042 line will have moved through an angle <MATH>2(<I>n</I>-1)<G>p</G>+<G>q</G></MATH>, say. | |
9043 <p>Hence <MATH><G>r</G>=<G>a</G>{2(<I>n</I>-1)<G>p</G>+<G>q</G>}</MATH>, | |
9044 and <MATH><I>OT</I>=<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>/<G>a</G>=<G>r</G>{2(<I>n</I>-1)<G>p</G>+<G>q</G>}</MATH>. | |
9045 <p>Archimedes's way of expressing this is to say (Prop. 20) | |
9046 that, if <I>p</I> be the circumference of the circle with radius | |
9047 <MATH><I>OP</I>(=<G>r</G>)</MATH>, and if this circle cut the initial line in the point <I>K</I>, | |
9048 <MATH><I>OT</I>=(<I>n</I>-1)<I>p</I>+arc<I>KP</I></MATH> measured ‘forward’ from <I>K</I> to <I>P.</I> | |
9049 <p>If <I>P</I> is the end of the <I>n</I>th turn, this reduces to | |
9050 <MATH><I>OT</I>=<I>n</I> (circumf. of circle with radius <I>OP</I>)</MATH>, | |
9051 and, if <I>P</I> is the end of the first turn in particular, | |
9052 <MATH><I>OT</I>=(circumf. of circle with radius <I>OP</I>). (Prop. 19.)</MATH> | |
9053 <p>The spiral can thus be used for the rectification of any | |
9054 circle. And the quadrature follows directly from <I>Measure- | |
9055 ment of a Circle</I>, Prop. 1. | |
9056 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Solutions by Apollonius and Carpus.</I></C> | |
9057 <p>Iamblichus says that Apollonius himself called the curve by | |
9058 means of which he squared the circle ‘sister of the cochloid’. | |
9059 What this curve was is uncertain. As the passage goes on to | |
9060 say that it was really ‘the same as the (curve) of Nicomedes’, | |
9061 and the quadratrix has just been mentioned as the curve used | |
9062 <pb n=232><head>THE SQUARING OF THE CIRCLE</head> | |
9063 by Nicomedes, some have supposed the ‘sister of the cochloid’ | |
9064 (or conchoid) to be the <I>quadratrix</I>, but this seems highly im- | |
9065 probable. There is, however, another possibility. Apollonius | |
9066 is known to have written a regular treatise on the <I>Cochlias</I>, | |
9067 which was the cylindrical helix.<note>Pappus, viii, p. 1110. 20; Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 105. 5.</note> It is conceivable that he | |
9068 might call the <I>cochlias</I> the ‘sister of the <I>cochloid</I>’ on the | |
9069 ground of the similarity of the names, if not of the curves. | |
9070 And, as a matter of fact, the drawing of a tangent to the | |
9071 helix enables the circular section of the cylinder to be squared. | |
9072 For, if a plane be drawn at right angles to the axis of the | |
9073 cylinder through the initial position of the moving radius | |
9074 which describes the helix, and if we project on this plane | |
9075 the portion of the tangent at any point of the helix intercepted | |
9076 between the point and the plane, the projection is equal to | |
9077 an arc of the circular section of the cylinder subtended by an | |
9078 angle at the centre equal to the angle through which the | |
9079 plane through the axis and the moving radius has turned | |
9080 from its original position. And this squaring by means of | |
9081 what we may call the ‘subtangent’ is sufficiently parallel to | |
9082 the use by Archimedes of the polar subtangent to the spiral | |
9083 for the same purpose to make the hypothesis attractive. | |
9084 <p>Nothing whatever is known of Carpus's curve ‘of double | |
9085 motion’. Tannery thought it was the cycloid; but there is no | |
9086 evidence for this. | |
9087 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>Approximations to the value of</I> <G>p</G>.</C> | |
9088 <p>As we have seen, Archimedes, by inscribing and cir- | |
9089 cumscribing regular polygons of 96 sides, and calculating | |
9090 their perimeters respectively, obtained the approximation | |
9091 <MATH>3 1/7 > <G>p</G> > 3 10/71</MATH> (<I>Measurement of a Circle</I>, Prop. 3). But we | |
9092 now learn<note>Heron, <I>Metrica</I>, i. 26, p. 66. 13-17.</note> that, in a work on <I>Plinthides and Cylinders</I>, he | |
9093 made a nearer approximation still. Unfortunately the figures | |
9094 as they stand in the Greek text are incorrect, the lower limit | |
9095 being given as the ratio of <G>m<SUP>ka</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>awoe</G> to <G>m<SUP>s</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>zuma</G>, or <MATH>211875:67441 | |
9096 (=3.141635)</MATH>, and the higher limit as the ratio of <G>m<SUP>iq</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>zwph</G> to | |
9097 <G>m<SUP>s</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>btna</G> or <MATH>197888:62351 (=3.17377)</MATH>, so that the lower limit | |
9098 <pb n=233><head>APPROXIMATIONS TO THE VALUE OF <I>II</I></head> | |
9099 as given is greater than the true value, and the higher limit is | |
9100 greater than the earlier upper limit 3 1/7. Slight corrections by | |
9101 Tannery (<G>m<SUP>ka</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>awob</G> for <G>m<SUP>ka</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>awoe</G> and <G>m<SUP>iq</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>ewpb</G> for <G>m<SUP>iq</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>zwph</G>) give | |
9102 better figures, namely | |
9103 <MATH>195882/62351 > <G>p</G> > 211872/67441</MATH> | |
9104 or <MATH>3.1416016 > <G>p</G> > 3.1415904 ....</MATH> | |
9105 <p>Another suggestion<note>J. L. Heiben in <I>Nordisk Tidsskrift for Filologi</I>, 3<SUP>e</SUP> Sér. xx. Fasc. 1-2.</note> is to correct <G>m<SUP>s</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>zuma</G> into <G>m<SUP>s</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>zumd</G> and | |
9106 <G>m<SUP>iq</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>zwph</G> into <G>m<SUP>iq</SUP><SUB>/</SUB>ewph</G>, giving | |
9107 <MATH>195888/62351 > <G>p</G> > 211875/67444</MATH> | |
9108 or <MATH>3.141697 ... > <G>p</G> > 3.141495 ....</MATH> | |
9109 <p>If either suggestion represents the true reading, the mean | |
9110 between the two limits gives the same remarkably close | |
9111 approximation 3.141596. | |
9112 <p>Ptolemy<note>Ptolemy, <I>Suntaxis</I>, vi. 7, p. 513. 1-5, Heib.</note> gives a value for the ratio of the circumference | |
9113 of a circle to its diameter expressed thus in sexagesimal | |
9114 fractions, <G>g h l</G>, i.e. <MATH>3+8/60+30/60<SUP>2</SUP></MATH> or 3.1416. He observes | |
9115 that this is almost exactly the mean between the Archimedean | |
9116 limits 3 1/7 and 3 10/71. It is, however, more exact than this mean, | |
9117 and Ptolemy no doubt obtained his value independently. He | |
9118 had the basis of the calculation ready to hand in his Table | |
9119 of Chords. This Table gives the lengths of the chords of | |
9120 a circle subtended by arcs of 1/2°, 1°, 1 1/2°, and so on by half | |
9121 degrees. The chords are expressed in terms of 120th parts | |
9122 of the length of the diameter. If one such part be denoted | |
9123 by 1<SUP><I>p</I></SUP>, the chord subtended by an arc of 1° is given by the | |
9124 Table in terms of this unit and sexagesimal fractions of it | |
9125 thus, 1<SUP><I>p</I></SUP> 2′ 50″. Since an angle of 1° at the centre subtends | |
9126 a side of the regular polygon of 360 sides inscribed in the | |
9127 circle, the perimeter of this polygon is 360 times 1<SUP><I>p</I></SUP> 2′ 50″ | |
9128 or, since <MATH>1<SUP><I>p</I></SUP>=1/120th</MATH> of the diameter, the perimeter of the | |
9129 polygon expressed in terms of the diameter is 3 times 1 2′ 50″, | |
9130 that is 3 8′ 30″, which is Ptolemy's figure for <G>p</G>. | |
9131 <pb n=234><head>THE SQUARING OF THE CIRCLE</head> | |
9132 <p>There is evidence of a still closer calculation than Ptolemy's | |
9133 due to some Greek whose name we do not know. The Indian | |
9134 mathematician Aryabhatta (born A.D. 476) says in his <I>Lessons | |
9135 in Calculation</I>: | |
9136 <p>‘To 100 add 4; multiply the sum by 8; add 62000 more | |
9137 and thus (we have), for a diameter of 2 myriads, the approxi- | |
9138 mate length of the circumference of the circle’; | |
9139 <p>that is, he gives 62832/20000 or 3.1416 as the value of <G>p</G>. But the | |
9140 way in which he expresses it points indubitably to a Greek | |
9141 source, ‘for the Greeks alone of all peoples made the myriad | |
9142 the unit of the second order’ (Rodet). | |
9143 <p>This brings us to the notice at the end of Eutocius's com- | |
9144 mentary on the <I>Measurement of a Circle</I> of Archimedes, which | |
9145 records<note>Archimedes, ed. Heib., vol. iii, pp. 258-9.</note> that other mathematicians made similar approxima- | |
9146 tions, though it does not give their results. | |
9147 <p>‘It is to be observed that Apollonius of Perga solved the | |
9148 same problem in his <G>*w)kuto/kion</G> (“means of quick delivery”), | |
9149 using other numbers and making the approximation closer | |
9150 [than that of Archimedes]. While Apollonius's figures seem | |
9151 to be more accurate, they do not serve the purpose which | |
9152 Archimedes had in view; for, as we said, his object in this | |
9153 book was to find an approximate figure suitable for use in | |
9154 daily life. Hence we cannot regard as appropriate the censure | |
9155 of Sporus of Nicaea, who seems to charge Archimedes with | |
9156 having failed to determine with accuracy (the length of) the | |
9157 straight line which is equal to the circumference of the circle, | |
9158 to judge by the passage in his <I>Keria</I> where Sporus observes | |
9159 that his own teacher, meaning Philon of Gadara, reduced (the | |
9160 matter) to more exact numerical expression than Archimedes | |
9161 did, I mean in his 1/7 and 10/71; in fact people seem, one after the | |
9162 other, to have failed to appreciate Archimedes's object. They | |
9163 have also used multiplications and divisions of myriads, a | |
9164 method not easy to follow for any one who has not gone | |
9165 through a course of Magnus's <I>Logistica.</I>’ | |
9166 <p>It is possible that, as Apollonius used myriads, ‘second | |
9167 myriads’, ‘third myriads’, &c., as orders of integral numbers, | |
9168 he may have worked with the fractions 1/10000, 1/10000<SUP>2</SUP>, &c.; | |
9169 <pb n=235><head>APPROXIMATIONS TO THE VALUE OF <I>II</I></head> | |
9170 in any case Magnus (apparently later than Sporus, and therefore | |
9171 perhaps belonging to the fourth or fifth century A.D.) would | |
9172 seem to have written an exposition of such a method, which, | |
9173 as Eutocius indicates, must have been very much more | |
9174 troublesome than the method of sexagesimal fractions used | |
9175 by Ptolemy. | |
9176 <C>The Trisection of any Angle.</C> | |
9177 <p>This problem presumably arose from attempts to continue | |
9178 the construction of regular polygons after that of the pentagon | |
9179 had been discovered. The trisection of an angle would be | |
9180 necessary in order to construct a regular polygon the sides | |
9181 of which are nine, or any multiple of nine, in number. | |
9182 A regular polygon of seven sides, on the other hand, would | |
9183 no doubt be constructed with the help of the first discovered | |
9184 method of dividing any angle in a given ratio, i.e. by means | |
9185 of the <I>quadratrix.</I> This method covered the case of trisection, | |
9186 but other more practicable ways of effecting this particular | |
9187 construction were in due time evolved. | |
9188 <p>We are told that the ancients attempted, and failed, to | |
9189 solve the problem by ‘plane’ methods, i.e. by means of the | |
9190 straight line and circle; they failed because the problem is | |
9191 not ‘plane’ but ‘solid’. Moreover, they were not yet familiar | |
9192 with conic sections, and so were at a loss; afterwards, | |
9193 however, they succeeded in trisecting an angle by means of | |
9194 conic sections, a method to which they were led by the | |
9195 reduction of the problem to another, of the kind known as | |
9196 <G>neu/seis</G> (<I>inclinationes</I>, or <I>vergings</I>).<note>Pappus, iv, p. 272. 7-14.</note> | |
9197 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Reduction to a certain <G>neu=sis</G>, solved by conics.</I></C> | |
9198 <p>The reduction is arrived at by the following analysis. It is | |
9199 only necessary to deal with the case where the given angle to | |
9200 be trisected is acute, since a right angle can be trisected | |
9201 by drawing an equilateral triangle. | |
9202 <p>Let <I>ABC</I> be the given angle, and let <I>AC</I> be drawn perpen- | |
9203 dicular to <I>BC.</I> Complete the parallelogram <I>ACBF</I>, and | |
9204 produce the side <I>FA</I> to <I>E.</I> | |
9205 <pb n=236><head>THE TRISECTION OF ANY ANGLE</head> | |
9206 <p><I>Suppose E to be such a point that, if BE be joined meeting | |
9207 AC in D, the intercept DE between AC and AE is equal | |
9208 to 2 AB.</I> | |
9209 <FIG> | |
9210 <p>Bisect <I>DE</I> at <I>G</I>, and join <I>AG.</I> | |
9211 <p>Then <MATH><I>DG</I>=<I>GE</I>=<I>AG</I>=<I>AB</I></MATH>. | |
9212 <p>Therefore <MATH>∠<I>ABG</I>=∠<I>AGB</I>=2∠<I>AEG</I> | |
9213 =2∠<I>DBC</I></MATH>, since <I>FE, BC</I> are parallel. | |
9214 <p>Hence <MATH>∠<I>DBC</I>=1/3∠<I>ABC</I></MATH>, | |
9215 and the angle <I>ABC</I> is trisected by <I>BE.</I> | |
9216 <p>Thus the problem is reduced to <I>drawing BE from B to cut | |
9217 AC and AE in such a way that the intercept</I> <MATH><I>DE</I>=2<I>AB</I></MATH>. | |
9218 <p>In the phraseology of the problems called <G>neu/seis</G> the | |
9219 problem is to insert a straight line <I>ED</I> of given length | |
9220 2<I>AB</I> between <I>AE</I> and <I>AC</I> in such a way that <I>ED verges</I> | |
9221 towards <I>B.</I> | |
9222 <p>Pappus shows how to solve this problem in a more general | |
9223 form. Given a parallelogram <I>ABCD</I> (which need not be | |
9224 rectangular, as Pappus makes it), to draw <I>AEF</I> to meet <I>CD</I> | |
9225 and <I>BC</I> produced in points <I>E</I> and <I>F</I> such that <I>EF</I> has a given | |
9226 length. | |
9227 <p>Suppose the problem solved, <I>EF</I> being of the given length. | |
9228 <FIG> | |
9229 <p>Complete the parallelogram | |
9230 <I>EDGF.</I> | |
9231 <p>Then, <I>EF</I> being given in length, | |
9232 <I>DG</I> is given in length. | |
9233 <p>Therefore <I>G</I> lies on a circle with | |
9234 centre <I>D</I> and radius equal to the | |
9235 given length. | |
9236 <p>Again, by the help of Eucl. I. 43 relating to the complements | |
9237 <pb n=237><head>REDUCTION TO A <G>*n*e*g*s*i*s</G></head> | |
9238 of the parallelograms about the diagonal of the complete | |
9239 parallelogram, we see that | |
9240 <MATH><I>BC.CD</I>=<I>BF.ED</I> | |
9241 =<I>BF.FG.</I></MATH> | |
9242 <p>Consequently <I>G</I> lies on a hyperbola with <I>BF, BA</I> as | |
9243 asymptotes and passing through <I>D.</I> | |
9244 <p>Thus, in order to effect the construction, we have only to | |
9245 draw this hyperbola as well as the circle with centre <I>D</I> and | |
9246 radius equal to the given length. Their intersection gives the | |
9247 point <I>G</I>, and <I>E, F</I> are then determined by drawing <I>GF</I> parallel | |
9248 to <I>DC</I> to meet <I>BC</I> produced in <I>F</I> and joining <I>AF.</I> | |
9249 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The <G>neu=sis</G> equivalent to a cubic equation.</I></C> | |
9250 <p>It is easily seen that the solution of the <G>neu=sis</G> is equivalent | |
9251 to the solution of a cubic equation. For in the first figure on | |
9252 p. 236, if <I>FA</I> be the axis of <I>x, FB</I> the axis of <I>y</I>, <MATH><I>FA</I>=<I>a</I>, | |
9253 <I>FB</I>=<I>b</I></MATH>, the solution of the problem by means of conics as | |
9254 Pappus gives it is the equivalent of finding a certain point | |
9255 as the intersection of the conics | |
9256 <MATH><I>xy</I>=<I>ab</I>, | |
9257 (<I>x</I>-<I>a</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>y</I>-<I>b</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>=4(<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>. | |
9258 <p>The second equation gives | |
9259 <MATH>(<I>x</I>+<I>a</I>)(<I>x</I>-3<I>a</I>)=(<I>y</I>+<I>b</I>)(3<I>b</I>-<I>y</I>)</MATH>. | |
9260 <p>From the first equation it is easily seen that | |
9261 <MATH>(<I>x</I>+<I>a</I>):(<I>y</I>+<I>b</I>)=<I>a</I>:<I>y</I></MATH>, | |
9262 and that <MATH>(<I>x</I>-3<I>a</I>)<I>y</I>=<I>a</I>(<I>b</I>-3<I>y</I>)</MATH>; | |
9263 therefore, eliminating <I>x</I>, we have | |
9264 <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>(<I>b</I>-3<I>y</I>)=<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>(3<I>b</I>-<I>y</I>)</MATH>, | |
9265 or <MATH><I>y</I><SUP>3</SUP>-3<I>by</I><SUP>2</SUP>-3<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>y</I>+<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b</I>=0</MATH>. | |
9266 <p>Now suppose that <MATH>∠<I>ABC</I>=<G>q</G></MATH>, so that tan <MATH><G>q</G>=<I>b/a</I></MATH>; | |
9267 and suppose that <MATH><I>t</I>=tan <I>DBC</I></MATH>, | |
9268 so that <MATH><I>y</I>=<I>at.</I></MATH> | |
9269 <p>We have then | |
9270 <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP><I>t</I><SUP>3</SUP>-3<I>ba</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>t</I><SUP>2</SUP>-3<I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP><I>t</I>+<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b</I>=0</MATH>, | |
9271 <pb n=238><head>THE TRISECTION OF ANY ANGLE</head> | |
9272 or <MATH><I>at</I><SUP>3</SUP>-3<I>bt</I><SUP>2</SUP>-3<I>at</I>+<I>b</I>=0</MATH>, | |
9273 whence <MATH><I>b</I>(1-3<I>t</I><SUP>2</SUP>)=<I>a</I>(3<I>t</I>-<I>t</I><SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>, | |
9274 or <MATH>tan<G>q</G>=<I>b/a</I>=(3<I>t</I>-<I>t</I><SUP>3</SUP>)/(1-3<I>t</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>, | |
9275 so that, by the well-known trigonometrical formula, | |
9276 <MATH><I>t</I>=tan1/3<G>q</G></MATH>; | |
9277 that is, <I>BD</I> trisects the angle <I>ABC.</I> | |
9278 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>The Conchoids of Nicomedes.</I></C> | |
9279 <p>Nicomedes invented a curve for the specific purpose of | |
9280 solving such <G>neu/seis</G> as the above. His date can be fixed with | |
9281 sufficient accuracy by the facts (1) that he seems to have | |
9282 criticized unfavourably Eratosthenes's solution of the problem | |
9283 of the two mean proportionals or the duplication of the cube, | |
9284 and (2) that Apollonius called a certain curve the ‘sister of | |
9285 the cochloid’, evidently out of compliment to Nicomedes. | |
9286 Nicomedes must therefore have been about intermediate | |
9287 between Eratosthenes (a little younger than Archimedes, and | |
9288 therefore born about 280 B.C.) and Apollonius (born probably | |
9289 about 264 B.C.). | |
9290 <p>The curve is called by Pappus the <I>cochloid</I> (<G>koxloeidh\s | |
9291 grammh/</G>), and this was evidently the original name for it; | |
9292 later, e.g. by Proclus, it was called the <I>conchoid</I> (<G>kogxoeidh\s | |
9293 grammh/</G>). There were varieties of the cochloidal curves; | |
9294 Pappus speaks of the ‘first’, ‘second’, ‘third’ and ‘fourth’, | |
9295 observing that the ‘first’ was used for trisecting an angle and | |
9296 duplicating the cube, while the others were useful for other | |
9297 investigations.<note>Pappus, iv, p. 244. 18-20.</note> It is the ‘first’ which concerns us here. | |
9298 Nicomedes constructed it by means of a mechanical device | |
9299 which may be described thus.<note><I>Ib.</I>, pp. 242-4.</note> <I>AB</I> is a ruler with a slot | |
9300 in it parallel to its length, <I>FE</I> a second ruler fixed at right | |
9301 angles to the first, with a peg <I>C</I> fixed in it. A third ruler | |
9302 <I>PC</I> pointed at <I>P</I> has a slot in it parallel to its length which | |
9303 fits the peg <I>C. D</I> is a fixed peg on <I>PC</I> in a straight line | |
9304 with the slot, and <I>D</I> can move freely along the slot in <I>AB.</I> | |
9305 If then the ruler <I>PC</I> moves so that the peg <I>D</I> describes the | |
9306 <pb n=239><head>THE CONCHOIDS OF NICOMEDES</head> | |
9307 length of the slot in <I>AB</I> on each side of <I>F</I>, the extremity <I>P</I> of | |
9308 the ruler describes the curve which is called a conchoid or | |
9309 cochloid. Nicomedes called the straight line <I>AB</I> the <I>ruler</I> | |
9310 (<G>kanw/n</G>), the fixed point <I>C</I> the <I>pole</I> (<G>po/los</G>), and the constant | |
9311 length <I>PD</I> the <I>distance</I> (<G>dia/sthma</G>). | |
9312 <FIG> | |
9313 <p>The fundamental property of the curve, which in polar | |
9314 coordinates would now be denoted by the equation | |
9315 <MATH><I>r</I>=<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>sec<G>q</G></MATH>, | |
9316 is that, if any radius vector be drawn from <I>C</I> to the curve, as | |
9317 <I>CP</I>, the length intercepted on the radius vector between the | |
9318 curve and the straight line <I>AB</I> is constant. Thus any <G>neu=sis</G> | |
9319 in which one of the two given lines (between which the | |
9320 straight line of given length is to be placed) is a straight line | |
9321 can be solved by means of the intersection of the other line | |
9322 with a certain conchoid having as its pole the fixed point | |
9323 to which the inserted straight line must <I>verge</I> (<G>neu/ein</G>). Pappus | |
9324 tells us that in practice the conchoid was not always actually | |
9325 drawn but that ‘some’, for greater convenience, moved a ruler | |
9326 about the fixed point until by trial the intercept was found to | |
9327 be equal to the given length.<note>Pappus, iv, p. 246. 15.</note> | |
9328 <p>In the figure above (p. 236) showing the reduction of the | |
9329 trisection of an angle to a <G>neu=sis</G> the conchoid to be used | |
9330 would have <I>B</I> for its <I>pole, AC</I> for the ‘<I>ruler</I>’ or <I>base</I>, a length | |
9331 equal to 2<I>AB</I> for its <I>distance</I>; and <I>E</I> would be found as the | |
9332 intersection of the conchoid with <I>FA</I> produced. | |
9333 <p>Proclus says that Nicomedes gave the construction, the | |
9334 order, and the properties of the conchoidal lines<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 272. 3-7.</note>; but nothing | |
9335 <pb n=240><head>THE TRISECTION OF ANY ANGLE</head> | |
9336 of his treatise has come down to us except the construction | |
9337 of the ‘first’ conchoid, its fundamental property, and the fact | |
9338 that the curve has the <I>ruler</I> or <I>base</I> as an asymptote in | |
9339 each direction. The distinction, however, drawn by Pappus | |
9340 between the ‘first’, ‘second’, ‘third’ and ‘fourth’ conchoids | |
9341 may well have been taken from the original treatise, directly | |
9342 or indirectly. We are not told the nature of the conchoids | |
9343 other than the ‘first’, but it is probable that they were three | |
9344 other curves produced by varying the conditions in the figure. | |
9345 Let <I>a</I> be the distance or fixed intercept between the curve and | |
9346 the base, <I>b</I> the distance of the pole from the base. Then | |
9347 clearly, if along each radius vector drawn through the pole | |
9348 we measure <I>a</I> backwards from the base towards the pole, | |
9349 we get a conchoidal figure on the side of the base towards | |
9350 the pole. This curve takes three forms according as <I>a</I> is | |
9351 greater than, equal to, or less than <I>b.</I> Each of them has | |
9352 the base for asymptote, but in the first of the three cases | |
9353 the curve has a loop as shown in the figure, in the second | |
9354 case it has a cusp at the pole, in the third it has no double | |
9355 point. The most probable hypothesis seems to be that the | |
9356 other three cochloidal curves mentioned by Pappus are these | |
9357 three varieties. | |
9358 <FIG> | |
9359 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>Another reduction to a</I> <G>neu=sis</G> (<I>Archimedes</I>).</C> | |
9360 <p>A proposition leading to the reduction of the trisection | |
9361 of an angle to another <G>neu=sis</G> is included in the collection of | |
9362 Lemmas (<I>Liber Assumptorum</I>) which has come to us under | |
9363 <pb n=241><head>ARCHIMEDES'S SOLUTION (BY NE<G>*g*s*i*s</G>)</head> | |
9364 the name of Archimedes through the Arabic. Though the | |
9365 Lemmas cannot have been written by Archimedes in their | |
9366 present form, because his name is quoted in them more than | |
9367 once, it is probable that some of them are of Archimedean | |
9368 origin, and especially is this the case with Prop. 8, since the | |
9369 <G>neu=sis</G> suggested by it is of very much the same kind as those | |
9370 the solution of which is assumed in the treatise <I>On Spirals</I>, | |
9371 Props. 5-8. The proposition is as follows. | |
9372 <p>If <I>AB</I> be any chord of a circle with centre <I>O</I>, and <I>AB</I> be | |
9373 produced to <I>C</I> so that <I>BC</I> is | |
9374 equal to the radius, and if <I>CO</I> | |
9375 meet the circle in <I>D, E</I>, then the | |
9376 arc <I>AE</I> will be equal to three | |
9377 times the arc <I>BD.</I> | |
9378 <FIG> | |
9379 <p>Draw the chord <I>EF</I> parallel | |
9380 to <I>AB</I>, and join <I>OB, OF.</I> | |
9381 <p>Since <MATH><I>BO</I>=<I>BC</I></MATH>, | |
9382 <MATH>∠<I>BOC</I>=∠<I>BCO</I></MATH>. | |
9383 <p>Now <MATH>∠<I>COF</I>=2∠<I>OEF</I>, | |
9384 =2∠<I>BCO</I></MATH>, by parallels, | |
9385 <MATH>=2∠<I>BOC</I></MATH>. | |
9386 <p>Therefore <MATH>∠<I>BOF</I>=3∠<I>BOD</I></MATH>, | |
9387 and <MATH>(arc <I>BF</I>)=(arc <I>AE</I>)=3(arc <I>BD</I>)</MATH>. | |
9388 <p>By means of this proposition we can reduce the trisection of | |
9389 the arc <I>AE</I> to a <G>neu=sis</G>. For, in order to find an arc which is | |
9390 one-third of the arc <I>AE</I>, we have only to draw through <I>A</I> | |
9391 a straight line <I>ABC</I> meeting the circle again in <I>B</I> and <I>EO</I> | |
9392 produced in <I>C</I>, and such that <I>BC</I> is equal to the radius of the | |
9393 circle. | |
9394 <C>(<G>e</G>) <I>Direct solutions by means of conics.</I></C> | |
9395 <p>Pappus gives two solutions of the trisection problem in | |
9396 which conics are applied directly without any preliminary | |
9397 reduction of the problem to a <G>neu=sis</G>.<note>Pappus, iv, pp. 282-4.</note> | |
9398 <p>1. The analysis leading to the first method is as follows. | |
9399 <p>Let <I>AC</I> be a straight line, and <I>B</I> a point without it such | |
9400 that, if <I>BA, BC</I> be joined, the angle <I>BCA</I> is double of the | |
9401 angle <I>BAC.</I> | |
9402 <pb n=242><head>THE TRISECTION OF ANY ANGLE</head> | |
9403 <p>Draw <I>BD</I> perpendicular to <I>AC</I>, and cut off <I>DE</I> along <I>DA</I> | |
9404 equal to <I>DC.</I> Join <I>BE.</I> | |
9405 <FIG> | |
9406 <p>Then, since <MATH><I>BE</I>=<I>BC</I></MATH>, | |
9407 <MATH>∠<I>BEC</I>=<I>BCE</I></MATH>. | |
9408 <p>But <MATH>∠<I>BEC</I>=∠<I>BAE</I>+∠<I>EBA</I></MATH>, | |
9409 and, by hypothesis, | |
9410 <MATH>∠<I>BCA</I>=2∠<I>BAE</I></MATH>. | |
9411 <p>Therefore <MATH>∠<I>BAE</I>+∠<I>EBA</I>=2∠<I>BAE</I></MATH>; | |
9412 therefore <MATH>∠<I>BAE</I>=∠<I>ABE</I></MATH>, | |
9413 or <MATH><I>AE</I>=<I>BE</I></MATH>. | |
9414 <p>Divide <I>AC</I> at <I>G</I> so that <MATH><I>AG</I>=2<I>GC</I></MATH>, or <MATH><I>CG</I>=1/3<I>AC</I></MATH>. | |
9415 <p>Also let <I>FE</I> be made equal to <I>ED</I>, so that <MATH><I>CD</I>=1/3<I>CF</I></MATH>. | |
9416 <p>It follows that <MATH><I>GD</I>=1/3(<I>AC</I>-<I>CF</I>)=1/3<I>AF</I></MATH>. | |
9417 <p>Now <MATH><I>BD</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BE</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>ED</I><SUP>2</SUP> | |
9418 =<I>BE</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
9419 <p>Also <MATH><I>DA.AF</I>=<I>AE</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> (Eucl. II. 6) | |
9420 <MATH>=<I>BE</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
9421 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>BD</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>DA.AF</I> | |
9422 =3<I>AD.DG</I></MATH>, from above, | |
9423 so that <MATH><I>BD</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>AD.DG</I>=3:1 | |
9424 =3<I>AG</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>AG</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
9425 <p>Hence <I>D</I> lies on a hyperbola with <I>AG</I> as transverse axis | |
9426 and with conjugate axis equal to √3.<I>AG</I>. | |
9427 <FIG> | |
9428 <p>Now suppose we are required | |
9429 to trisect an arc <I>AB</I> of a circle | |
9430 with centre <I>O.</I> | |
9431 <p>Draw the chord <I>AB</I>, divide it | |
9432 at <I>C</I> so that <MATH><I>AC</I>=2<I>CB</I></MATH>, and | |
9433 construct the hyperbola which | |
9434 has <I>AC</I> for transverse axis and | |
9435 a straight line equal to √3.<I>AC</I> for conjugate axis. | |
9436 <p>Let the hyperbola meet the circular arc in <I>P.</I> Join <I>PA, | |
9437 PO, PB.</I> | |
9438 <pb n=243><head>SOLUTIONS BY MEANS OF CONICS</head> | |
9439 <p>Then, by the above proposition, | |
9440 <MATH>∠<I>PBA</I>=2∠<I>PAB</I></MATH>. | |
9441 <p>Therefore their doubles are equal, | |
9442 or <MATH>∠<I>POA</I>=2∠<I>POB</I></MATH>, | |
9443 and <I>OP</I> accordingly trisects the arc <I>APB</I> and the angle <I>AOB.</I> | |
9444 <p>2. ‘Some’, says Pappus, set out another solution not in- | |
9445 volving recourse to a <G>neu=sis</G>, as follows. | |
9446 <p>Let <I>RPS</I> be an arc of a circle which it is required to | |
9447 trisect. | |
9448 <p>Suppose it done, and let the arc <I>SP</I> be one-third of the | |
9449 arc <I>SPR.</I> | |
9450 <p>Join <I>RP, SP.</I> | |
9451 <p>Then the angle <I>RSP</I> is equal | |
9452 to twice the angle <I>SRP.</I> | |
9453 <FIG> | |
9454 <p>Let <I>SE</I> bisect the angle <I>RSP</I>, | |
9455 meeting <I>RP</I> in <I>E</I>, and draw <I>EX, PN</I> perpendicular to <I>RS.</I> | |
9456 <p>Then <MATH>∠<I>ERS</I>=∠<I>ESR</I></MATH>, so that <MATH><I>RE</I>=<I>ES</I></MATH>. | |
9457 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>RX</I>=<I>XS</I></MATH>, and <I>X</I> is given. | |
9458 <p>Again <MATH><I>RS</I>:<I>SP</I>=<I>RE</I>:<I>EP</I>=<I>RX</I>:<I>XN</I></MATH>; | |
9459 therefore <MATH><I>RS</I>:<I>RX</I>=<I>SP</I>:<I>NX</I></MATH>. | |
9460 <p>But <MATH><I>RS</I>=2<I>RX</I></MATH>; | |
9461 therefore <MATH><I>SP</I>=2<I>NX</I></MATH>. | |
9462 <p>It follows that <I>P</I> lies on a hyperbola with <I>S</I> as focus and <I>XE</I> | |
9463 as directrix, and with eccentricity 2. | |
9464 <p>Hence, in order to trisect the arc, we have only to bisect <I>RS</I> | |
9465 at <I>X</I>, draw <I>XE</I> at right angles to <I>RS</I>, and then draw a hyper- | |
9466 bola with <I>S</I> as focus, <I>XE</I> as directrix, and 2 as the eccentricity. | |
9467 The hyperbola is the same as that used in the first solution. | |
9468 <p>The passage of Pappus from which this solution is taken is | |
9469 remarkable as being one of three passages in Greek mathe- | |
9470 matical works still extant (two being in Pappus and one in | |
9471 a fragment of Anthemius on burning mirrors) which refer to | |
9472 the focus-and-directrix property of conics. The second passage | |
9473 in Pappus comes under the heading of Lemmas to the <I>Surface- | |
9474 Loci</I> of Euclid.<note>Pappus, vii, pp. 1004-1114.</note> Pappus there gives a complete proof of the | |
9475 <pb n=244><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
9476 theorem that, <I>if the distance of a point from a fixed point is | |
9477 in a given ratio to its distance from <B>a</B> fixed line, the locus of | |
9478 the point is a conic section which is an ellipse, a parabola, | |
9479 or a hyperbola according as the given ratio is less than, equal | |
9480 to, or greater than, unity.</I> The importance of these passages | |
9481 lies in the fact that the Lemma was required for the | |
9482 understanding of Euclid's treatise. We can hardly avoid | |
9483 the conclusion that the property was used by Euclid in his | |
9484 <I>Surface-Loci</I>, but was assumed as well known. It was, there- | |
9485 fore, probably taken from some treatise current in Euclid's | |
9486 time, perhaps from Aristaeus's work on <I>Solid Loci.</I> | |
9487 <C><B>The Duplication of the Cube, or the problem | |
9488 of the two mean proportionals.</B></C> | |
9489 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>History of the problem.</I></C> | |
9490 <p>In his commentary on Archimedes, <I>On the Sphere and | |
9491 Cylinder</I>, II. 1, Eutocius has preserved for us a precious | |
9492 collection of solutions of this famous problem.<note>Archimedes, ed. Heib., vol. iii, pp. 54. 26-106. 24.</note> One of the | |
9493 solutions is that of Eratosthenes, a younger contemporary of | |
9494 Archimedes, and it is introduced by what purports to be | |
9495 a letter from Eratosthenes to Ptolemy. This was Ptolemy | |
9496 Euergetes, who at the beginning of his reign (245 B.C.) per- | |
9497 suaded Eratosthenes to come from Athens to Alexandria to be | |
9498 tutor to his son (Philopator). The supposed letter gives the | |
9499 tradition regarding the origin of the problem and the history of | |
9500 its solution up to the time of Eratosthenes. Then, after some | |
9501 remarks on its usefulness for practical purposes, the author | |
9502 describes the construction by which Eratosthenes himself solved | |
9503 it, giving the proof of it at some length and adding directions | |
9504 for making the instrument by which the construction could | |
9505 be effected in practice. Next he says that the mechanical | |
9506 contrivance represented by Eratosthenes was, ‘in the votive | |
9507 monument’, actually of bronze, and was fastened on with lead | |
9508 close under the <G>stefa/nh</G> of the pillar. There was, further, | |
9509 on the pillar the proof in a condensed form, with one figure, | |
9510 and, at the end, an epigram. The supposed letter of Eratos- | |
9511 thenes is a forgery, but the author rendered a real service | |
9512 <pb n=245><head>HISTORY OF THE PROBLEM</head> | |
9513 by actually quoting the proof and the epigram, which are the | |
9514 genuine work of Eratosthenes. | |
9515 <p>Our document begins with the story that an ancient tragic | |
9516 poet had represented Minos as putting up a tomb to Glaucus | |
9517 but being dissatisfied with its being only 100 feet each way; | |
9518 Minos was then represented as saying that it must be made | |
9519 double the size, by increasing each of the dimensions in that | |
9520 ratio. Naturally the poet ‘was thought to have made a mis- | |
9521 take’. Von Wilamowitz has shown that the verses which | |
9522 Minos is made to say cannot have been from any play by | |
9523 Aeschylus, Sophocles, or Euripides. They are the work of | |
9524 some obscure poet, and the ignorance of mathematics shown | |
9525 by him is the only reason why they became notorious and so | |
9526 survived. The letter goes on to say that | |
9527 <p>‘Geometers took up the question and sought to find out | |
9528 how one could double a given solid while keeping the same | |
9529 shape; the problem took the name of “the duplication of the | |
9530 cube” because they started from a cube and sought to double | |
9531 it. For a long time all their efforts were vain; then Hippo- | |
9532 crates of Chios discovered for the first time that, if we can | |
9533 devise a way of finding two mean proportionals in continued | |
9534 proportion between two straight lines the greater of which | |
9535 is double of the less, the cube will be doubled; that is, one | |
9536 puzzle (<G>a)po/rhma</G>) was turned by him into another not less | |
9537 difficult. After a time, so goes the story, certain Delians, who | |
9538 were commanded by the oracle to double a certain altar, fell | |
9539 into the same quandary as before.’ | |
9540 <p>At this point the versions of the story diverge somewhat. | |
9541 The pseudo-Eratosthenes continues as follows: | |
9542 <p>‘They therefore sent over to beg the geometers who were | |
9543 with Plato in the Academy to find them the solution. The | |
9544 latter applying themselves diligently to the problem of finding | |
9545 two mean proportionals between two given straight lines, | |
9546 Archytas of Taras is said to have found them by means of | |
9547 a half cylinder, and Eudoxus by means of the so-called curved | |
9548 lines; but, as it turned out, all their solutions were theoretical, | |
9549 and no one of them was able to give a practical construction | |
9550 for ordinary use, save to a certain small extent Menaechmus, | |
9551 and that with difficulty.’ | |
9552 <p>Fortunately we have Eratosthenes's own version in a quota- | |
9553 tion by Theon of Smyrna: | |
9554 <p>‘Eratosthenes in his work entitled <I>Platonicus</I> relates that, | |
9555 <pb n=246><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
9556 when the god proclaimed to the Delians by the oracle that, if | |
9557 they would get rid of a plague, they should construct an altar | |
9558 double of the existing one, their craftsmen fell into great | |
9559 perplexity in their efforts to discover how a solid could be made | |
9560 double of a (similar) solid; they therefore went to ask Plato | |
9561 about it, and he replied that the oracle meant, not that the god | |
9562 wanted an altar of double the size, but that he wished, in | |
9563 setting them the task, to shame the Greeks for their neglect | |
9564 of mathematics and their contempt for geometry.’<note>Theon of Smyrna, p. 2. 3-12.</note> | |
9565 <p>Eratosthenes's version may well be true; and there is no | |
9566 doubt that the question was studied in the Academy, solutions | |
9567 being attributed to Eudoxus, Menaechmus, and even (though | |
9568 erroneously) to Plato himself. The description by the pseudo- | |
9569 Eratosthenes of the three solutions by Archytas, Eudoxus and | |
9570 Menaechmus is little more than a paraphrase of the lines about | |
9571 them in the genuine epigram of Eratosthenes, | |
9572 <p>‘Do not seek to do the difficult business of the cylinders of | |
9573 Archytas, or to cut the cones in the triads of Menaechmus, or | |
9574 to draw such a curved form of lines as is described by the | |
9575 god-fearing Eudoxus.’ | |
9576 <p>The different versions are reflected in Plutarch, who in one | |
9577 place gives Plato's answer to the Delians in almost the same | |
9578 words as Eratosthenes,<note>Plutarch, <I>De E apud Delphos</I>, c. 6, 386 E.</note> and in another place tells us that | |
9579 Plato referred the Delians to Eudoxus and Helicon of Cyzicus | |
9580 for a solution of the problem.<note><I>De genio Socratis</I>, c. 7, 579 C, D.</note> | |
9581 <p>After Hippocrates had discovered that the duplication of | |
9582 the cube was equivalent to finding two mean proportionals in | |
9583 continued proportion between two given straight lines, the | |
9584 problem seems to have been attacked in the latter form | |
9585 exclusively. The various solutions will now be reproduced | |
9586 in chronological order. | |
9587 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>Archytas.</I></C> | |
9588 <p>The solution of Archytas is the most remarkable of all, | |
9589 especially when his date is considered (first half of fourth cen- | |
9590 tury B.C.), because it is not a construction in a plane but a bold | |
9591 <pb n=247><head>ARCHYTAS</head> | |
9592 construction in three dimensions, determining a certain point | |
9593 as the intersection of three surfaces of revolution, (1) a right | |
9594 cone, (2) a cylinder, (3) a <I>tore</I> or anchor-ring with inner | |
9595 diameter <I>nil.</I> The intersection of the two latter surfaces | |
9596 gives (says Archytas) a certain curve (which is in fact a curve | |
9597 of double curvature), and the point required is found as the | |
9598 point in which the cone meets this curve. | |
9599 <FIG> | |
9600 <p>Suppose that <I>AC, AB</I> are the two straight lines between | |
9601 which two mean proportionals are to be found, and let <I>AC</I> be | |
9602 made the diameter of a circle and <I>AB</I> a chord in it. | |
9603 <p>Draw a semicircle with <I>AC</I> as diameter, but in a plane at | |
9604 right angles to the plane of the circle <I>ABC</I>, and imagine this | |
9605 semicircle to revolve about a straight line through <I>A</I> per- | |
9606 pendicular to the plane of <I>ABC</I> (thus describing half a <I>tore</I> | |
9607 with inner diameter <I>nil</I>). | |
9608 <p>Next draw a right half-cylinder on the semicircle <I>ABC</I> as | |
9609 base; this will cut the surface of the half-<I>tore</I> in a certain | |
9610 curve. | |
9611 <p>Lastly let <I>CD</I>, the tangent to the circle <I>ABC</I> at the point <I>C</I>, | |
9612 meet <I>AB</I> produced in <I>D</I>; and suppose the triangle <I>ADC</I> to | |
9613 revolve about <I>AC</I> as axis. This will generate the surface | |
9614 of a right circular cone; the point <I>B</I> will describe a semicircle | |
9615 <I>BQE</I> at right angles to the plane of <I>ABC</I> and having its | |
9616 diameter <I>BE</I> at right angles to <I>AC</I>; and the surface of the | |
9617 cone will meet in some point <I>P</I> the curve which is the inter- | |
9618 section of the half-cylinder and the half-<I>tore.</I> | |
9619 <pb n=248><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
9620 <p>Let <I>APC</I>′ be the corresponding position of the revolving | |
9621 semicircle, and let <I>AC</I>′ meet the circumference <I>ABC</I> in <I>M.</I> | |
9622 <p>Drawing <I>PM</I> perpendicular to the plane of <I>ABC</I>, we see | |
9623 that it must meet the circumference of the circle <I>ABC</I> because | |
9624 <I>P</I> is on the cylinder which stands on <I>ABC</I> as base. | |
9625 <p>Let <I>AP</I> meet the circumference of the semicircle <I>BQE</I> in <I>Q</I>, | |
9626 and let <I>AC</I>′ meet its diameter in <I>N.</I> Join <I>PC</I>′, <I>QM, QN.</I> | |
9627 <p>Then, since both semicircles are perpendicular to the plane | |
9628 <I>ABC</I>, so is their line of intersection <I>QN</I> [Eucl. XI. 19]. | |
9629 <p>Therefore <I>QN</I> is perpendicular to <I>BE.</I> | |
9630 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>QN</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BN.NE</I>=<I>AN.NM</I></MATH>, [Eucl. III. 35] | |
9631 so that the angle <I>AQM</I> is a right angle. | |
9632 <p>But the angle <I>APC</I>′ is also right; | |
9633 therefore <I>MQ</I> is parallel to <I>C</I>′<I>P.</I> | |
9634 <p>It follows, by similar triangles, that | |
9635 <MATH><I>C</I>′<I>A</I>:<I>AP</I>=<I>AP</I>:<I>AM</I>=<I>AM</I>:<I>AQ</I></MATH>; | |
9636 that is, <MATH><I>AC</I>:<I>AP</I>=<I>AP</I>:<I>AM</I>=<I>AM</I>:<I>AB</I></MATH>, | |
9637 and <I>AB, AM, AP, AC</I> are in continued proportion, so that | |
9638 <I>AM, AP</I> are the two mean proportionals required. | |
9639 <p>In the language of analytical geometry, if <I>AC</I> is the axis | |
9640 of <I>x</I>, a line through <I>A</I> perpendicular to <I>AC</I> in the plane of | |
9641 <I>ABC</I> the axis of <I>y</I>, and a line through <I>A</I> parallel to <I>PM</I> the | |
9642 axis of <I>z</I>, then <I>P</I> is determined as the intersection of the | |
9643 surfaces | |
9644 (1) <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>z</I><SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>)<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, (the cone) | |
9645 (2) <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>ax</I></MATH>, (the cylinder) | |
9646 (3) <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>z</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>a</I>√(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>, (the <I>tore</I>) | |
9647 where <MATH><I>AC</I>=<I>a, AB</I>=<I>b.</I></MATH> | |
9648 <p>From the first two equations we obtain | |
9649 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>z</I><SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)<SUP>2</SUP>/<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
9650 and from this and (3) we have | |
9651 <MATH><I>a</I>/√(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>z</I><SUP>2</SUP>)=&radic(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>z</I><SUP>2</SUP>)/&radic(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)=√(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I> | |
9652 <SUP>2</SUP>)/<I>b</I></MATH>, | |
9653 or <MATH><I>AC</I>:<I>AP</I>=<I>AP</I>:<I>AM</I>=<I>AM</I>:<I>AB.</I></MATH> | |
9654 <pb n=249><head>ARCHYTAS. EUDOXUS</head> | |
9655 <p>Compounding the ratios, we have | |
9656 <MATH><I>AC</I>:<I>AB</I>=(<I>AM</I>:<I>AB</I>)<SUP>3</SUP></MATH>; | |
9657 therefore the cube of side <I>AM</I> is to the cube of side <I>AB</I> as <I>AC</I> | |
9658 is to <I>AB.</I> | |
9659 <p>In the particular case where <MATH><I>AC</I>=2<I>AB, AM</I><SUP>3</SUP>=2<I>AB</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH>, | |
9660 and the cube is doubled. | |
9661 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Eudoxus.</I></C> | |
9662 <p>Eutocius had evidently seen some document purporting to | |
9663 give Eudoxus's solution, but it is clear that it must have | |
9664 been an erroneous version. The epigram of Eratosthenes | |
9665 says that Eudoxus solved the problem by means of lines | |
9666 of a ‘curved or bent form’ (<G>kampu/lon ei=)dos e)n grammai=s</G>). | |
9667 According to Eutocius, while Eudoxus said in his preface | |
9668 that he had discovered a solution by means of ‘curved lines’, | |
9669 yet, when he came to the proof, he made no use of such | |
9670 lines, and further he committed an obvious error in that he | |
9671 treated a certain discrete proportion as if it were continuous.<note>Archimedes, ed. Heib., vol. iii, p. 56. 4-8.</note> | |
9672 It may be that, while Eudoxus made use of what was really | |
9673 a curvilinear locus, he did not actually draw the whole curve | |
9674 but only indicated a point or two upon it sufficient for his | |
9675 purpose. This may explain the first part of Eutocius's remark, | |
9676 but in any case we cannot believe the second part; Eudoxus | |
9677 was too accomplished a mathematician to make any confusion | |
9678 between a discrete and a continuous proportion. Presumably | |
9679 the mistake which Eutocius found was made by some one | |
9680 who wrongly transcribed the original; but it cannot be too | |
9681 much regretted, because it caused Eutocius to omit the solution | |
9682 altogether from his account. | |
9683 <p>Tannery<note>Tannery, <I>Mémoires scientifiques</I>, vol. i, pp. 53-61.</note> made an ingenious suggestion to the effect that | |
9684 Eudoxus's construction was really adapted from that of | |
9685 Archytas by what is practically projection on the plane | |
9686 of the circle <I>ABC</I> in Archytas's construction. It is not difficult | |
9687 to represent the projection on that plane of the curve of | |
9688 intersection between the cone and the <I>tore</I>, and, when this | |
9689 curve is drawn in the plane <I>ABC</I>, its intersection with the | |
9690 circle <I>ABC</I> itself gives the point <I>M</I> in Archytas's figure. | |
9691 <pb n=250><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
9692 <p>The projection on the plane <I>ABC</I> of the intersection between | |
9693 the cone and the <I>tore</I> is seen, by means of their equations | |
9694 (1) and (3) above, to be | |
9695 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>a</I>&radic(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>, | |
9696 or, in polar coordinates referred to <I>A</I> as origin and <I>AC</I> as axis, | |
9697 <MATH><G>r</G>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>/(<G>a</G>cos<SUP>2</SUP><G>q</G>)</MATH> | |
9698 <p>It is easy to find any number of points on the curve. Take | |
9699 the circle <I>ABC</I>, and let <I>AC</I> the diameter and <I>AB</I> a chord | |
9700 be the two given straight lines between which two mean | |
9701 proportionals have to be found. | |
9702 <FIG> | |
9703 <p>With the above notation | |
9704 <MATH><I>AC</I>=<I>a, AB</I>=<I>b</I></MATH>; | |
9705 and, if <I>BF</I> be drawn perpendicular to <I>AC</I>, | |
9706 <MATH><I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>AF.AC</I></MATH>, | |
9707 or <MATH><I>AF</I>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>a</I></MATH>. | |
9708 <p>Take any point <I>G</I> on <I>BF</I> and join <I>AG.</I> | |
9709 <p>Then, if <MATH>∠<I>GAF</I>=<G>q</G>, <I>AG</I>=<I>AF</I>sec<G>q</G></MATH>. | |
9710 <p>With <I>A</I> as centre and <I>AG</I> as radius draw a circle meeting | |
9711 <I>AC</I> in <I>H</I>, and draw <I>HL</I> at right angles to <I>AC</I>, meeting <I>AG</I> | |
9712 produced in <I>L.</I> | |
9713 <pb n=251><head>EUDOXUS. MENAECHMUS</head> | |
9714 <p>Then <MATH><I>AL</I>=<I>AH</I> sec <G>q</G>=<I>AG</I> sec <G>q</G>=<I>AF</I> sec<SUP>2</SUP> <G>q</G></MATH>. | |
9715 <p>That is, if <MATH><G>r</G>=<I>AL,</I> <G>r</G>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>a</I> sec<SUP>2</SUP> <G>q</G></MATH>, | |
9716 and <I>L</I> is a point on the curve. | |
9717 <p>Similarly any number of other points on the curve may be | |
9718 found. If the curve meets the circle <I>ABC</I> in <I>M,</I> the length | |
9719 <I>AM</I> is the same as that of <I>AM</I> in the figure of Archytas's | |
9720 solution. | |
9721 <p>And <I>AM</I> is the first of the two mean proportionals between | |
9722 <I>AB</I> and <I>AC.</I> The second (= <I>AP</I> in the figure of Archytas's | |
9723 solution) is easily found from the relation <MATH><I>AM</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>AB.AP</I></MATH>, | |
9724 and the problem is solved. | |
9725 <p>It must be admitted that Tannery's suggestion as to | |
9726 Eudoxus's method is attractive; but of course it is only a con- | |
9727 jecture. To my mind the objection to it is that it is too close | |
9728 an adaptation of Archytas's ideas. Eudoxus was, it is true, | |
9729 a pupil of Archytas, and there is a good deal of similarity | |
9730 of character between Archytas's construction of the curve of | |
9731 double curvature and Eudoxus's construction of the spherical | |
9732 lemniscate by means of revolving concentric spheres; but | |
9733 Eudoxus was, I think, too original a mathematician to con- | |
9734 tent himself with a mere adaptation of Archytas's method | |
9735 of solution. | |
9736 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>Menaechmus.</I></C> | |
9737 <p>Two solutions by Menaechmus of the problem of finding | |
9738 two mean proportionals are described by Eutocius; both find | |
9739 a certain point as the intersection between two conics, in | |
9740 the one case two parabolas, in the other a parabola and | |
9741 a rectangular hyperbola. The solutions are referred to in | |
9742 Eratosthenes's epigram: ‘do not’, says Eratosthenes, ‘cut the | |
9743 cone in the triads of Menaechmus.’ From the solutions | |
9744 coupled with this remark it is inferred that Menaechmus | |
9745 was the discoverer of the conic sections. | |
9746 <p>Menaechmus, brother of Dinostratus, who used the <I>quadra- | |
9747 trix</I> to square the circle, was a pupil of Eudoxus and flourished | |
9748 about the middle of the fourth century B. C. The most attrac- | |
9749 tive from of the story about the geometer and the king who | |
9750 wanted a short cut to geometry is told of Menaechmus and | |
9751 <pb n=252><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
9752 Alexander: ‘O king,’ said Menaechmus, ‘for travelling over | |
9753 the country there are royal roads and roads for common | |
9754 citizens, but in geometry there is one road for all.’<note>Stobaeus, <I>Eclogae</I>, ii. 31, 115 (vol. ii, p. 228. 30, Wachsmuth).</note> A similar | |
9755 story is indeed told of Euclid and Ptolemy; but there would | |
9756 be a temptation to transfer such a story at a later date to | |
9757 the more famous mathematician. Menaechmus was evidently | |
9758 a considerable mathematician; he is associated by Proclus with | |
9759 Amyclas of Heraclea, a friend of Plato, and with Dinostratus | |
9760 as having ‘made the whole of geometry more perfect’.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 67. 9.</note> | |
9761 Beyond, however, the fact that the discovery of the conic | |
9762 sections is attributed to him, we have very few notices relating | |
9763 to his work. He is mentioned along with Aristotle and | |
9764 Callippus as a supporter of the theory of concentric spheres | |
9765 invented by Eudoxus, but as postulating a larger number of | |
9766 spheres.<note>Theon of Smyrna, pp. 201. 22-202. 2.</note> We gather from Proclus that he wrote on the | |
9767 technology of mathematics; he discussed for instance the | |
9768 difference between the broader meaning of the word <I>element</I> | |
9769 (in which any proposition leading to another may be said | |
9770 to be an element of it) and the stricter meaning of something | |
9771 simple and fundamental standing to consequences drawn from | |
9772 it in the relation of a <I>principle,</I> which is capable of being | |
9773 universally applied and enters into the proof of all manner | |
9774 of propositions.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, pp. 72. 23-73. 14.</note> Again, he did not agree in the distinction | |
9775 between theorems and problems, but would have it that they | |
9776 were all <I>problems,</I> though directed to two different objects<note><I>Ib.,</I> p. 78. 8-13.</note>; | |
9777 he also discussed the important question of the convertibility | |
9778 of theorems and the conditions necessary to it.<note><I>Ib.,</I> p. 254. 4-5.</note> | |
9779 <p>If <I>x, y</I> are two mean proportionals between straight | |
9780 lines <I>a, b,</I> | |
9781 that is, if <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>x</I>=<I>x</I>:<I>y</I>=<I>y</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>, | |
9782 then clearly <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>ay</I>, <I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>bx</I></MATH>, and <MATH><I>xy</I>=<I>ab</I></MATH>. | |
9783 <p>It is easy for us to recognize here the Cartesian equations | |
9784 of two parabolas referred to a diameter and the tangent at its | |
9785 extremity, and of a hyperbola referred to its asymptotes. | |
9786 But Menaechmus appears to have had not only to recognize, | |
9787 <pb n=253><head>MENAECHMUS AND CONICS</head> | |
9788 but to discover, the existence of curves having the properties | |
9789 corresponding to the Cartesian equations. He discovered | |
9790 them in plane sections of right circular cones, and it would | |
9791 doubtless be the properties of the <I>principal</I> ordinates in | |
9792 relation to the abscissae on the axes which he would arrive | |
9793 at first. Though only the parabola and the hyperbola are | |
9794 wanted for the particular problem, he would certainly not | |
9795 fail to find the ellipse and its property as well. But in the | |
9796 case of the hyperbola he needed the property of the curve | |
9797 with reference to the <I>asymptotes,</I> represented by the equation | |
9798 <MATH><I>xy</I>=<I>ab</I></MATH>; he must therefore have discovered the existence of | |
9799 the asymptotes, and must have proved the property, at all | |
9800 events for the rectangular hyperbola. The original method | |
9801 of discovery of the conics will occupy us later. In the mean- | |
9802 time it is obvious that the use of any two of the curves | |
9803 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>ay</I>, <I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>bx</I>, <I>xy</I>=<I>ab</I></MATH> gives the solution of our problem, | |
9804 and it was in fact the intersection of the second and third | |
9805 which Menaechmus used in his first solution, while for his | |
9806 second solution he used the first two. Eutocius gives the | |
9807 analysis and synthesis of each solution in full. I shall repro- | |
9808 duce them as shortly as possible, only suppressing the use of | |
9809 four separate lines representing the two given straight lines | |
9810 and the two required means in the figure of the first solution. | |
9811 <C><I>First solution.</I></C> | |
9812 <p>Suppose that <I>AO, OB</I> are two given straight lines of which | |
9813 <I>AO</I> > <I>OB,</I> and let them form a right angle at <I>O.</I> | |
9814 <p>Suppose the problem solved, and let the two mean propor- | |
9815 tionals be <I>OM</I> measured along <I>BO</I> produced and <I>ON</I> measured | |
9816 along <I>AO</I> produced. Complete the rectangle <I>OMPN.</I> | |
9817 <p>Then, since <MATH><I>AO</I>:<I>OM</I>=<I>OM</I>:<I>ON</I>=<I>ON</I>:<I>OB</I></MATH>, | |
9818 we have (1) <MATH><I>OB.OM</I>=<I>ON</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>PM</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
9819 so that <I>P</I> lies on a parabola which has <I>O</I> for vertex, <I>OM</I> for | |
9820 axis, and <I>OB</I> for <I>latus rectum</I>; | |
9821 and (2) <MATH><I>AO.OB</I>=<I>OM.ON</I>=<I>PN.PM</I></MATH>, | |
9822 so that <I>P</I> lies on a hyperbola with <I>O</I> as centre and <I>OM, ON</I> as | |
9823 asymptotes. | |
9824 <pb n=254><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
9825 <p>Accordingly, to find the point <I>P,</I> we have to construct | |
9826 (1) a parabola with <I>O</I> as vertex, <I>OM</I> as axis, and <I>latus rectum</I> | |
9827 equal to <I>OB,</I> | |
9828 <FIG> | |
9829 (2) a hyperbola with asymptotes <I>OM, ON</I> and such that | |
9830 the rectangle contained by straight lines <I>PM, PN</I> drawn | |
9831 from any point <I>P</I> on the curve parallel to one asymptote and | |
9832 meeting the other is equal to the rectangle <I>AO.OB.</I> | |
9833 <p>The intersection of the parabola and hyperbola gives the | |
9834 point <I>P</I> which solves the problem, for | |
9835 <MATH><I>AO</I>:<I>PN</I>=<I>PN</I>:<I>PM</I>=<I>PM</I>:<I>OB</I></MATH>. | |
9836 <C><I>Second solution.</I></C> | |
9837 <p>Supposing the problem solved, as in the first case, we have, | |
9838 since <MATH><I>AO</I>:<I>OM</I>=<I>OM</I>:<I>ON</I>=<I>ON</I>:<I>OB</I></MATH>, | |
9839 <p>(1) the relation <MATH><I>OB.OM</I>=<I>ON</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>PM</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
9840 <FIG> | |
9841 <pb n=255><head>MENAECHMUS AND CONICS</head> | |
9842 so that <I>P</I> lies on a parabola which has <I>O</I> for vertex, <I>OM</I> for | |
9843 axis, and <I>OB</I> for <I>latus rectum,</I> | |
9844 <p>(2) the similar relation <MATH><I>AO.ON</I>=<I>OM</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>PN</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
9845 so that <I>P</I> lies on a parabola which has <I>O</I> for vertex, <I>ON</I> for | |
9846 axis, and <I>OA</I> for <I>latus rectum.</I> | |
9847 <p>In order therefore to find <I>P,</I> we have only to construct the | |
9848 two parabolas with <I>OM, ON</I> for axes and <I>OB, OA</I> for <I>latera | |
9849 recta</I> respectively; the intersection of the two parabolas gives | |
9850 a point <I>P</I> such that | |
9851 <MATH><I>AO</I>:<I>PN</I>=<I>PN</I>:<I>PM</I>=<I>PM</I>:<I>OB</I></MATH>, | |
9852 and the problem is solved. | |
9853 <p>(We shall see later on that Menaechmus did not use the | |
9854 names <I>parabola</I> and <I>hyperbola</I> to describe the curves, those | |
9855 names being due to Apollonius.) | |
9856 <C>(<G>e</G>) <I>The solution attributed to Plato.</I></C> | |
9857 <p>This is the first in Eutocius's arrangement of the various | |
9858 solutions reproduced by him. But there is almost conclusive | |
9859 reason, for thinking that it is wrongly attributed to Plato. | |
9860 No one but Eutocius mentions it, and there is no reference to | |
9861 it in Eratosthenes's epigram, whereas, if a solution by Plato | |
9862 had then been known, it could hardly fail to have been | |
9863 mentioned along with those of Archytas, Menaechmus, and | |
9864 Eudoxus. Again, Plutarch says that Plato told the Delians | |
9865 that the problem of the two mean proportionals was no easy | |
9866 one, but that Eudoxus or Helicon of Cyzicus would solve it | |
9867 for them; he did not apparently propose to attack it himself. | |
9868 And, lastly, the solution attributed to him is mechanical, | |
9869 whereas we are twice told that Plato objected to mechanical | |
9870 solutions as destroying the good of geometry.<note>Plutarch, <I>Quaest. Conviv.</I> 8. 2. 1, p. 718 E, F; <I>Vita Marcelli,</I> c. 14. 5.</note> Attempts | |
9871 have been made to reconcile the contrary traditions. It is | |
9872 argued that, while Plato objected to mechanical solutions on | |
9873 principle, he wished to show how easy it was to discover | |
9874 such solutions and put forward that attributed to him as an | |
9875 illustration of the fact. I prefer to treat the silence of | |
9876 Eratosthenes as conclusive on the point, and to suppose that | |
9877 the solution was invented in the Academy by some one con- | |
9878 temporary with or later than Menaechmus. | |
9879 <pb n=256><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
9880 <p>For, if we look at the figure of Menaechmus's second solu- | |
9881 tion, we shall see that the given straight lines and the two | |
9882 means between them are shown in cyclic order (clockwise) | |
9883 as straight lines radiating from <I>O</I> and separated by right | |
9884 angles. This is exactly the arrangement of the lines in | |
9885 ‘Plato's’ solution. Hence it seems probable that some one | |
9886 who had Menaechmus's second solution before him wished | |
9887 to show how the same representation of the four straight | |
9888 lines could be got by a mechanical construction as an alterna- | |
9889 tive to the use of conics. | |
9890 <p>Drawing the two given straight lines with the means, that | |
9891 is to say, <I>OA, OM, ON, OB,</I> in cyclic clockwise order, as in | |
9892 Menaechmus's second solution, we have | |
9893 <MATH><I>AO</I>:<I>OM</I>=<I>OM</I>:<I>ON</I>=<I>ON</I>:<I>OB</I></MATH>, | |
9894 and it is clear that, if <I>AM, MN, NB</I> are joined, the angles | |
9895 <I>AMN, MNB</I> are both right angles. The problem then is, | |
9896 given <I>OA, OB</I> at right angles to one another, to contrive the | |
9897 rest of the figure so that the angles at <I>M, N</I> are right. | |
9898 <FIG> | |
9899 <p>The instrument used is somewhat like that which a shoe- | |
9900 maker uses to measure the length of the foot. <I>FGH</I> is a rigid | |
9901 right angle made, say, of wood. <I>KL</I> is a strut which, fastened, | |
9902 say, to a stick <I>KF</I> which slides along <I>GF,</I> can move while | |
9903 remaining always parallel to <I>GH</I> or at right angles to <I>GF.</I> | |
9904 <p>Now place the rigid right angle <I>FGH</I> so that the leg <I>GH</I> | |
9905 passes through <I>B,</I> and turn it until the angle <I>G</I> lies on <I>AO</I> | |
9906 <pb n=257><head>THE SOLUTION ATTRIBUTED TO PLATO</head> | |
9907 produced. Then slide the movable strut <I>KL,</I> which remains | |
9908 always parallel to <I>GH,</I> until its edge (towards <I>GH</I>) passes | |
9909 through <I>A.</I> If now the inner angular point between the | |
9910 strut <I>KL</I> and the leg <I>FG</I> does not lie on <I>BO</I> produced, | |
9911 the machine has to be turned again and the strut moved | |
9912 until the said point does lie on <I>BO</I> produced, as <I>M</I>, care being | |
9913 taken that during the whole of the motion the inner edges | |
9914 of <I>KL</I> and <I>HG</I> pass through <I>A, B</I> respectively and the inner | |
9915 angular point at <I>G</I> moves along <I>AO</I> produced. | |
9916 <p>That it is possible for the machine to take up the desired | |
9917 position is clear from the figure of Menaechmus, in which | |
9918 <I>MO, NO</I> are the means between <I>AO</I> and <I>BO</I> and the angles | |
9919 <I>AMN, MNB</I> are right angles, although to get it into the | |
9920 required position is perhaps not quite easy. | |
9921 <p>The matter may be looked at analytically thus. Let us | |
9922 take any other position of the machine in which the strut and | |
9923 the leg <I>GH</I> pass through <I>A, B</I> respectively, while <I>G</I> lies on <I>AO</I> | |
9924 produced, but <I>P,</I> the angular point between the strut <I>KL</I> and | |
9925 <FIG> | |
9926 the leg <I>FG,</I> does not lie on <I>OM</I> produced. Take <I>ON, OM</I> as | |
9927 the axes of <I>x, y</I> respectively. Draw <I>PR</I> perpendicular to <I>OG,</I> | |
9928 and produce <I>GP</I> to meet <I>OM</I> produced in <I>S.</I> | |
9929 <p>Let <MATH><I>AO</I>=<I>a</I>, <I>BO</I>=<I>b</I>, <I>OG</I>=<I>r</I></MATH>. | |
9930 <pb n=258><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
9931 <p>Then <MATH><I>AR.RG</I>=<I>PR</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
9932 or <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>) (<I>r</I>-<I>x</I>)=<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. (1) | |
9933 <p>Also, by similar triangles, | |
9934 <MATH><I>PR</I>:<I>RG</I>=<I>SO</I>:<I>OG</I> | |
9935 =<I>OG</I>:<I>OB</I></MATH>; | |
9936 or <MATH><I>y</I>/(<I>r</I>-<I>x</I>)=<I>r/b</I></MATH>. (2) | |
9937 <p>From the equation (1) we obtain | |
9938 <MATH><I>r</I>=(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>ax</I>)/(<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>)</MATH>, | |
9939 and, by multiplying (1) and (2), we have | |
9940 <MATH><I>by</I>(<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>)=<I>ry</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
9941 whence, substituting the value of <I>r,</I> we obtain, as the locus of | |
9942 <I>P,</I> a curve of the third degree, | |
9943 <MATH><I>b</I>(<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>=<I>y</I>(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>ax</I>)</MATH>. | |
9944 <p>The intersection (<I>M</I>) of this curve with the axis of <I>y</I> gives | |
9945 <MATH><I>OM</I><SUP>3</SUP>=<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b</I></MATH>. | |
9946 <p>As a theoretical solution, therefore, ‘Plato's’ solution is | |
9947 more difficult than that of Menaechmus. | |
9948 <C>(<G>z</G>) <I>Eratosthenes.</I></C> | |
9949 <p>This is also a mechanical solution effected by means of | |
9950 three plane figures (equal right-angled triangles or rectangles) | |
9951 which can move parallel to one another and to their original | |
9952 positions between two parallel rulers forming a sort of frame | |
9953 and fitted with grooves so arranged that the figures can | |
9954 move over one another. Pappus's account makes the figures | |
9955 triangles,<note>Pappus, iii, pp. 56-8.</note> Eutocius has parallelograms with diagonals drawn; | |
9956 triangles seem preferable. I shall use the lettering of Eutocius | |
9957 for the second figure so far as it goes, but I shall use triangles | |
9958 instead of rectangles. | |
9959 <pb n=259><head>ERATOSTHENES</head> | |
9960 <p>Suppose the frame bounded by the parallels <I>AX, EY.</I> The | |
9961 <FIG> | |
9962 <CAP>FIG. 1.</CAP> | |
9963 initial position of the triangles is that shown in the first figure, | |
9964 where the triangles are <I>AMF, MNG, NQH.</I> | |
9965 <p>In the second figure the straight lines <I>AE, DH</I> which are | |
9966 <FIG> | |
9967 <CAP>FIG. 2.</CAP> | |
9968 parallel to one another are those between which two mean | |
9969 proportionals have to be found. | |
9970 <p>In the second figure the triangles (except <I>AMF,</I> which | |
9971 remains fixed) are moved parallel to their original positions | |
9972 towards <I>AMF</I> so that they overlap (as <I>AMF</I>, <I>M</I>′<I>NG</I>, <I>N</I>′<I>QH</I>), | |
9973 <I>NQH</I> taking the position <I>N</I>′<I>QH</I> in which <I>QH</I> passes through <I>D,</I> | |
9974 and <I>MNG</I> a position <I>M</I>′<I>NG</I> such that the points <I>B, C</I> where | |
9975 <I>MF</I>, <I>M</I>′<I>G</I> and <I>NG</I>, <I>N</I>′<I>H</I> respectively intersect are in a straight | |
9976 line with <I>A, D.</I> | |
9977 <p>Let <I>AD, EH</I> meet in <I>K.</I> | |
9978 <p>Then <MATH><I>EK</I>:<I>KF</I>=<I>AK</I>:<I>KB</I> | |
9979 =<I>FK</I>:<I>KG</I></MATH>, | |
9980 and <MATH><I>EK</I>:<I>KF</I>=<I>AE</I>:<I>BF</I></MATH>, while <MATH><I>FK</I>:<I>KG</I>=<I>BF</I>:<I>CG</I></MATH>; | |
9981 therefore <MATH><I>AE</I>:<I>BF</I>=<I>BF</I>:<I>CG</I></MATH>. | |
9982 <p>Similarly <MATH><I>BF</I>:<I>CG</I>=<I>CG</I>:<I>DH</I></MATH>, | |
9983 so that <I>AE, BF, CG, DH</I> are in continued proportion, and | |
9984 <I>BF, CG</I> are the required mean proportionals. | |
9985 <p>This is substantially the short proof given in Eratosthenes's | |
9986 <pb n=260><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
9987 inscription on the column; the construction was left to be | |
9988 inferred from the single figure which corresponded to the | |
9989 second above. | |
9990 <p>The epigram added by Eratosthenes was as follows: | |
9991 <p>‘If, good friend, thou mindest to obtain from a small (cube) | |
9992 a cube double of it, and duly to change any solid figure into | |
9993 another, this is in thy power; thou canst find the measure of | |
9994 a fold, a pit, or the broad basin of a hollow well, by this | |
9995 method, that is, if thou (thus) catch between two rulers (two) | |
9996 means with their extreme ends-converging.<note>Lit. ‘converging with their extreme ends’ (<G>te/rmasin a(/krois sundro- | |
9997 ma/das</G>).</note> Do not thou seek | |
9998 to do the difficult business of Archytas's cylinders, or to cut the | |
9999 cone in the triads of Menaechmus, or to compass such a curved | |
10000 form of lines as is described by the god-fearing Eudoxus. | |
10001 Nay thou couldst, on these tablets, easily find a myriad of | |
10002 means, beginning from a small base. Happy art thou, | |
10003 Ptolemy, in that, as a father the equal of his son in youthful | |
10004 vigour, thou hast thyself given him all that is dear to Muses | |
10005 and Kings, and may he in the future,<note>Reading with v. Wilamowitz <G>o^ d' e)s u(/steron</G>.</note> O Zeus, god of heaven, | |
10006 also receive the sceptre at thy hands. Thus may it be, and | |
10007 let any one who sees this offering say “This is the gift of | |
10008 Eratosthenes of Cyrene”.’ | |
10009 <C>(<G>h</G>) <I>Nicomedes.</I></C> | |
10010 <p>The solution by Nicomedes was contained in his book on | |
10011 conchoids, and, according to Eutocius, he was inordinately | |
10012 proud of it, claiming for it much superiority over the method | |
10013 of Eratosthenes, which he derided as being impracticable as | |
10014 well as ungeometrical. | |
10015 <p>Nicomedes reduced the problem to a <G>neu=sis</G> which he solved | |
10016 by means of the conchoid. Both Pappus and Eutocius explain | |
10017 the method (the former twice over<note>Pappus, iii, pp. 58. 23-62. 13; iv, pp. 246. 20-250. 25.</note>) with little variation. | |
10018 <p>Let <I>AB, BC</I> be the two straight lines between which two | |
10019 means are to be found. Complete the parallelogram <I>ABCL.</I> | |
10020 <p>Bisect <I>AB, BC</I> in <I>D</I> and <I>E.</I> | |
10021 <p>Join <I>LD,</I> and produce it to meet <I>CB</I> produced in <I>G.</I> | |
10022 <p>Draw <I>EF</I> at right angles to <I>BC</I> and of such length that | |
10023 <MATH><I>CF</I>=<I>AD.</I></MATH> | |
10024 <p>Join <I>GF,</I> and draw <I>CH</I> parallel to it. | |
10025 <pb n=261><head>NICOMEDES</head> | |
10026 <p>Then from the point <I>F</I> draw <I>FHK</I> cutting <I>CH</I> and <I>EC</I> | |
10027 produced in <I>H</I> and <I>K</I> in such a way that the intercept | |
10028 <MATH><I>HK</I>=<I>CF</I>=<I>AD</I></MATH>. | |
10029 <p>(This is done by means of a conchoid constructed with <I>F</I> as | |
10030 pole, <I>CH</I> as ‘ruler’, and ‘distance’ equal to <I>AD</I> or <I>CF,</I> This | |
10031 <FIG> | |
10032 conchoid meets <I>EC</I> produced in a point <I>K.</I> We then join <I>FK</I> | |
10033 and, by the property of the conchoid, <MATH><I>HK</I> = the ‘distance’</MATH>.) | |
10034 <p>Join <I>KL,</I> and produce it to meet <I>BA</I> produced in <I>M.</I> | |
10035 <p>Then shall <I>CK, MA</I> be the required mean proportionals. | |
10036 <p>For, since <I>BC</I> is bisected at <I>E</I> and produced to <I>K,</I> | |
10037 <MATH><I>BK.KC</I>+<I>CE</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>EK</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
10038 <p>Add <I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP> to each; | |
10039 therefore <MATH><I>BK.KC</I>+<I>CF</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>KF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. (1) | |
10040 <p>Now, by parallels, <MATH><I>MA</I>:<I>AB</I>=<I>ML</I>:<I>LK</I> | |
10041 =<I>BC</I>:<I>CK</I></MATH>. | |
10042 <p>But <MATH><I>AB</I>=2<I>AD</I></MATH>, and <MATH><I>BC</I>=1/2<I>GC</I></MATH>; | |
10043 therefore <MATH><I>MA</I>:<I>AD</I>=<I>GC</I>:<I>CK</I> | |
10044 =<I>FH</I>:<I>HK</I></MATH>, | |
10045 and, <I>componendo,</I> <MATH><I>MD</I>:<I>DA</I>=<I>FK</I>:<I>HK</I></MATH>. | |
10046 <p>But, by construction, <MATH><I>DA</I>=<I>HK</I></MATH>; | |
10047 therefore <MATH><I>MD</I>=<I>FK</I></MATH>, and <MATH><I>MD</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>FK</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
10048 <pb n=262><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
10049 <p>Now <MATH><I>MD</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BM.MA</I>+<I>DA</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
10050 while, by (1), <MATH><I>FK</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BK.KC</I>+<I>CF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>; | |
10051 therefore <MATH><I>BM.MA</I>+<I>DA</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BK.KC</I>+<I>CF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
10052 <p>But <MATH><I>DA</I>=<I>CF</I></MATH>; therefore <MATH><I>BM.MA</I>=<I>BK.KC</I></MATH>. | |
10053 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>CK</I>:<I>MA</I>=<I>BM</I>:<I>BK</I> | |
10054 =<I>LC</I>:<I>CK</I></MATH>; | |
10055 while, at the same time, <MATH><I>BM</I>:<I>BK</I>=<I>MA</I>:<I>AL</I></MATH>. | |
10056 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>LC</I>:<I>CK</I>=<I>CK</I>:<I>MA</I>=<I>MA</I>:<I>AL</I></MATH>, | |
10057 or <MATH><I>AB</I>:<I>CK</I>=<I>CK</I>:<I>MA</I>=<I>MA</I>:<I>BC</I></MATH>. | |
10058 <C>(<G>q</G>) <I>Apollonius, Heron, Philon of Byzantium.</I></C> | |
10059 <p>I give these solutions together because they really amount | |
10060 to the same thing.<note>Heron's solution is given in his <I>Mechanics</I> (i. 11) and <I>Belopoeica</I>, and is | |
10061 reproduced by Pappus (iii, pp. 62-4) as well as by Eutocius (loc. cit.).</note> | |
10062 <p>Let <I>AB, AC,</I> placed at right angles, be the two given straight | |
10063 <FIG> | |
10064 lines. Complete the rectangle <I>ABDC,</I> and let <I>E</I> be the point | |
10065 at which the diagonals bisect one another. | |
10066 <p>Then a circle with centre <I>E</I> and radius <I>EB</I> will circumscribe | |
10067 the rectangle <I>ABDC.</I> | |
10068 <p>Now (Apollonius) draw with centre <I>E</I> a circle cutting | |
10069 <I>AB, AC</I> produced in <I>F, G</I> but such that <I>F, D, G</I> are in one | |
10070 straight line. | |
10071 <p>Or (Heron) place a ruler so that its edge passes through <I>D,</I> | |
10072 <pb n=263><head>APOLLONIUS, HERON, PHILON OF BYZANTIUM</head> | |
10073 and move it about <I>D</I> until the edge intersects <I>AB, AC</I> pro- | |
10074 duced in points (<I>F, G</I>) which are equidistant from <I>E.</I> | |
10075 <p>Or (Philon) place a ruler so that it passes through <I>D</I> and | |
10076 turn it round <I>D</I> until it cuts <I>AB, AC</I> produced and the circle | |
10077 about <I>ABDC</I> in points <I>F, G, H</I> such that the intercepts <I>FD, | |
10078 HG</I> are equal. | |
10079 <p>Clearly all three constructions give the same points <I>F, G.</I> | |
10080 For in Philon's construction, since <MATH><I>FD</I>=<I>HG</I></MATH>, the perpendicular | |
10081 from <I>E</I> on <I>DH,</I> which bisects <I>DH,</I> must also bisect <I>FG,</I> so | |
10082 that <MATH><I>EF</I>=<I>EG</I></MATH>. | |
10083 <p>We have first to prove that <MATH><I>AF.FB</I>=<I>AG.GC</I></MATH>. | |
10084 <p>(<I>a</I>) With Apollonius's and Heron's constructions we have, if | |
10085 <I>K</I> be the middle point of <I>AB,</I> | |
10086 <MATH><I>AF.FB</I>+<I>BK</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>FK</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
10087 <p>Add <I>KE</I><SUP>2</SUP> to both sides; | |
10088 therefore <MATH><I>AF.FB</I>+<I>BE</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>EF</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
10089 <p>Similarly <MATH><I>AG.GC</I>+<I>CE</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>EG</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
10090 <p>But <MATH><I>BE</I>=<I>CE</I></MATH>, and <MATH><I>EF</I>=<I>EG</I></MATH>; | |
10091 therefore <MATH><I>AF.FB</I>=<I>AG.GC</I></MATH>. | |
10092 <p>(<I>b</I>) With Philon's construction, since <MATH><I>GH</I>=<I>FD</I></MATH>, | |
10093 <MATH><I>HF.FD</I>=<I>DG.GH</I></MATH>. | |
10094 <p>But, since the circle <I>BDHC</I> passes through <I>A,</I> | |
10095 <MATH><I>HF.FD</I>=<I>AF.FB</I></MATH>, and <MATH><I>DG.GH</I>=<I>AG.GC</I></MATH>; | |
10096 therefore <MATH><I>AF.FB</I>=<I>AG.GC</I></MATH>. | |
10097 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>FA</I>:<I>AG</I>=<I>CG</I>:<I>FB</I></MATH>. | |
10098 <p>But, by similar triangles, | |
10099 <MATH><I>FA</I>:<I>AG</I>=<I>DC</I>:<I>CG</I></MATH>, and also <MATH>=<I>FB</I>:<I>BD</I></MATH>; | |
10100 therefore <MATH><I>DC</I>:<I>CG</I>=<I>CG</I>:<I>FB</I>=<I>FB</I>:<I>BD</I></MATH>, | |
10101 or <MATH><I>AB</I>:<I>CG</I>=<I>CG</I>:<I>FB</I>=<I>FB</I>:<I>AC</I></MATH>. | |
10102 <p>The connexion between this solution and that of Menaech- | |
10103 mus can be seen thus. We saw that, if <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>x</I>=<I>x</I>:<I>y</I>=<I>y</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>, | |
10104 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>ay</I>, <I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>bx</I>, <I>xy</I>=<I>ab</I></MATH>, | |
10105 which equations represent, in Cartesian coordinates, two | |
10106 parabolas and a hyperbola. Menaechmus in effect solved the | |
10107 <pb n=264><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
10108 problem of the two mean proportionals by means of the points | |
10109 of intersection of any two of these conics. | |
10110 <p>But, if we add the first two equations, we have | |
10111 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>bx</I>-<I>ay</I>=0</MATH>, | |
10112 which is a circle passing through the points common to the | |
10113 two parabolas <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>ay</I>, <I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>bx</I></MATH>. | |
10114 <p>Therefore we can equally obtain a solution by means of | |
10115 the intersections of the circle <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>bx</I>-<I>ay</I>=0</MATH> and the | |
10116 rectangular hyperbola <MATH><I>xy</I>=<I>ab</I></MATH>. | |
10117 <p>This is in effect what Philon does, for, if <I>AF, AG</I> are the | |
10118 coordinate axes, the circle <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>bx</I>-<I>ay</I>=0</MATH> is the circle | |
10119 <I>BDHC,</I> and <MATH><I>xy</I>=<I>ab</I></MATH> is the rectangular hyperbola with | |
10120 <I>AF, AG</I> as asymptotes and passing through <I>D,</I> which | |
10121 hyperbola intersects the circle again in <I>H,</I> a point such | |
10122 that <MATH><I>FD</I>=<I>HG</I></MATH>. | |
10123 <C>(<G>i</G>) <I>Diocles and the cissoid.</I></C> | |
10124 <p>We gather from allusions to the cissoid in Proclus's com- | |
10125 mentary on Eucl. I that the curve which Geminus called by | |
10126 that name was none other than the curve invented by Diocles | |
10127 and used by him for doubling the cube or finding two mean | |
10128 proportionals. Hence Diocles must have preceded Geminus | |
10129 (fl. 70 B.C.). Again, we conclude from the two fragments | |
10130 preserved by Eutocius of a work by him, <G>pepi\ purei/wn</G>, <I>On | |
10131 burning-mirrors,</I> that he was later than Archimedes and | |
10132 Apollonius. He may therefore have flourished towards the | |
10133 end of the second century or at the beginning of the first | |
10134 century B.C. Of the two fragments given by Eutocius one | |
10135 contains a solution by means of conics of the problem of | |
10136 dividing a sphere by a plane in such a way that the volumes | |
10137 of the resulting segments shall be in a given ratio—a problem | |
10138 equivalent to the solution of a certain cubic equation—while | |
10139 the other gives the solution of the problem of the two mean | |
10140 proportionals by means of the cissoid. | |
10141 <p>Suppose that <I>AB, DC</I> are diameters of a circle at right | |
10142 angles to one another. Let <I>E, F</I> be points on the quadrants | |
10143 <I>BD, BC</I> respectively such that the arcs <I>BE, BF</I> are equal. | |
10144 <p>Draw <I>EG, FH</I> perpendicular to <I>DC.</I> Join <I>CE,</I> and let <I>P</I> be | |
10145 the point in which <I>CE, FH</I> intersect. | |
10146 <pb n=265><head>DIOCLES AND THE CISSOID</head> | |
10147 <p>The cissoid is the locus of all the points <I>P</I> corresponding to | |
10148 different positions of <I>E</I> on the quadrant <I>BD</I> and of <I>F</I> at an | |
10149 equal distance from <I>B</I> on the quadrant <I>BC.</I> | |
10150 <p>If <I>P</I> is any point found by the above construction, it is | |
10151 <FIG> | |
10152 required to prove that <I>FH, HC</I> are two mean proportionals in | |
10153 continued proportion between <I>DH</I> and <I>HP,</I> or that | |
10154 <MATH><I>DH</I>:<I>HF</I>=<I>HF</I>:<I>HC</I>=<I>HC</I>:<I>HP</I></MATH>. | |
10155 <p>Now it is clear from the construction that <MATH><I>EG</I>=<I>FH</I>, | |
10156 <I>DG</I>=<I>HC</I></MATH>, so that <MATH><I>CG</I>:<I>GE</I>&equals3;<I>DH</I>:<I>HF</I></MATH>. | |
10157 <p>And, since <I>FH</I> is a mean proportional between <I>DH, HC,</I> | |
10158 <MATH><I>DH</I>:<I>HF</I>=<I>HF</I>:<I>CH</I></MATH>. | |
10159 <p>But, by similar triangles, | |
10160 <MATH><I>CG</I>:<I>GE</I>=<I>CH</I>:<I>HP</I></MATH>. | |
10161 <p>It follows that | |
10162 <MATH><I>DH</I>:<I>HF</I>=<I>HF</I>:<I>CH</I>=<I>CH</I>:<I>HP</I></MATH>, | |
10163 or <I>FH, HC</I> are the two mean proportionals between <I>DH, HP.</I> | |
10164 <p>[Since <MATH><I>DH.HP</I>=<I>HF.CH</I></MATH>, we have, if <I>a</I> is the radius of | |
10165 the circle and if <MATH><I>OH</I>=<I>x</I>, <I>HP</I>=<I>y</I></MATH>, or (in other words) if we | |
10166 use <I>OC, OB</I> as axes of coordinates, | |
10167 <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>)<I>y</I>=√(<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>).(<I>a</I>-<I>x</I>)</MATH> | |
10168 or <MATH><I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>(<I>a</I>+<I>x</I>)=(<I>a</I>-<I>x</I>)<SUP>3</SUP></MATH>, | |
10169 which is the Cartesian equation of the curve. It has a cusp | |
10170 at <I>C,</I> and the tangent to the circle at <I>D</I> is an asymptote to it.] | |
10171 <pb n=266><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
10172 <p>Suppose now that the cissoid has been drawn as shown by | |
10173 the dotted line in the figure, and that we are required to find | |
10174 two mean proportionals between two straight lines <I>a, b.</I> | |
10175 <p>Take the point <I>K</I> on <I>OB</I> such that <MATH><I>DO</I>:<I>OK</I>=<I>a</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>. | |
10176 <p>Join <I>DK,</I> and produce it to meet the cissoid in <I>Q.</I> | |
10177 <p>Through <I>Q</I> draw the ordinate <I>LM</I> perpendicular to <I>DC.</I> | |
10178 <p>Then, by the property of the cissoid, <I>LM, MC</I> are the two | |
10179 mean proportionals between <I>DM, MQ.</I> And | |
10180 <MATH><I>DM</I>:<I>MQ</I>=<I>DO</I>:<I>OK</I>=<I>a</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>. | |
10181 <p>In order, then, to obtain the two mean proportionals between | |
10182 <I>a</I> and <I>b,</I> we have only to take straight lines which bear respec- | |
10183 tively the same ratio to <I>DM, LM, MC, MQ</I> as <I>a</I> bears to <I>DM.</I> | |
10184 The extremes are then <I>a, b,</I> and the two mean proportionals | |
10185 are found. | |
10186 <C>(<G>k</G>) <I>Sporus and Pappus.</I></C> | |
10187 <p>The solutions of Sporus and Pappus are really the same as | |
10188 that of Diocles, the only difference being that, instead of using | |
10189 the cissoid, they use a ruler which they turn about a certain | |
10190 point until certain intercepts which it cuts off between two | |
10191 pairs of lines are equal. | |
10192 <p>In order to show the identity of the solutions, I shall draw | |
10193 Sporus's figure with the same lettering as above for corre- | |
10194 sponding points, and I shall add dotted lines to show the | |
10195 additional auxiliary lines used by Pappus.<note>Pappus, iii, pp. 64-8; viii, pp. 1070-2.</note> (Compared with | |
10196 my figure, Sporus's is the other way up, and so is Pappus's | |
10197 where it occurs in his own <I>Synagoge,</I> though not in Eutocius.) | |
10198 <p>Sporus was known to Pappus, as we have gathered from | |
10199 Pappus's reference to his criticisms on the <I>quadratrix,</I> and | |
10200 it is not unlikely that Sporus was either Pappus's master or | |
10201 a fellow-student of his. But when Pappus gives (though in | |
10202 better form, if we may judge by Eutocius's reproduction of | |
10203 Sporus) the same solution as that of Sporus, and calls it | |
10204 a solution <G>kaq) h(ma=s</G>, he clearly means ‘according to my | |
10205 method’, not ‘<I>our</I> method’, and it appears therefore that he | |
10206 claimed the credit of it for himself. | |
10207 <p>Sporus makes <I>DO, OK</I> (at right angles to one another) the | |
10208 actual given straight lines; Pappus, like Diocles, only takes | |
10209 <pb n=267><head>SPORUS AND PAPPUS</head> | |
10210 them in the same proportion as the given straight lines. | |
10211 Otherwise the construction is the same. | |
10212 <p>A circle being drawn with centre <I>O</I> and radius <I>DO,</I> we join | |
10213 <I>DK</I> and produce it to meet the circle in <I>I.</I> | |
10214 <p>Now conceive a ruler to pass through <I>C</I> and to be turned | |
10215 about <I>C</I> until it cuts <I>DI, OB</I> and the circumference of the | |
10216 <FIG> | |
10217 circle in points <I>Q, T, R</I> such that <MATH><I>QT</I>=<I>TR</I></MATH>. Draw <I>QM, RN</I> | |
10218 perpendicular to <I>DC.</I> | |
10219 <p>Then, since <MATH><I>QT</I>=<I>TR</I>, <I>MO</I>=<I>ON</I></MATH>, and <I>MQ, NR</I> are equi- | |
10220 distant from <I>OB.</I> Therefore in reality <I>Q</I> lies on the cissoid of | |
10221 Diocles, and, as in the first part of Diocles's proof, we prove | |
10222 (since <I>RN</I> is equal to the ordinate through <I>Q,</I> the foot of | |
10223 which is <I>M</I>) that | |
10224 <MATH><I>DM</I>:<I>RN</I>=<I>RN</I>:<I>MC</I>=<I>MC</I>:<I>MQ</I></MATH>, | |
10225 and we have the two means between <I>DM, MQ,</I> so that we can | |
10226 easily construct the two means between <I>DO, OK.</I> | |
10227 <p>But Sporus actually proves that the first of the two means | |
10228 between <I>DO</I> and <I>OK</I> is <I>OT.</I> This is obvious from the above | |
10229 relations, because | |
10230 <MATH><I>RN</I>:<I>OT</I>=<I>CN</I>:<I>CO</I>=<I>DM</I>:<I>DO</I>=<I>MQ</I>:<I>OK</I></MATH>. | |
10231 <p>Sporus has an <I>ab initio</I> proof of the fact, but it is rather | |
10232 confused, and Pappus's proof is better worth giving, especially | |
10233 as it includes the actual duplication of the cube. | |
10234 <p>It is required to prove that <MATH><I>DO</I>:<I>OK</I>=<I>DO</I><SUP>3</SUP>:<I>OT</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH>. | |
10235 <pb n=268><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
10236 <p>Join <I>RO,</I> and produce it to meet the circle at <I>S.</I> Join | |
10237 <I>DS, SC.</I> | |
10238 <p>Then, since <MATH><I>RO</I>=<I>OS</I></MATH> and <MATH><I>RT</I>=<I>TQ</I></MATH>, <I>SQ</I> is parallel to <I>AB</I> | |
10239 and meets <I>OC</I> in <I>M.</I> | |
10240 <p>Now | |
10241 <MATH><I>DM</I>:<I>MC</I>=<I>SM</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>MC</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>CM</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>MQ</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> (since ∠<I>RCS</I> is right). | |
10242 <p>Multiply by the ratio <I>CM</I>:<I>MQ</I>; | |
10243 therefore <MATH>(<I>DM</I>:<I>MC</I>).(<I>CM</I>:<I>MQ</I>)=(<I>CM</I><SUP>2</SUP>:<I>MQ</I><SUP>2</SUP>).(<I>CM</I>:<I>MQ</I>)</MATH> | |
10244 or <MATH><I>DM</I>:<I>MQ</I>=<I>CM</I><SUP>3</SUP>:<I>MQ</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH>. | |
10245 <p>But <MATH><I>DM</I>:<I>MQ</I>=<I>DO</I>:<I>OK</I></MATH>, | |
10246 and <MATH><I>CM</I>:<I>MQ</I>=<I>CO</I>:<I>OT</I></MATH>. | |
10247 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>DO</I>:<I>OK</I>=<I>CO</I><SUP>3</SUP>:<I>OT</I><SUP>3</SUP>=<I>DO</I><SUP>3</SUP>:<I>OT</I><SUP>3</SUP></MATH>. | |
10248 <p>Therefore <I>OT</I> is the first of the two mean proportionals to | |
10249 <I>DO, OK</I>; the second is found by taking a third proportional | |
10250 to <I>DO, OT.</I> | |
10251 <p>And a cube has been increased in any given ratio. | |
10252 <C>(<G>l</G>) <I>Approximation to a solution by plane methods only.</I></C> | |
10253 <p>There remains the procedure described by Pappus and | |
10254 criticized by him at length at the beginning of Book III of | |
10255 his <I>Collection.</I><note>Pappus, iii, pp. 30-48.</note> It was suggested by some one ‘who was | |
10256 thought to be a great geometer’, but whose name is not given. | |
10257 Pappus maintains that the author did not understand what | |
10258 he was about, ‘for he claimed that he was in possession of | |
10259 a method of finding two mean proportionals between two | |
10260 straight lines by means of plane considerations only’; he | |
10261 gave his construction to Pappus to examine and pronounce | |
10262 upon, while Hierius the philosopher and other friends of his | |
10263 supported his request for Pappus's opinion. The construction | |
10264 is as follows. | |
10265 <p>Let the given straight lines be <I>AB, AD</I> placed at right | |
10266 angles to one another, <I>AB</I> being the greater. | |
10267 <p>Draw <I>BC</I> parallel to <I>AD</I> and equal to <I>AB.</I> Join <I>CD</I> meeting | |
10268 <I>BA</I> produced in <I>E.</I> Produce <I>BC</I> to <I>L,</I> and draw <I>EL</I>′ through | |
10269 <I>E</I> parallel to <I>BL.</I> Along <I>CL</I> cut off lengths <I>CF, FG, GK, KL,</I> | |
10270 <pb n=269><head>APPROXIMATION BY PLANE METHODS</head> | |
10271 each of which is equal to <I>BC.</I> Draw <I>CC</I>′, <I>FF</I>′, <I>GG</I>′, <I>KK</I>′, <I>LL</I>′ | |
10272 parallel to <I>BA.</I> | |
10273 <p>On <I>LL</I>′, <I>KK</I>′ take <I>LM, KR</I> equal to <I>BA,</I> and bisect <I>LM</I> | |
10274 in <I>N.</I> | |
10275 <p>Take <I>P, Q</I> on <I>LL</I>′ such that <I>L</I>′<I>L</I>, <I>L</I>′<I>N</I>, <I>L</I>′<I>P</I>, <I>L</I>′<I>Q</I> are in con- | |
10276 <FIG> | |
10277 tinued proportion; join <I>QR, RL,</I> and through <I>N</I> draw <I>NS</I> | |
10278 parallel to <I>QR</I> meeting <I>RL</I> in <I>S.</I> | |
10279 <p>Draw <I>ST</I> parallel to <I>BL</I> meeting <I>GG</I>′ in <I>T.</I> | |
10280 <p>To <I>G</I>′<I>G</I>, <I>G</I>′<I>T</I> take continued proportionals <I>G</I>′<I>O</I>, <I>G</I>′<I>U,</I> as before. | |
10281 Take <I>W</I> on <I>FF</I>′ such that <MATH><I>FW</I>=<I>BA</I></MATH>, join <I>UW, WG,</I> and | |
10282 through <I>T</I> draw <I>TI</I> parallel to <I>UW</I> meeting <I>WG</I> in <I>I.</I> | |
10283 <p>Through <I>I</I> draw <I>IV</I> parallel to <I>BC</I> meeting <I>CC</I>′ in <I>V.</I> | |
10284 <p>Take continued proportionals <I>C</I>′<I>C</I>, <I>C</I>′<I>V</I>, <I>C</I>′<I>X</I>, <I>C</I>′<I>Y,</I> and draw | |
10285 <I>XZ, VZ</I>′ parallel to <I>YD</I> meeting <I>EC</I> in <I>Z, Z</I>′. Lastly draw | |
10286 <I>ZX</I>′, <I>Z</I>′<I>Y</I>′ parallel to <I>BC.</I> | |
10287 <p>Then, says the author, it is required to prove that <I>ZX</I>′, <I>Z</I>′<I>Y</I>′ | |
10288 are two mean proportionals in continued proportion between | |
10289 <I>AD, BC.</I> | |
10290 <p>Now, as Pappus noticed, the supposed conclusion is clearly | |
10291 not true unless <I>DY</I> is parallel to <I>BC,</I> which in general it is not. | |
10292 But what Pappus failed to observe is that, if the operation of | |
10293 taking the continued proportionals as described is repeated, | |
10294 not three times, but an infinite number of times, the length of | |
10295 the line <I>C</I>′<I>Y</I> tends continually towards equality with <I>EA.</I> | |
10296 Although, therefore, by continuing the construction we can | |
10297 never exactly determine the required means, the method gives | |
10298 an endless series of approximations tending towards the true | |
10299 lengths of the means. | |
10300 <pb n=270><head>THE DUPLICATION OF THE CUBE</head> | |
10301 <p>Let <MATH><I>LL</I>′=<I>BE</I>=<I>a</I>, <I>AB</I>=<I>b</I>, <I>L</I>′<I>N</I>=<G>a</G></MATH> (for there is no | |
10302 necessity to take <I>N</I> at the middle point of <I>LM</I>). | |
10303 <p>Then <MATH><I>L</I>′<I>Q</I>=<G>a</G><SUP>3</SUP>/<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
10304 therefore <MATH><I>LQ</I>=(<I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>-<G>a</G><SUP>3</SUP>)/<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
10305 <p>And <MATH><I>TG/RK</I>=<I>SL/RL</I>=<I>NL/QL</I>=((<I>a</I>-<G>a</G>)<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>)/(<I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>-<G>a</G><SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>; | |
10306 therefore <MATH><I>TG</I>=((<I>a</I>-<G>a</G>)<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b</I>)/(<I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>-<G>a</G><SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>, | |
10307 and accordingly <MATH><I>G</I>′<I>T</I>=<I>a</I>-((<I>a</I>-<G>a</G>)<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b</I>)/(<I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>-<G>a</G><SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>. | |
10308 <p>Now let <G>a</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB> be the length corresponding to <I>G</I>′<I>T</I> after <I>n</I> | |
10309 operations; then it is clear that | |
10310 <MATH><I>a</I>-<G>a</G><SUB><I>n</I>+1</SUB>=(<I>a</I>-<G>a</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>)<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b</I>/(<I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>-<G>a</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB><SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>. | |
10311 <p><G>a</G><SUB><I>n</I></SUB> must approach some finite limit when <MATH><I>n</I>=<*></MATH>. Taking <G>x</G> | |
10312 as this limit, we have | |
10313 <MATH><I>a</I>-<G>x</G>=(<I>a</I>-<G>x</G>)<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b</I>/(<I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>-<G>x</G><SUP>3</SUP>)</MATH>, | |
10314 and, <MATH><G>x</G>=<I>a</I></MATH> not being a root of this equation, we get at once | |
10315 <MATH><G>x</G><SUP>3</SUP>=<I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>-<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b</I>=<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)</MATH>. | |
10316 Therefore, ultimately <I>C</I>′<I>V</I> is one of the mean proportionals | |
10317 between <I>EA</I> and <I>EB,</I> whence <I>Y</I>′<I>Z</I>′ will be one of the mean | |
10318 proportionals between <I>AD, BC,</I> that is, between <I>AD</I> and <I>AB.</I> | |
10319 <p>The above was pointed out for the first time by R. Pendle- | |
10320 bury,<note><I>Messenger of Mathematics,</I> ser. 2, vol. ii (1873), pp. 166-8.</note> and I have followed his way of stating the matter. | |
10321 <pb> | |
10322 <C>VIII | |
10323 ZENO OF ELEA</C> | |
10324 <p>WE have already seen how the consideration of the subject | |
10325 of infinitesimals was forced upon the Greek mathematicians so | |
10326 soon as they came to close grips with the problem of the | |
10327 quadrature of the circle. Antiphon the Sophist was the first | |
10328 to indicate the correct road upon which the solution was to | |
10329 be found, though he expressed his idea in a crude form which | |
10330 was bound to provoke immediate and strong criticism from | |
10331 logical minds. Antiphon had inscribed a series of successive | |
10332 regular polygons in a circle, each of which had double as | |
10333 many sides as the preceding, and he asserted that, by con- | |
10334 tinuing this process, we should at length exhaust the circle: | |
10335 ‘he thought that in this way the area of the circle would | |
10336 sometime be used up and a polygon would be inscribed in the | |
10337 circle the sides of which on account of their smallness would | |
10338 coincide with the circumference.’<note>Simpl. <I>in Arist. Phys.</I>, p. 55. 6 Diels.</note> Aristotle roundly said that | |
10339 this was a fallacy which it was not even necessary for a | |
10340 geometer to trouble to refute, since an expert in any science | |
10341 is not called upon to refute <I>all</I> fallacies, but only those which | |
10342 are false deductions from the admitted principles of the | |
10343 science; if the fallacy is based on anything which is in con- | |
10344 tradiction to any of those principles, it may at once be ignored.<note>Arist. <I>Phys.</I> i. 2, 185 a 14-17.</note> | |
10345 Evidently therefore, in Aristotle's view, Antiphon's argument | |
10346 violated some ‘geometrical principle’, whether this was the | |
10347 truth that a straight line, however short, can never coincide | |
10348 with an arc of a circle, or the principle assumed by geometers | |
10349 that geometrical magnitudes can be divided <I>ad infinitum.</I> | |
10350 <p>But Aristotle is only a representative of the criticisms | |
10351 directed against the ideas implied in Antiphon's argument; | |
10352 those ideas had already, as early as the time of Antiphon | |
10353 <pb n=272><head>ZENO OF ELEA</head> | |
10354 himself (a contemporary of Socrates), been subjected to a | |
10355 destructive criticism expressed with unsurpassable piquancy | |
10356 and force. No wonder that the subsequent course of Greek | |
10357 geometry was profoundly affected by the arguments of Zeno | |
10358 on motion. Aristotle indeed called them ‘fallacies’, without | |
10359 being able to refute them. The mathematicians, however, knew | |
10360 better, and, realizing that Zeno's arguments were fatal to | |
10361 infinitesimals, they saw that they could only avoid the diffi- | |
10362 culties connected with them by once for all banishing the idea | |
10363 of the infinite, even the potentially infinite, altogether from | |
10364 their science; thenceforth, therefore, they made no use of | |
10365 magnitudes increasing or diminishing <I>ad infinitum</I>, but con- | |
10366 tented themselves with finite magnitudes that can be made as | |
10367 great or as small <I>as we please.</I><note>Cf. Arist. <I>Phys.</I> iii. 7, 207 b 31.</note> If they used infinitesimals | |
10368 at all, it was only as a tentative means of <I>discovering</I> proposi- | |
10369 tions; they <I>proved</I> them afterwards by rigorous geometrical | |
10370 methods. An illustration of this is furnished by the <I>Method</I> of | |
10371 Archimedes. In that treatise Archimedes finds (<I>a</I>) the areas | |
10372 of curves, and (<I>b</I>) the volumes of solids, by treating them | |
10373 respectively as the sums of an infinite number (<I>a</I>) of parallel | |
10374 <I>lines</I>, i.e. infinitely narrow strips, and (<I>b</I>) of parallel <I>planes</I>, | |
10375 i.e. infinitely thin laminae; but he plainly declares that this | |
10376 method is only useful for discovering results and does not | |
10377 furnish a proof of them, but that to establish them scientific- | |
10378 ally a geometrical proof by the method of exhaustion, with | |
10379 its double <I>reductio ad absurdum</I>, is still necessary. | |
10380 <p>Notwithstanding that the criticisms of Zeno had so impor- | |
10381 tant an influence upon the lines of development of Greek | |
10382 geometry, it does not appear that Zeno himself was really | |
10383 a mathematician or even a physicist. Plato mentions a work | |
10384 of his (<G>ta\ tou= *zh/nwnos gra/mmata</G>, or <G>to\ su/ggramma</G>) in terms | |
10385 which imply that it was his only known work.<note>Plato, <I>Parmenides</I>, 127 c sq.</note> Simplicius | |
10386 too knows only one work of his, and this the same as that | |
10387 mentioned by Plato<note>Simpl. <I>in Phys.</I>, pp. 139. 5, 140. 27 Diels.</note>; when Suidas mentions four, a <I>Commen- | |
10388 tary on</I> or <I>Exposition of Empedocles, Controversies, Against | |
10389 the philosophers</I> and <I>On Nature</I>, it may be that the last three | |
10390 titles are only different designations for the one work, while | |
10391 the book on Empedocles may have been wrongly attributed | |
10392 <pb n=273><head>ZENO OF ELEA</head> | |
10393 to Zeno.<note>Zeller, i<SUP>5</SUP>, p. 587 note.</note> Plato puts into the mouth of Zeno himself an | |
10394 explanation of the character and object of his book.<note>Plato, <I>Parmenides</I> 128 C-E.</note> It was | |
10395 a youthful effort, and it was stolen by some one, so that the | |
10396 author had no opportunity of considering whether to publish | |
10397 it or not. Its object was to defend the system of Parmenides | |
10398 by attacking the common conceptions of things. Parmenides | |
10399 held that only the One exists; whereupon common sense | |
10400 pointed out that many contradictions and absurdities will | |
10401 follow if this be admitted. Zeno replied that, if the popular | |
10402 view that Many exist be accepted, still more absurd results | |
10403 will follow. The work was divided into several parts (<G>lo/goi</G> | |
10404 according to Plato) and each of these again into sections | |
10405 (‘hypotheses’ in Plato, ‘contentions’, <G>e)pixeirh/mata</G>, in Sim- | |
10406 plicius): each of the latter (which according to Proclus | |
10407 numbered forty in all<note>Proclus <I>in Parm.</I>, p. 694. 23 seq.</note>) seems to have taken one of the | |
10408 assumptions made on the ordinary view of life and to have | |
10409 shown that it leads to an absurdity. It is doubtless on | |
10410 account of this systematic use of indirect proof by the <I>reductio | |
10411 ad absurdum</I> of particular hypotheses that Zeno is said to | |
10412 have been called by Aristotle the discoverer of Dialectic<note>Diog. L. viii. 57, ix. 25; Sext. Emp. <I>Math.</I> vii. 6.</note>; | |
10413 Plato, too, says of him that he understood how to make one | |
10414 and the same thing appear like and unlike, one and many, at | |
10415 rest and in motion.<note>Plato, <I>Phaedrus</I> 261 D.</note> | |
10416 <C>Zeno's arguments about motion.</C> | |
10417 <p>It does not appear that the full significance and value of | |
10418 Zeno's paradoxes have ever been realized until these latter | |
10419 days. The most modern view of them shall be expressed in | |
10420 the writer's own words: | |
10421 <p>‘In this capricious world nothing is more capricious than | |
10422 posthumous fame. One of the most notable victims of pos- | |
10423 terity's lack of judgement is the Eleatic Zeno. Having | |
10424 invented four arguments all immeasurably subtle and pro- | |
10425 found, the grossness of subsequent philosophers pronounced | |
10426 him to be a mere ingenious juggler, and his arguments to be | |
10427 <pb n=274><head>ZENO OF ELEA</head> | |
10428 one and all sophisms. After two thousand years of continual | |
10429 refutation, these sophisms were reinstated, and made the | |
10430 foundation of a mathematical renaissance, by a German | |
10431 professor who probably never dreamed of any connexion | |
10432 between himself and Zeno. Weierstrass, by strictly banishing | |
10433 all infinitesimals, has at last shown that we live in an | |
10434 unchanging world, and that the arrow, at every moment of its | |
10435 flight, is truly at rest. The only point where Zeno probably | |
10436 erred was in inferring (if he did infer) that, because there | |
10437 is no change, the world must be in the same state at one time | |
10438 as at another. This consequence by no means follows, and in | |
10439 this point the German professor is more constructive than the | |
10440 ingenious Greek. Weierstrass, being able to embody his | |
10441 opinions in mathematics, where familiarity with truth elimi- | |
10442 nates the vulgar prejudices of common sense, has been able to | |
10443 give to his propositions the respectable air of platitudes; and | |
10444 if the result is less delightful to the lover of reason than Zeno's | |
10445 bold defiance, it is at any rate more calculated to appease the | |
10446 mass of academic mankind.’<note>Bertrand Russell, <I>The Principles of Mathematics</I>, vol. i, 1903, pp. | |
10447 347, 348.</note> | |
10448 <p>Thus, while in the past the arguments of Zeno have been | |
10449 treated with more or less disrespect as mere sophisms, we have | |
10450 now come to the other extreme. It appears to be implied that | |
10451 Zeno anticipated Weierstrass. This, I think, a calmer judge- | |
10452 ment must pronounce to be incredible. If the arguments of | |
10453 Zeno are found to be ‘immeasurably subtle and profound’ | |
10454 because they contain ideas which Weierstrass used to create | |
10455 a great mathematical theory, it does not follow that for Zeno | |
10456 they meant at all the same thing as for Weierstrass. On the | |
10457 contrary, it is probable that Zeno happened upon these ideas | |
10458 without realizing any of the significance which Weierstrass | |
10459 was destined to give them; nor shall we give Zeno any less | |
10460 credit on this account. | |
10461 <p>It is time to come to the arguments themselves. It is the | |
10462 four arguments on the subject of motion which are most | |
10463 important from the point of view of the mathematician; but | |
10464 they have points of contact with the arguments which Zeno | |
10465 used to prove the non-existence of Many, in refutation of | |
10466 those who attacked Parmenides's doctrine of the One. Accord- | |
10467 ing to Simplicius, he showed that, if Many exist, they must | |
10468 <pb n=275><head>ZENO'S ARGUMENTS ABOUT MOTION</head> | |
10469 be both great and small, so great on the one hand as to be | |
10470 infinite in size and so small on the other as to have no size.<note>Simpl. <I>in Phys.</I>, p. 139. 5, Diels.</note> | |
10471 To prove the latter of these contentions, Zeno relied on the | |
10472 infinite divisibility of bodies as evident; assuming this, he | |
10473 easily proved that division will continually give smaller and | |
10474 smaller parts, there will be no limit to the diminution, and, if | |
10475 there is a final element, it must be absolutely <I>nothing.</I> Conse- | |
10476 quently to add any number of these <I>nil</I>-elements to anything | |
10477 will not increase its size, nor will the subtraction of them | |
10478 diminish it; and of course to add them to one another, even | |
10479 in infinite number, will give <I>nothing</I> as the total. (The | |
10480 second horn of the dilemma, not apparently stated by Zeno | |
10481 in this form, would be this. A critic might argue that infinite | |
10482 division would only lead to parts having <I>some</I> size, so that the | |
10483 last element would itself have some size; to this the answer | |
10484 would be that, as there would, by hypothesis, be an infinite | |
10485 number of such parts, the original magnitude which was | |
10486 divided would be infinite in size.) The connexion between | |
10487 the arguments against the Many and those against motion | |
10488 lies in the fact that the former rest on the assumption of | |
10489 the divisibility of matter <I>ad infinitum</I>, and that this is the | |
10490 hypothesis assumed in the first two arguments against motion. | |
10491 We shall see that, while the first two arguments proceed on | |
10492 this hypothesis, the last two appear to proceed on the opposite | |
10493 hypothesis that space and time are not infinitely divisible, but | |
10494 that they are composed of <I>indivisible</I> elements; so that the | |
10495 four arguments form a complete dilemma. | |
10496 <p>The four arguments against motion shall be stated in the | |
10497 words of Aristotle. | |
10498 <p>I. The <I>Dichotomy.</I> | |
10499 <p>‘There is no motion because that which is moved must | |
10500 arrive at the middle (of its course) before it arrives at the | |
10501 end.’<note>Aristotle, <I>Phys.</I> vi. 9, 239 b 11.</note> (And of course it must traverse the half of the half | |
10502 before it reaches the middle, and so on <I>ad infinitum.</I>) | |
10503 <p>II. The <I>Achilles.</I> | |
10504 <p>‘This asserts that the slower when running will never be | |
10505 <pb n=276><head>ZENO OF ELEA</head> | |
10506 overtaken by the quicker; for that which is pursuing must | |
10507 first reach the point from which that which is fleeing started, | |
10508 so that the slower must necessarily always be some distance | |
10509 ahead.’<note>Aristotle, <I>Phys.</I> vi. 9, 239 b 14.</note> | |
10510 <p>III. The <I>Arrow.</I> | |
10511 <p>‘If, says Zeno, everything is either at rest or moving when | |
10512 it occupies a space equal (to itself), while the object moved is | |
10513 always in the instant (<G>e)/sti d) a)ei\ to\ fero/menon e)n tw=| nu=n</G>, in | |
10514 the <I>now</I>), the moving arrow is unmoved.’<note><I>Ib.</I> 239 b 5-7.</note> | |
10515 <p>I agree in Brochard's interpretation of this passage,<note>V. &Bdot;rochard, <I>Études de Philosophie ancienne et de Philosophie moderne</I>, | |
10516 Paris 1912, p. 6.</note> from | |
10517 which Zeller<note>Zeller, i<SUP>5</SUP>, p. 599.</note> would banish <G>h)\ kinei=tai</G>, ‘or is moved’. The | |
10518 argument is this. It is strictly impossible that the arrow can | |
10519 move in the <I>instant</I>, supposed indivisible, for, if it changed its | |
10520 position, the instant would be at once divided. Now the | |
10521 moving object is, in the instant, either at rest or in motion; | |
10522 but, as it is not in motion, it is at rest, and as, by hypothesis, | |
10523 time is composed of nothing but instants, the moving object is | |
10524 always at rest. This interpretation has the advantage of | |
10525 agreeing with that of Simplicius,<note>Simpl. <I>in Phys.</I>, pp. 1011-12, Diels.</note> which seems preferable | |
10526 to that of Themistius<note>Them. (<I>ad loc.</I>, p. 392 Sp., p. 199 Sch.)</note> on which Zeller relies. | |
10527 <p>IV. The <I>Stadium.</I> I translate the first two sentences of | |
10528 Aristotle's account<note><I>Phys.</I> vi, 9, 239 b 33-240 a 18.</note>: | |
10529 <p>‘The fourth is the argument concerning the two rows of | |
10530 bodies each composed of an equal number of bodies of equal | |
10531 size, which pass one another on a race-course as they proceed | |
10532 with equal velocity in opposite directions, one row starting | |
10533 from the end of the course and the other from the middle. | |
10534 This, he thinks, involves the conclusion that half a given time | |
10535 is equal to its double. The fallacy of the reasoning lies in | |
10536 the assumption that an equal magnitude occupies an equal | |
10537 time in passing with equal velocity a magnitude that is in | |
10538 motion and a magnitude that is at rest, an assumption which | |
10539 is false.’ | |
10540 <p>Then follows a description of the process by means of | |
10541 <pb n=277><head>ZENO'S ARGUMENTS ABOUT MOTION</head> | |
10542 letters <I>A, B, C</I> the <I>exact</I> interpretation of which is a matter | |
10543 of some doubt<note>The interpretation of the passage 240 a 4-18 is elaborately discussed | |
10544 by R. K. Gaye in the <I>Journal of Philology</I>, xxxi, 1910, pp. 95-116. It is | |
10545 a question whether in the above quotation Aristotle means that Zeno | |
10546 argued that half the given time would be equal to double the half, i. e. | |
10547 the whole time simply, or to double the whole, i.e. <I>four</I> times the half. | |
10548 Gaye contends (unconvincingly, I think) for the latter.</note>; the essence of it, however, is clear. The first | |
10549 diagram below shows the original positions of the rows of | |
10550 <FIG> | |
10551 bodies (say eight in number). The <I>A</I>'s represent a row which | |
10552 is stationary, the <I>B</I>'s and <I>C</I>'s are rows which move with equal | |
10553 velocity alongside the <I>A</I>'s and one another, in the directions | |
10554 shown by the arrows. Then clearly there will be (1) a moment | |
10555 <FIG> | |
10556 when the <I>B</I>'s and <I>C</I>'s will be exactly under the respective <I>A</I>'s, | |
10557 as in the second diagram, and after that (2) a moment when | |
10558 the <I>B</I>'s and <I>C</I>'s will have exactly reversed their positions | |
10559 relatively to the <I>A</I>'s, as in the third figure. | |
10560 <FIG> | |
10561 <p>The observation has been made<note>Brochard, <I>loc. cit.</I>, pp. 4, 5.</note> that the four arguments | |
10562 form a system curiously symmetrical. The first and fourth | |
10563 consider the continuous and movement within given limits, | |
10564 the second and third the continuous and movement over | |
10565 <pb n=278><head>ZENO OF ELEA</head> | |
10566 lengths which are indeterminate. In the first and third there | |
10567 is only one moving object, and it is shown that it cannot even | |
10568 begin to move. The second and fourth, comparing the motions | |
10569 of two objects, make the absurdity of the hypothesis even | |
10570 more palpable, so to speak, for they prove that the movement, | |
10571 even if it has once begun, cannot continue, and that relative | |
10572 motion is no less impossible than absolute motion. The first | |
10573 two establish the impossibility of movement by the nature of | |
10574 space, supposed continuous, without any implication that time | |
10575 is otherwise than continuous in the same way as space; in the | |
10576 last two it is the nature of time (considered as made up of | |
10577 indivisible elements or instants) which serves to prove the | |
10578 impossibility of movement, and without any implication that | |
10579 space is not likewise made up of indivisible elements or points. | |
10580 The second argument is only another form of the first, and | |
10581 the fourth rests on the same principle as the third. Lastly, the | |
10582 first pair proceed on the hypothesis that continuous magni- | |
10583 tudes are divisible <I>ad infinitum</I>; the second pair give the | |
10584 other horn of the dilemma, being directed against the assump- | |
10585 tion that continuous magnitudes are made up of <I>indivisible</I> | |
10586 elements, an assumption which would scarcely suggest itself | |
10587 to the imagination until the difficulties connected with the | |
10588 other were fully realized. Thus the logical order of the argu- | |
10589 ments corresponds exactly to the historical order in which | |
10590 Aristotle has handed them down and which was certainly the | |
10591 order adopted by Zeno. | |
10592 <p>Whether or not the paradoxes had for Zeno the profound | |
10593 meaning now claimed for them, it is clear that they have | |
10594 been very generally misunderstood, with the result that the | |
10595 criticisms directed against them have been wide of the mark. | |
10596 Aristotle, it is true, saw that the first two arguments, the | |
10597 <I>Dichotomy</I> and the <I>Achilles</I>, come to the same thing, the latter | |
10598 differing from the former only in the fact that the ratio of | |
10599 each space traversed by Achilles to the preceding space is not | |
10600 that of 1 : 2 but a ratio of 1 : <I>n</I>, where <I>n</I> may be any number, | |
10601 however large; but, he says, both proofs rest on the fact that | |
10602 a certain moving object ‘cannot reach the end of the course if | |
10603 the magnitude is divided in a certain way’.<note>Arist. <I>Phys.</I> vi. 9, 239 b 18-24.</note> But another | |
10604 passage shows that he mistook the character of the argument | |
10605 <pb n=279><head>ZENO'S ARGUMENTS ABOUT MOTION</head> | |
10606 in the <I>Dichotomy.</I> He observes that time is divisible in | |
10607 exactly the same way as a length; if therefore a length is | |
10608 infinitely divisible, so is the corresponding time; he adds | |
10609 ‘<I>this is why</I> (<G>dio/</G>) Zeno's argument falsely assumes that it is | |
10610 not possible to traverse or touch each of an infinite number of | |
10611 points in a finite time’,<note><I>Ib.</I> vi. 2, 233 a 16-23.</note> thereby implying that Zeno did not | |
10612 regard time as divisible <I>ad infinitum</I> like space. Similarly, | |
10613 when Leibniz declares that a space divisible <I>ad infinitum</I> | |
10614 is traversed in a time divisible <I>ad infinitum</I>, he, like Aristotle, | |
10615 is entirely beside the question. Zeno was perfectly aware that, | |
10616 in respect of divisibility, time and space have the same | |
10617 property, and that they are alike, always, and concomitantly, | |
10618 divisible <I>ad infinitum.</I> The question is how, in the one as | |
10619 in the other, this series of divisions, by definition inexhaustible, | |
10620 can be exhausted; and it must be exhausted if motion is to | |
10621 be possible. It is not an answer to say that the two series | |
10622 are exhausted simultaneously. | |
10623 <p>The usual mode of refutation given by mathematicians | |
10624 from Descartes to Tannery, correct in a sense, has an analogous | |
10625 defect. To show that the sum of the infinite series <MATH>1 + 1/2 + 1/4 + ...</MATH> | |
10626 is equal to 2, or to calculate (in the <I>Achilles</I>) the exact moment | |
10627 when Achilles will overtake the tortoise, is to answer the | |
10628 question <I>when</I>? whereas the question actually asked is <I>how</I>? | |
10629 On the hypothesis of divisibility <I>ad infinitum</I> you will, in the | |
10630 <I>Dichotomy</I>, never reach the limit, and, in the <I>Achilles</I>, the | |
10631 distance separating Achilles from the tortoise, though it con- | |
10632 tinually decreases, will never vanish. And if you introduce | |
10633 the limit, or, with a numerical calculation, the discontinuous, | |
10634 Zeno is quite aware that his arguments are no longer valid. | |
10635 We are then in presence of another hypothesis as to the com- | |
10636 position of the continuum; and this hypothesis is dealt with | |
10637 in the third and fourth arguments.<note>Brochard, <I>loc. cit.</I>, p. 9.</note> | |
10638 <p>It appears then that the first and second arguments, in their | |
10639 full significance, were not really met before G. Cantor formu- | |
10640 lated his new theory of continuity and infinity. On this I | |
10641 can only refer to Chapters xlii and xliii of Mr. Bertrand | |
10642 Russell's <I>Principles of Mathematics</I>, vol. i. Zeno's argument | |
10643 in the <I>Dichotomy</I> is that, whatever motion we assume to have | |
10644 taken place, this presupposes another motion; this in turn | |
10645 <pb n=280><head>ZENO OF ELEA</head> | |
10646 another, and so on <I>ad infinitum.</I> Hence there is an endless | |
10647 regress in the mere idea of any assigned motion. Zeno's | |
10648 argument has then to be met by proving that the ‘infinite | |
10649 regress’ in this case is ‘harmless’. | |
10650 <p>As regards the <I>Achilles</I>, Mr. G. H. Hardy remarks that ‘the | |
10651 kernel of it lies in the perfectly valid proof which it affords | |
10652 that the tortoise passes through as many points as Achilles, | |
10653 a view which embodies an accepted doctrine of modern mathe- | |
10654 matics’.<note><I>Encyclopaedia Britannica</I>, art. Zeno.</note> | |
10655 <p>The argument in the <I>Arrow</I> is based on the assumption that | |
10656 time is made up of <I>indivisible</I> elements or instants. Aristotle | |
10657 meets it by denying the assumption. ‘For time is not made | |
10658 up of indivisible instants (<I>nows</I>), any more than any other | |
10659 magnitude is made up of indivisible elements.’ ‘(Zeno's result) | |
10660 follows through assuming that time is made up of (indivisible) | |
10661 instants (<I>nows</I>); if this is not admitted, his conclusion does | |
10662 not follow.’<note>Arist. <I>Phys.</I> vi. 9, 239 b 8, 31.</note> On the other hand, the modern view is that | |
10663 Zeno's contention is <I>true</I>: ‘If’ (said Zeno) ‘everything is at | |
10664 rest or in motion when it occupies a space equal to itself, and | |
10665 if what moves is always in the instant, it follows that the | |
10666 moving arrow is unmoved.’ Mr. Russell<note>Russell, <I>Principles of Mathematics</I>, i, pp. 350, 351.</note> holds that this is | |
10667 ‘a very plain statement of an elementary fact’; | |
10668 <p>‘it is a very important and very widely applicable platitude, | |
10669 namely “Every possible value of a variable is a constant”. | |
10670 If <I>x</I> be a variable which can take all values from 0 to 1, | |
10671 all the values it can take are definite numbers such as 1/2 or 1/3, | |
10672 which are all absolute constants ... Though a variable is | |
10673 always connected with some class, it is not the class, nor | |
10674 a particular member of the class, nor yet the whole class, but | |
10675 <I>any</I> member of the class.’ The usual <I>x</I> in algebra ‘denotes | |
10676 the disjunction formed by the various members’ ... ‘The | |
10677 values of <I>x</I> are then the terms of the disjunction; and each | |
10678 of these is a constant. This simple logical fact seems to | |
10679 constitute the essence of Zeno's contention that the arrow | |
10680 is always at rest.’ ‘But Zeno's argument contains an element | |
10681 which is specially applicable to continua. In the case of | |
10682 motion it denies that there is such a thing as a <I>state</I> of motion. | |
10683 In the general case of a continuous variable, it may be taken | |
10684 as denying actual infinitesimals. For infinitesimals are an | |
10685 <pb n=281><head>ZENO'S ARGUMENTS ABOUT MOTION</head> | |
10686 attempt to extend to the <I>values</I> of a variable the variability | |
10687 which belongs to it alone. When once it is firmly realized | |
10688 that all the values of a variable are constants, it becomes easy | |
10689 to see, by taking <I>any</I> two such values, that their difference is | |
10690 always finite, and hence that there are no infinitesimal differ- | |
10691 ences. If <I>x</I> be a variable which may take all real values | |
10692 from 0 to 1, then, taking any two of these values, we see that | |
10693 their difference is finite, although <I>x</I> is a continuous variable. | |
10694 It is true the difference might have been less than the one we | |
10695 chose; but if it had been, it would still have been finite. The | |
10696 lower limit to possible differences is zero, but all possible | |
10697 differences are finite; and in this there is no shadow of | |
10698 contradiction. This static theory of the variable is due to the | |
10699 mathematicians, and its absence in Zeno's day led him to | |
10700 suppose that continuous change was impossible without a state | |
10701 of change, which involves infinitesimals and the contradiction | |
10702 of a body's being where it is not.’ | |
10703 <p>In his later chapter on Motion Mr. Russell concludes as | |
10704 follows:<note><I>Op. cit.</I>, p. 473.</note> | |
10705 <p>‘It is to be observed that, in consequence of the denial | |
10706 of the infinitesimal and in consequence of the allied purely | |
10707 technical view of the derivative of a function, we must | |
10708 entirely reject the notion of a <I>state</I> of motion. Motion consists | |
10709 <I>merely</I> in the occupation of different places at different times, | |
10710 subject to continuity as explained in Part V. There is no | |
10711 transition from place to place, no consecutive moment or | |
10712 consecutive position, no such thing as velocity except in the | |
10713 sense of a real number which is the limit of a certain set | |
10714 of quotients. The rejection of velocity and acceleration as | |
10715 physical facts (i. e. as properties belonging <I>at each instant</I> to | |
10716 a moving point, and not merely real numbers expressing limits | |
10717 of certain ratios) involves, as we shall see, some difficulties | |
10718 in the statement of the laws of motion; but the reform | |
10719 introduced by Weierstrass in the infinitesimal calculus has | |
10720 rendered this rejection imperative.’ | |
10721 <p>We come lastly to the fourth argument (the <I>Stadium</I>). | |
10722 Aristotle's representation of it is obscure through its extreme | |
10723 brevity of expression, and the matter is further perplexed by | |
10724 an uncertainty of reading. But the meaning intended to be | |
10725 conveyed is fairly clear. The eight <I>A</I>'s, <I>B</I>'s and <I>C</I>'s being | |
10726 <pb n=282><head>ZENO OF ELEA</head> | |
10727 initially in the position shown in Figure 1, suppose, e.g., that | |
10728 the <I>B</I>'s move to the right and the <I>C</I>'s to the left with equal | |
10729 <FIG> | |
10730 velocity until the rows are vertically under one another as in | |
10731 Figure 2. Then <I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB> has passed alongside all the eight <I>B</I>'s (and <I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB> | |
10732 <FIG> | |
10733 alongside all the eight <I>C</I>'s), while <I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB> has passed alongside only | |
10734 half the <I>A</I>'s (and similarly for <I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB>). But (Aristotle makes Zeno | |
10735 say) <I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB> <I>is the same time in passing each of the B's as it is in | |
10736 passing each of the A's.</I> It follows that the time occupied by <I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB> | |
10737 in passing all the <I>A</I>'s is the same as the time occupied by | |
10738 <I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB> in passing half the <I>A</I>'s, or a given time is equal to its half. | |
10739 Aristotle's criticism on this is practically that Zeno did not | |
10740 understand the difference between absolute and relative motion. | |
10741 This is, however, incredible, and another explanation must be | |
10742 found. The real explanation seems to be that given by | |
10743 <FIG> | |
10744 Brochard, Noël and Russell. Zeno's object is to prove that | |
10745 time is not made up of indivisible elements or instants. | |
10746 Suppose the <I>B</I>'s have moved one place to the right and the <I>C</I>'s | |
10747 one place to the left, so that <I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB>, which was under <I>A</I><SUB>4</SUB>, is now | |
10748 under <I>A</I><SUB>5</SUB>, and <I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB>, which was under <I>A</I><SUB>5</SUB>, is now under <I>A</I><SUB>4</SUB>. We | |
10749 must suppose that <I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB> and <I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB> are absolute indivisible elements | |
10750 of space, and that they move to their new positions in an | |
10751 <pb n=283><head>ZENO'S ARGUMENTS ABOUT MOTION</head> | |
10752 instant, the absolute indivisible element of time; this is Zeno's | |
10753 hypothesis. But, in order that <I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB> may have taken up | |
10754 their new positions, there must have been a moment at which | |
10755 they crossed or <I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB> was vertically over <I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB>. Yet the motion | |
10756 has, by hypothesis, taken place in an indivisible instant. | |
10757 Therefore, either they have <I>not</I> crossed (in which case there | |
10758 is no movement), or in the particular indivisible instant two | |
10759 positions have been occupied by the two moving objects, that | |
10760 is to say, the instant is no longer indivisible. And, if the | |
10761 instant is divided into two equal parts, this, on the hypothesis | |
10762 of indivisibles, is equivalent to saying that an instant is double | |
10763 of itself. | |
10764 <p>Two remarks may be added. Though the first two argu- | |
10765 ments are directed against those who assert the divisibility <I>ad | |
10766 infinitum</I> of magnitudes and times, there is no sufficient | |
10767 justification for Tannery's contention that they were specially | |
10768 directed against a view, assumed by him to be Pythagorean, | |
10769 that bodies, surfaces and lines are made up of <I>mathematical</I> | |
10770 points. There is indeed no evidence that the Pythagoreans | |
10771 held this view at all; it does not follow from their definition | |
10772 of a point as a ‘unit having position’ (<G>mona\s qe/sin e)/xousa</G>); | |
10773 and, as we have seen, Aristotle says that the Pythagoreans | |
10774 maintained that units and numbers have magnitude.<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> M. 6, 1080 b 19, 32.</note> | |
10775 <p>It would appear that, after more than 2,300 years, con- | |
10776 troversy on Zeno's arguments is yet by no means at an end. | |
10777 But the subject cannot here be pursued further.<note>It is a pleasure to be able to refer the reader to a most valuable and | |
10778 comprehensive series of papers by Professor Florian Cajori, under the | |
10779 title ‘The History of Zeno's arguments on Motion’, published in the | |
10780 <I>American Mathematical Monthly</I> of 1915, and also available in a reprint. | |
10781 This work carries the history of the various views and criticisms of | |
10782 Zeno's arguments down to 1914. I may also refer to the portions of | |
10783 Bertrand Russell's work, <I>Our Knowledge of the External World as a Field | |
10784 for Scientific Method in Philosophy</I>, 1914, which deal with Zeno, and to | |
10785 Philip E. B. Jourdain's article, ‘The Flying Arrow; an Anachronism’, in | |
10786 <I>Mind</I>, January 1916, pp. 42-55.</note> | |
10787 <pb><C>IX | |
10788 PLATO</C> | |
10789 <p>IT is in the Seventh Book of the <I>Republic</I> that we find | |
10790 the most general statement of the attitude of Plato towards | |
10791 mathematics. Plato regarded mathematics in its four branches, | |
10792 arithmetic, geometry, stereometry and astronomy, as the first | |
10793 essential in the training of philosophers and of those who | |
10794 should rule his ideal State; ‘let no one destitute of geometry | |
10795 enter my doors’, said the inscription over the door of his | |
10796 school. There could be no better evidence of the supreme | |
10797 importance which he attached to the mathematical sciences. | |
10798 <p>What Plato emphasizes throughout when speaking of mathe- | |
10799 matics is its value for the training of the mind; its practical | |
10800 utility is of no account in comparison. Thus arithmetic must | |
10801 be pursued for the sake of knowledge, not for any practical | |
10802 ends such as its use in trade<note><I>Rep.</I> vii. 525 C, D.</note>; the real science of arithmetic | |
10803 has nothing to do with actions, its object is knowledge.<note><I>Politicus</I> 258 D.</note> | |
10804 A very little geometry and arithmetical calculation suffices | |
10805 for the commander of an army; it is the higher and more | |
10806 advanced portions which tend to lift the mind on high and | |
10807 to enable it ultimately to see the final aim of philosophy, | |
10808 the idea of the Good<note><I>Rep.</I> 526 D, E.</note>; the value of the two sciences consists | |
10809 in the fact that they draw the soul towards truth and create | |
10810 the philosophic attitude of mind, lifting on high the things | |
10811 which our ordinary habit would keep down.<note><I>Ib.</I> 527 B.</note> | |
10812 <p>The extent to which Plato insisted on the purely theoretical | |
10813 character of the mathematical sciences is illustrated by his | |
10814 peculiar views about the two subjects which the ordinary | |
10815 person would regard as having, at least, an important practical | |
10816 side, namely astronomy and music. According to Plato, true | |
10817 astronomy is not concerned with the movements of the visible | |
10818 <pb n=285><head>PLATO</head> | |
10819 heavenly bodies. The arrangement of the stars in the heaven | |
10820 and their apparent movements are indeed wonderful and | |
10821 beautiful, but the observation of and the accounting for them | |
10822 falls far short of true astronomy. Before we can attain to | |
10823 this we must get beyond mere observational astronomy, ‘we | |
10824 must leave the heavens alone’. The true science of astronomy | |
10825 is in fact a kind of ideal kinematics, dealing with the laws | |
10826 of motion of true stars in a sort of mathematical heaven of | |
10827 which the visible heaven is an imperfect expression in time | |
10828 and space. The visible heavenly bodies and their apparent | |
10829 motions we are to regard merely as illustrations, comparable | |
10830 to the diagrams which the geometer draws to illustrate the | |
10831 true straight lines, circles, &c., about which his science reasons; | |
10832 they are to be used as ‘problems’ only, with the object of | |
10833 ultimately getting rid of the apparent irregularities and | |
10834 arriving at ‘the true motions with which essential speed | |
10835 and essential slowness move in relation to one another in the | |
10836 true numbers and the true forms, and carry their contents | |
10837 with them’ (to use Burnet's translation of <G>ta\ e)no/nta</G>).<note><I>Rep.</I> vii. 529 C-530 C.</note> | |
10838 ‘Numbers’ in this passage correspond to the periods of the | |
10839 apparent motions; the ‘true forms’ are the true orbits con- | |
10840 trasted with the apparent. It is right to add that according | |
10841 to one view (that of Burnet) Plato means, not that true | |
10842 astronomy deals with an ‘ideal heaven’ different from the | |
10843 apparent, but that it deals with the true motions of the visible | |
10844 bodies as distinct from their apparent motions. This would | |
10845 no doubt agree with Plato's attitude in the <I>Laws,</I> and at the | |
10846 time when he set to his pupils as a problem for solution | |
10847 the question by what combinations of uniform circular revolu- | |
10848 tions the apparent movements of the heavenly bodies can be | |
10849 accounted for. But, except on the assumption that an ideal | |
10850 heaven is meant, it is difficult to see what Plato can mean | |
10851 by the contrast which he draws between the visible broideries | |
10852 of heaven (the visible stars and their arrangement), which | |
10853 are indeed beautiful, and the true broideries which they | |
10854 only imitate and which are infinitely more beautiful and | |
10855 marvellous. | |
10856 <p>This was not a view of astronomy that would appeal to | |
10857 the ordinary person. Plato himself admits the difficulty. | |
10858 <pb n=286><head>PLATO</head> | |
10859 When Socrates's interlocutor speaks of the use of astronomy | |
10860 for distinguishing months and seasons, for agriculture and | |
10861 navigation, and even for military purposes, Socrates rallies | |
10862 him on his anxiety that his curriculum should not consist | |
10863 of subjects which the mass of people would regard as useless: | |
10864 ‘it is by no means an easy thing, nay it is difficult, to believe | |
10865 that in studying these subjects a certain organ in the mind | |
10866 of every one is purified and rekindled which is destroyed and | |
10867 blinded by other pursuits, an organ which is more worthy | |
10868 of preservation than ten thousand eyes; for by it alone is | |
10869 truth discerned.’<note><I>Rep.</I> 527 D, E.</note> | |
10870 <p>As with astronomy, so with harmonics.<note><I>Ib.</I> 531 A-C.</note> The true science of | |
10871 harmonics differs from that science as commonly understood. | |
10872 Even the Pythagoreans, who discovered the correspondence | |
10873 of certain intervals to certain numerical ratios, still made | |
10874 their theory take too much account of audible sounds. The | |
10875 true science of harmonics should be altogether independent | |
10876 of observation and experiment. Plato agreed with the Pytha- | |
10877 goreans as to the nature of sound. Sound is due to concussion of | |
10878 air, and when there is rapid motion in the air the tone is high- | |
10879 pitched, when the motion is slow the tone is low; when the | |
10880 speeds are in certain arithmetical proportions, consonances or | |
10881 harmonies result. But audible movements produced, say, by | |
10882 different lengths of strings are only useful as illustrations; | |
10883 they are imperfect representations of those mathematical | |
10884 movements which produce mathematical consonances, and | |
10885 it is these true consonances which the true <G>a(rmoniko/s</G> should | |
10886 study. | |
10887 <p>We get on to easier ground when Plato discusses geometry. | |
10888 The importance of geometry lies, not in its practical use, but | |
10889 in the fact that it is a study of objects eternal and unchange- | |
10890 able, and tends to lift the soul towards truth. The essence | |
10891 of geometry is therefore directly opposed even to the language | |
10892 which, for want of better terms, geometers are obliged to use; | |
10893 thus they speak of ‘squaring’, ‘applying (a rectangle)’, | |
10894 ‘adding’, &c., as if the object were to <I>do</I> something, whereas | |
10895 the true purpose of geometry is knowledge.<note><I>Ib.</I> vii. 526 D-527 B.</note> Geometry is | |
10896 concerned, not with material things, but with mathematical | |
10897 <pb n=287><head>PLATO</head> | |
10898 points, lines, triangles, squares, &c., as objects of pure thought. | |
10899 If we use a diagram in geometry, it is only as an illustration; | |
10900 the triangle which we draw is an imperfect representation | |
10901 of the real triangle of which we think. <I>Constructions,</I> then, | |
10902 or the <I>processes</I> of squaring, adding, and so on, are not of the | |
10903 essence of geometry, but are actually antagonistic to it. With | |
10904 these views before us, we can without hesitation accept as | |
10905 well founded the story of Plutarch that Plato blamed Eudoxus, | |
10906 Archytas and Menaechmus for trying to reduce the dupli- | |
10907 cation of the cube to mechanical constructions by means of | |
10908 instruments, on the ground that ‘the good of geometry is | |
10909 thereby lost and destroyed, as it is brought back to things | |
10910 of sense instead of being directed upward and grasping at | |
10911 eternal and incorporeal images’.<note>Plutarch, <I>Quaest. Conviv.</I> viii. 2. 1, p. 718 F.</note> It follows almost inevitably | |
10912 that we must reject the tradition attributing to Plato himself | |
10913 the elegant mechanical solution of the problem of the two | |
10914 mean proportionals which we have given in the chapter on | |
10915 Special Problems (pp. 256-7). Indeed, as we said, it is certain | |
10916 on other grounds that the so-called Platonic solution was later | |
10917 than that of Eratosthenes; otherwise Eratosthenes would | |
10918 hardly have failed to mention it in his epigram, along | |
10919 with the solutions by Archytas and Menaechmus. Tannery, | |
10920 indeed, regards Plutarch's story as an invention based on | |
10921 nothing more than the general character of Plato's philosophy, | |
10922 since it took no account of the real nature of the solutions | |
10923 of Archytas and Menaechmus; these solutions are in fact | |
10924 purely theoretical and would have been difficult or impossible | |
10925 to carry out in practice, and there is no reason to doubt that | |
10926 the solution by Eudoxus was of a similar kind.<note>Tannery, <I>La géométrie grecque</I>, pp. 79, 80.</note> This is true, | |
10927 but it is evident that it was the practical difficulty quite as | |
10928 much as the theoretical elegance of the constructions which | |
10929 impressed the Greeks. Thus the author of the letter, wrongly | |
10930 attributed to Eratosthenes, which gives the history of the | |
10931 problem, says that the earlier solvers had all solved the | |
10932 problem in a theoretical manner but had not been able to | |
10933 reduce their solutions to practice, except to a certain small | |
10934 extent Menaechmus, and that with difficulty; and the epigram | |
10935 of Eratosthenes himself says, ‘do not attempt the impracticable | |
10936 <pb n=288><head>PLATO</head> | |
10937 business of the cylinders of Archytas or the cutting of the | |
10938 cone in the three curves of Menaechmus’. It would therefore | |
10939 be quite possible for Plato to regard Archytas and Menaechmus | |
10940 as having given constructions that were ultra-mechanical, since | |
10941 they were more mechanical than the ordinary constructions by | |
10942 means of the straight line and circle; and even the latter, which | |
10943 alone are required for the processes of ‘squaring’, ‘applying | |
10944 (a rectangle)’ and ‘adding’, are according to Plato no part of | |
10945 theoretic geometry. This banning even of simple constructions | |
10946 from true geometry seems, incidentally, to make it impossible | |
10947 to accept the conjecture of Hankel that we owe to Plato the | |
10948 limitation, so important in its effect on the later development | |
10949 of geometry, of the instruments allowable in constructions to | |
10950 the ruler and compasses.<note>Hankel, <I>op. cit.,</I> p. 156.</note> Indeed, there are signs that the | |
10951 limitation began before Plato's time (e.g. this may be the | |
10952 explanation of the two constructions attributed to Oenopides), | |
10953 although no doubt Plato's influence would help to keep the | |
10954 restriction in force; for other instruments, and the use of | |
10955 curves of higher order than circles in constructions, were | |
10956 expressly barred in any case where the ruler and compasses | |
10957 could be made to serve (cf. Pappus's animadversion on a solu- | |
10958 tion of a ‘plane’ problem by means of conics in Apollonius's | |
10959 <I>Conics,</I> Book V). | |
10960 <C>Contributions to the philosophy of mathematics.</C> | |
10961 <p>We find in Plato's dialogues what appears to be the first | |
10962 serious attempt at a philosophy of mathematics. Aristotle | |
10963 says that between sensible objects and the ideas Plato placed | |
10964 ‘things mathematical’ (<G>ta\ maqhmatika/</G>), which differed from | |
10965 sensibles in being eternal and unmoved, but differed again | |
10966 from the ideas in that there can be many mathematical | |
10967 objects of the same kind, while the idea is one only; e.g. the | |
10968 idea of triangle is one, but there may be any number of | |
10969 mathematical triangles as of visible triangles, namely the | |
10970 perfect triangles of which the visible triangles are imper- | |
10971 fect copies. A passage in one of the <I>Letters</I> (No. 7, to the | |
10972 friends of Dion) is interesting in this connexion.<note>Plato, <I>Letters,</I> 342 B, C, 343 A, B.</note> Speaking | |
10973 of a circle by way of example, Plato says there is (1) some- | |
10974 <pb n=289><head>THE PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS</head> | |
10975 thing called a circle and known by that name; next there | |
10976 is (2) its definition as that in which the distances from its | |
10977 extremities in all directions to the centre are always equal, | |
10978 for this may be said to be the definition of that to which the | |
10979 names ‘round’ and ‘circle’ are applied; again (3) we have | |
10980 the circle which is drawn or turned: this circle is perishable | |
10981 and perishes; not so, however, with (4) <G>au)to\s o( ku/klos</G>, the | |
10982 essential circle, or the idea of circle: it is by reference to | |
10983 this that the other circles exist, and it is different from each | |
10984 of them. The same distinction applies to anything else, e. g. | |
10985 the straight, colour, the good, the beautiful, or any natural | |
10986 or artificial object, fire, water, &c. Dealing separately with | |
10987 the four things above distinguished, Plato observes that there | |
10988 is nothing essential in (1) the name: it is merely conventional; | |
10989 there is nothing to prevent our assigning the name ‘straight’ | |
10990 to what we now call ‘round’ and vice versa; nor is there any | |
10991 real definiteness about (2) the definition, seeing that it too | |
10992 is made up of parts of speech, nouns and verbs. The circle | |
10993 (3), the particular circle drawn or turned, is not free from | |
10994 admixture of other things: it is even full of what is opposite | |
10995 to the true nature of a circle, for it will anywhere touch | |
10996 a straight line’, the meaning of which is presumably that we | |
10997 cannot in practice draw a circle and a tangent with only <I>one</I> | |
10998 point common (although a mathematical circle and a mathe- | |
10999 matical straight line touching it meet in one point only). It | |
11000 will be observed that in the above classification there is no | |
11001 place given to the many particular mathematical circles which | |
11002 correspond to those which we draw, and are intermediate | |
11003 between these imperfect circles and the idea of circle which | |
11004 is one only. | |
11005 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>The hypotheses of mathematics.</I></C> | |
11006 <p>The <I>hypotheses</I> of mathematics are discussed by Plato in | |
11007 the <I>Republic.</I> | |
11008 <p>‘I think you know that those who occupy themselves with | |
11009 geometries and calculations and the like take for granted the | |
11010 odd and the even, figures, three kinds of angles, and other | |
11011 things cognate to these in each subject; assuming these things | |
11012 as known, they take them as hypotheses and thenceforward | |
11013 they do not feel called upon to give any explanation with | |
11014 <pb n=290><head>PLATO</head> | |
11015 regard to them either to themselves or any one else, but treat | |
11016 them as manifest to every one; basing themselves on these | |
11017 hypotheses, they proceed at once to go through the rest of | |
11018 the argument till they arrive, with general assent, at the | |
11019 particular conclusion to which their inquiry was directed. | |
11020 Further you know that they make use of visible figures and | |
11021 argue about them, but in doing so they are not thinking of | |
11022 these figures but of the things which they represent; thus | |
11023 it is the absolute square and the absolute diameter which is | |
11024 the object of their argument, not the diameter which they | |
11025 draw; and similarly, in other cases, the things which they | |
11026 actually model or draw, and which may also have their images | |
11027 in shadows or in water, are themselves in turn used as | |
11028 images, the object of the inquirer being to see their abso- | |
11029 lute counterparts which cannot be seen otherwise than by | |
11030 thought.’<note><I>Republic,</I> vi. 510 C-E.</note> | |
11031 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The two intellectual methods.</I></C> | |
11032 <p>Plato distinguishes two processes: both begin from hypo- | |
11033 theses. The one method cannot get above these hypotheses, | |
11034 but, treating them as if they were first principles, builds upon | |
11035 them and, with the aid of diagrams or images, arrives at | |
11036 conclusions: this is the method of geometry and mathematics | |
11037 in general. The other method treats the hypotheses as being | |
11038 really hypotheses and nothing more, but uses them as stepping- | |
11039 stones for mounting higher and higher until the principle | |
11040 of all things is reached, a principle about which there is | |
11041 nothing hypothetical; when this is reached, it is possible to | |
11042 descend again, by steps each connected with the preceding | |
11043 step, to the conclusion, a process which has no need of any | |
11044 sensible images but deals in ideas only and ends in them<note><I>Ib.</I> vi. 510 B 511 A-C.</note>; | |
11045 this method, which rises above and puts an end to hypotheses, | |
11046 and reaches the first principle in this way, is the dialectical | |
11047 method. For want of this, geometry and the other sciences | |
11048 which in some sort lay hold of truth are comparable to one | |
11049 dreaming about truth, nor can they have a waking sight of | |
11050 it so long as they treat their hypotheses as immovable | |
11051 truths, and are unable to give any account or explanation | |
11052 of them.<note><I>Ib.</I> vii. 533 B-E.</note> | |
11053 <pb n=291><head>THE TWO INTELLECTUAL METHODS</head> | |
11054 <p>With the above quotations we should read a passage of | |
11055 Proclus. | |
11056 <p>‘Nevertheless certain methods have been handed down. The | |
11057 finest is the method which by means of <I>analysis</I> carries | |
11058 the thing sought up to an acknowledged principle; a method | |
11059 which Plato, as they say, communicated to Leodamas, and by | |
11060 which the latter too is said to have discovered many things | |
11061 in geometry. The second is the method of <I>division,</I> which | |
11062 divides into its parts the genus proposed for consideration, | |
11063 and gives a starting-point for the demonstration by means of | |
11064 the elimination of the other elements in the construction | |
11065 of what is proposed, which method also Plato extolled as | |
11066 being of assistance to all sciences.’<note>Proclus, <I>Comm. on Eucl.</I> I, pp. 211. 18-212. 1.</note> | |
11067 <p>The first part of this passage, with a like dictum in Diogenes | |
11068 Laertius that Plato ‘explained to Leodamas of Thasos the | |
11069 method of inquiry by analysis’,<note>Diog. L. iii. 24, p. 74, Cobet.</note> has commonly been under- | |
11070 stood as attributing to Plato the <I>invention</I> of the method | |
11071 of mathematical analysis. But, analysis being according to | |
11072 the ancient view nothing more than a series of successive | |
11073 reductions of a theorem or problem till it is finally reduced | |
11074 to a theorem or problem already known, it is difficult to | |
11075 see in what Plato's supposed discovery could have consisted; | |
11076 for analysis in this sense must have been frequently used | |
11077 in earlier investigations. Not only did Hippocrates of Chios | |
11078 reduce the problem of duplicating the cube to that of finding | |
11079 two mean proportionals, but it is clear that the method of | |
11080 analysis in the sense of reduction must have been in use by | |
11081 the Pythagoreans. On the other hand, Proclus's language | |
11082 suggests that what he had in mind was the philosophical | |
11083 method described in the passage of the <I>Republic,</I> which of | |
11084 course does not refer to mathematical analysis at all; it may | |
11085 therefore well be that the idea that Plato discovered the | |
11086 method of analysis is due to a misapprehension. But analysis | |
11087 and synthesis following each other are related in the same | |
11088 way as the upward and downward progressions in the dialec- | |
11089 tician's intellectual method. It has been suggested, therefore, | |
11090 that Plato's achievement was to observe the importance | |
11091 from the point of view of logical rigour, of the confirma- | |
11092 tory synthesis following analysis. The method of <I>division</I> | |
11093 <pb n=292><head>PLATO</head> | |
11094 mentioned by Proclus is the method of successive bipartitions | |
11095 of genera into species such as we find in the <I>Sophist</I> and | |
11096 the <I>Politicus,</I> and has little to say to geometry; but the | |
11097 mention of it side by side with analysis itself suggests that | |
11098 Proclus confused the latter with the philosophical method | |
11099 referred to. | |
11100 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Definitions.</I></C> | |
11101 <p>Among the fundamentals of mathematics Plato paid a good | |
11102 deal of attention to definitions. In some cases his definitions | |
11103 connect themselves with Pythagorean tradition; in others he | |
11104 seems to have struck out a new line for himself. The division | |
11105 of numbers into odd and even is one of the most common of | |
11106 his illustrations; number, he says, is divided equally, i. e. | |
11107 there are as many odd numbers as even, and this is the true | |
11108 division of number; to divide number (e. g.) into myriads and | |
11109 what are not myriads is not a proper division.<note><I>Politicus,</I> 262 D, E.</note> An even | |
11110 number is defined as a number divisible into two equal parts<note><I>Laws,</I> 895 E.</note>; | |
11111 in another place it is explained as that which is not scalene | |
11112 but isosceles<note><I>Euthyphro,</I> 12 D.</note>: a curious and apparently unique application | |
11113 of these terms to number, and in any case a defective state- | |
11114 ment unless the term ‘scalene’ is restricted to the case in which | |
11115 one part of the number is odd and the other even; for of | |
11116 course an even number can be divided into two unequal odd | |
11117 numbers or two unequal even numbers (except 2 in the first | |
11118 case and 2 and 4 in the second). The further distinction | |
11119 between even-times-even, odd-times-even, even-times-odd and | |
11120 odd-times-odd occurs in Plato<note><I>Parmenides,</I> 143 E-144 A.</note>: but, as thrice two is called | |
11121 odd-times-even and twice three is even-times-odd, the number | |
11122 in both cases being the same, it is clear that, like Euclid, | |
11123 Plato regarded even-times-odd and odd-times-even as con- | |
11124 vertible terms, and did not restrict their meaning in the way | |
11125 that Nicomachus and the neo-Pythagoreans did. | |
11126 <p>Coming to geometry we find an interesting view of the | |
11127 term ‘figure’. What is it, asks Socrates, that is true of the | |
11128 round, the straight, and the other things that you call figures, | |
11129 and is the same for all? As a suggestion for a definition | |
11130 of ‘figure’, Socrates says, ‘let us regard as <I>figure</I> that which | |
11131 alone of existing things is associated with colour’. Meno | |
11132 <pb n=293><head>DEFINITIONS</head> | |
11133 asks what is to be done if the interlocutor says he does not | |
11134 know what colour is; what alternative definition is there? | |
11135 Socrates replies that it will be admitted that in geometry | |
11136 there are such things as what we call a surface or a solid, | |
11137 and so on; from these examples we may learn what we mean | |
11138 by figure; figure is that in which a solid ends, or figure is | |
11139 the limit (or extremity, <G>pe/ras</G>) of a solid.<note><I>Meno,</I> 75 A-76 A.</note> Apart from | |
11140 ‘figure’ as form or shape, e.g. the round or straight, this | |
11141 passage makes ‘figure’ practically equivalent to surface, and | |
11142 we are reminded of the Pythagorean term for surface, <G>xroia/</G>, | |
11143 colour or skin, which Aristotle similarly explains as <G>xrw=ma</G>, | |
11144 colour, something inseparable from <G>pe/ras</G>, extremity.<note>Arist. <I>De sensu,</I> 439 a 31, &c.</note> In | |
11145 Euclid of course <G>o(/ros</G>, limit or boundary, is defined as the | |
11146 extremity (<G>pe/ras</G>) of a thing, while ‘figure’ is that which is | |
11147 contained by one or more boundaries. | |
11148 <p>There is reason to believe, though we are not specifically | |
11149 told, that the definition of a line as ‘breadthless length’ | |
11150 originated in the Platonic School, and Plato himself gives | |
11151 a definition of a straight line as ‘that of which the middle | |
11152 covers the ends’<note><I>Parmenides,</I> 137 E.</note> (i. e. to an eye placed at either end and | |
11153 looking along the straight line); this seems to me to be the | |
11154 origin of the Euclidean definition ‘a line which lies evenly | |
11155 with the points on it’, which, I think, can only be an attempt | |
11156 to express the sense of Plato's definition in terms to which | |
11157 a geometer could not take exception as travelling outside the | |
11158 subject matter of geometry, i. e. in terms excluding any appeal | |
11159 to vision. A <I>point</I> had been defined by the Pythagoreans as | |
11160 a ‘monad having position’; Plato apparently objected to this | |
11161 definition and substituted no other; for, according to Aristotle, | |
11162 he regarded the genus of points as being a ‘geometrical | |
11163 fiction’, calling a point the beginning of a line, and often using | |
11164 the term ‘indivisible lines’ in the same sense.<note>Arist. <I>Metaph.</I> A. 9, 992 a 20.</note> Aristotle | |
11165 points out that even indivisible lines must have extremities, | |
11166 and therefore they do not help, while the definition of a point | |
11167 as ‘the extremity of a line’ is unscientific.<note>Arist. <I>Topics,</I> vi. 4, 141 b 21.</note> | |
11168 <p>The ‘round’ (<G>stroggu/lon</G>) or the circle is of course defined | |
11169 as ‘that in which the furthest points (<G>ta\ e)/sxata</G>) in all | |
11170 <pb n=294><head>PLATO</head> | |
11171 directions are at the same distance from the middle (centre)’.<note><I>Parmenides,</I> 137 E.</note> | |
11172 The ‘sphere’ is similarly defined as ‘that which has the | |
11173 distances from its centre to its terminations or ends in every | |
11174 direction equal’, or simply as that which is ‘equal (equidistant) | |
11175 from the centre in all directions’.<note><I>Timaeus,</I> 33 B, 34 B.</note> | |
11176 <p>The <I>Parmenides</I> contains certain phrases corresponding to | |
11177 what we find in Euclid's preliminary matter. Thus Plato | |
11178 speaks of something which is ‘a part’ but not ‘parts’ of the | |
11179 One,<note><I>Parmenides,</I> 153 D.</note> reminding us of Euclid's distinction between a fraction | |
11180 which is ‘a part’, i. e. an aliquot part or submultiple, and one | |
11181 which is ‘parts’, i. e. some number more than one of such | |
11182 parts, e. g. 3/7. If equals be added to unequals, the sums differ | |
11183 by the same amount as the original unequals did:<note><I>Ib.</I> 154 B.</note> an axiom | |
11184 in a rather more complete form than that subsequently inter- | |
11185 polated in Euclid. | |
11186 <C>Summary of the mathematics in Plato.</C> | |
11187 <p>The actual arithmetical and geometrical propositions referred | |
11188 to or presupposed in Plato's writings are not such as to suggest | |
11189 that he was in advance of his time in mathematics; his | |
11190 knowledge does not appear to have been more than up to | |
11191 date. In the following paragraphs I have attempted to give | |
11192 a summary, as complete as possible, of the mathematics con- | |
11193 tained in the dialogues. | |
11194 <p>A proposition in proportion is quoted in the <I>Parmenides,</I><note><I>Ib.</I> 154 D.</note> | |
11195 namely that, if <I>a</I> > <I>b</I>, then <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>c</I>):(<I>b</I>+<I>c</I>)<<I>a</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>. | |
11196 <p>In the <I>Laws</I> a certain number, 5,040, is selected as a most | |
11197 convenient number of citizens to form a state; its advantages | |
11198 are that it is the product of 12, 21 and 20, that a twelfth | |
11199 part of it is again divisible by 12, and that it has as many as | |
11200 59 different divisors in all, including all the natural numbers | |
11201 from 1 to 12 with the exception of 11, while it is nearly | |
11202 divisible by 11 (5038 being a multiple of 11).<note><I>Laws,</I> 537 E-538 A.</note> | |
11203 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Regular and semi-regular solids.</I></C> | |
11204 <p>The ‘so-called Platonic figures’, by which are meant the | |
11205 five regular solids, are of course not Plato's discovery, for they | |
11206 had been partly investigated by the Pythagoreans, and very | |
11207 <pb n=295><head>REGULAR AND SEMI-REGULAR SOLIDS</head> | |
11208 fully by Theaetetus; they were evidently only called Platonic | |
11209 because of the use made of them in the <I>Timaeus,</I> where the | |
11210 particles of the four elements are given the shapes of the first | |
11211 four of the solids, the pyramid or tetrahedron being appro- | |
11212 priated to fire, the octahedron to air, the icosahedron to water, | |
11213 and the cube to earth, while the Creator used the fifth solid, | |
11214 the dodecahedron, for the universe itself.<note><I>Timaeus,</I> 55 D-56 B, 55 C.</note> | |
11215 <p>According to Heron, however, Archimedes, who discovered | |
11216 thirteen semi-regular solids inscribable in a sphere, said that | |
11217 <p>‘Plato also knew one of them, the figure with fourteen faces, | |
11218 of which there are two sorts, one made up of eight triangles | |
11219 and six squares, of earth and air, and already known to some | |
11220 of the ancients, the other again made up of eight squares and | |
11221 six triangles, which seems to be more difficult.’<note>Heron, <I>Definitions,</I> 104, p. 66, Heib.</note> | |
11222 <p>The first of these is easily obtained; if we take each square | |
11223 face of a cube and make in it a smaller square by joining | |
11224 the middle points of each pair of consecutive sides, we get six | |
11225 squares (one in each face); taking the three out of the twenty- | |
11226 four sides of these squares which are about any one angular | |
11227 point of the cube, we have an equilateral triangle; there are | |
11228 eight of these equilateral triangles, and if we cut off-from the | |
11229 corners of the cube the pyramids on these triangles as bases, | |
11230 <FIG> | |
11231 we have a semi-regular polyhedron | |
11232 inscribable in a sphere and having | |
11233 as faces eight equilateral triangles | |
11234 and six squares. The description of | |
11235 the second semi-regular figure with | |
11236 fourteen faces is wrong: there are | |
11237 only two more such figures, (1) the | |
11238 figure obtained by cutting off from | |
11239 the corners of the cube smaller | |
11240 pyramids on equilateral triangular bases such that regular | |
11241 <I>octagons,</I> and not squares, are left in the six square faces, | |
11242 the figure, that is, contained by eight triangles and six | |
11243 octagons, and (2) the figure obtained by cutting off from the | |
11244 corners of an <I>octahedron</I> equal pyramids with square bases | |
11245 such as to leave eight regular hexagons in the eight faces, | |
11246 that is, the figure contained by six squares and eight hexagons. | |
11247 <pb n=296><head>PLATO</head> | |
11248 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The construction of the regular solids.</I></C> | |
11249 <p>Plato, of course, constructs the regular solids by simply | |
11250 putting together the plane faces. These faces are, he observes, | |
11251 made up of triangles; and all triangles are decomposable into | |
11252 two right-angled triangles. Right-angled triangles are either | |
11253 (1) isosceles or (2) not isosceles, having the two acute angles | |
11254 unequal. Of the latter class, which is unlimited in number, | |
11255 one triangle is the most beautiful, that in which the square on | |
11256 the perpendicular is triple of the square on the base (i. e. the | |
11257 triangle which is the half of an equilateral triangle obtained | |
11258 by drawing a perpendicular from a vertex on the opposite | |
11259 side). (Plato is here Pythagorizing.<note>Cf. Speusippus in <I>Theol. Ar.,</I> p. 61, Ast.</note>) One of the regular | |
11260 solids, the cube, has its faces (squares) made up of the first | |
11261 <FIG> | |
11262 kind of right-angled triangle, the isosceles, four of | |
11263 them being put together to form the square; three | |
11264 others with equilateral triangles for faces, the tetra- | |
11265 hedron, octahedron and icosahedron, depend upon | |
11266 the other species of right-angled triangle only, | |
11267 each face being made up of six (not two) of those right-angled | |
11268 triangles, as shown in the figure; the fifth solid, the dodeca- | |
11269 <FIG> | |
11270 hedron, with twelve regular pentagons for | |
11271 faces, is merely alluded to, not described, in | |
11272 the passage before us, and Plato is aware that | |
11273 its faces cannot be constructed out of the two | |
11274 elementary right-angled triangles on which the | |
11275 four other solids depend. That an attempt was made to divide | |
11276 the pentagon into a number of triangular elements is clear | |
11277 <FIG> | |
11278 from three passages, two in Plutarch<note>Plutarch, <I>Quaest. Plat.</I> 5. 1, 1003 D; <I>De defectu Oraculorum,</I> c. 33, 428 A.</note> | |
11279 and one in Alcinous.<note>Alcinous, <I>De Doctrina Platonis,</I> c. 11.</note> Plutarch says | |
11280 that each of the twelve faces of a | |
11281 dodecahedron is made up of thirty | |
11282 elementary scalene triangles which are | |
11283 different from the elementary triangle | |
11284 of the solids with triangular faces. | |
11285 Alcinous speaks of the 360 elements | |
11286 which are produced when each pen- | |
11287 tagon is divided into five isosceles triangles and each of the | |
11288 <pb n=297><head>THE REGULAR SOLIDS</head> | |
11289 latter into six scalene triangles. If we draw lines in a pen- | |
11290 tagon as shown in the accompanying figure, we obtain such | |
11291 a set of triangles in a way which also shows the Pythagorean | |
11292 pentagram (cf. p. 161, above). | |
11293 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Geometric means between two square numbers | |
11294 or two cubes.</I></C> | |
11295 <p>In the <I>Timaeus</I> Plato, speaking of numbers ‘whether solid | |
11296 or square’ with a (geometric) mean or means between them, | |
11297 observes that between <I>planes</I> one mean suffices, but to connect | |
11298 two <I>solids</I> two means are necessary.<note><I>Timaeus,</I> 31 C-32 B.</note> By <I>planes</I> and <I>solids</I> | |
11299 Plato probably meant <I>square</I> and <I>cube numbers</I> respectively, | |
11300 so that the theorems quoted are probably those of Eucl. VIII. | |
11301 11, 12, to the effect that between two square numbers there is | |
11302 one mean proportional number, and between two cube numbers | |
11303 two mean proportional numbers. Nicomachus quotes these | |
11304 very propositions as constituting ‘a certain Platonic theorem’.<note>Nicom. ii. 24. 6.</note> | |
11305 Here, too, it may be that the theorem is called ‘Platonic’ for | |
11306 the sole reason that it is quoted by Plato in the <I>Timaeus</I>; | |
11307 it may well be older, for the idea of two mean proportionals | |
11308 between two straight lines had already appeared in Hippo- | |
11309 crates's reduction of the problem of doubling the cube. Plato's | |
11310 allusion does not appear to be to the duplication of the cube | |
11311 in this passage any more than in the expression <G>ku/bwn au)/xh</G>, | |
11312 ‘cubic increase’, in the <I>Republic,</I><note><I>Republic,</I> 528 B.</note> which appears to be nothing | |
11313 but the addition of the third dimension to a square, making | |
11314 a cube (cf. <G>tri/th au)/xh</G>, ‘third increase’,<note><I>Ib.</I> 587 D.</note> meaning a cube | |
11315 number as compared with <G>du/namis</G>, a square number, terms | |
11316 which are applied, e. g. to the numbers 729 and 81 respec- | |
11317 tively). | |
11318 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>The two geometrical passages in the</I> MENO.</C> | |
11319 <p>We come now to the two geometrical passages in the <I>Meno.</I> | |
11320 In the first<note><I>Meno,</I> 82 B-85 B.</note> Socrates is trying to show that teaching is only | |
11321 reawaking in the mind of the learner the memory of some- | |
11322 thing. He illustrates by putting to the slave a carefully | |
11323 prepared series of questions, each requiring little more than | |
11324 <pb n=298><head>PLATO</head> | |
11325 ‘yes’ or ‘no’ for an answer, but leading up to the geometrical | |
11326 construction of √2. Starting with a straight line <I>AB</I> 2 feet | |
11327 long, Socrates describes a square <I>ABCD</I> upon it and easily | |
11328 shows that the area is 4 square feet. Producing the sides | |
11329 <I>AB, AD</I> to <I>G, K</I> so that <I>BG, DK</I> are equal to <I>AB, AD,</I> and | |
11330 completing the figure, we have a square of side 4 feet, and this | |
11331 square is equal to four times the original square and therefore | |
11332 has an area of 16 square feet. Now, says Socrates, a square | |
11333 8 feet in area must have its side | |
11334 <FIG> | |
11335 greater than 2 and less than 4 feet. | |
11336 The slave suggests that it is 3 feet | |
11337 in length. By taking <I>N</I> the | |
11338 middle point of <I>DK</I> (so that <I>AN</I> | |
11339 is 3 feet) and completing the square | |
11340 on <I>AN,</I> Socrates easily shows that | |
11341 the square on <I>AN</I> is not 8 but 9 | |
11342 square feet in area. If <I>L, M</I> be | |
11343 the middle points of <I>GH, HK</I> and | |
11344 <I>CL, CM</I> be joined, we have four | |
11345 squares in the figure, one of which is <I>ABCD,</I> while each of the | |
11346 others is equal to it. If now we draw the diagonals <I>BL, LM, | |
11347 MD, DB</I> of the four squares, each diagonal bisects its square, | |
11348 and the four make a square <I>BLMD,</I> the area of which is half | |
11349 that of the square <I>AGHK,</I> and is therefore 8 square feet; | |
11350 <I>BL</I> is a side of this square. Socrates concludes with the | |
11351 words: | |
11352 <p>‘The Sophists call this straight line (<I>BD</I>) the <I>diameter</I> | |
11353 (diagonal); this being its name, it follows that the square | |
11354 which is double (of the original square) has to be described on | |
11355 the diameter.’ | |
11356 <p>The other geometrical passage in the <I>Meno</I> is much more | |
11357 difficult,<note><I>Meno,</I> 86 E-87 C.</note> and it has gathered round it a literature almost | |
11358 comparable in extent to the volumes that have been written | |
11359 to explain the Geometrical Number of the <I>Republic.</I> C. Blass, | |
11360 writing in 1861, knew thirty different interpretations; and | |
11361 since then many more have appeared. Of recent years | |
11362 Benecke's interpretation<note>Dr. Adolph Benecke, <I>Ueber die geometrische Hypothesis in Platon's | |
11363 Menon</I> (Elbing, 1867). See also below, pp. 302-3.</note> seems to have enjoyed the most | |
11364 <pb n=299><head>TWO GEOMETRICAL PASSAGES IN THE <I>MENO</I></head> | |
11365 acceptance; nevertheless, I think that it is not the right one, | |
11366 but that the essentials of the correct interpretation were given | |
11367 by S. H. Butcher<note><I>Journal of Philology,</I> vol. xvii, pp. 219-25; cf. E. S. Thompson's edition | |
11368 of the <I>Meno.</I></note> (who, however, seems to have been com- | |
11369 pletely anticipated by E. F. August, the editor of Euclid, in | |
11370 1829). It is necessary to begin with a literal translation of | |
11371 the passage. Socrates is explaining a procedure ‘by way | |
11372 of hypothesis’, a procedure which, he observes, is illustrated | |
11373 by the practice of geometers | |
11374 <p>‘when they are asked, for example, as regards a given area, | |
11375 whether it is possible for this area to be inscribed in the form | |
11376 of a triangle in a given circle. The answer might be, “I do | |
11377 not yet know whether this area is such as can be so inscribed, | |
11378 but I think I can suggest a hypothesis which will be useful for | |
11379 the purpose; I mean the following. If the given area is such | |
11380 as, when one has applied it (as a rectangle) to the given | |
11381 straight line in the circle [<G>th\n doqei=san au)tou= grammh/n</G>, the | |
11382 given straight line <I>in it,</I> cannot, I think, mean anything | |
11383 but the <I>diameter</I> of the circle<note>The obvious ‘line’ of a circle is its diameter, just as, in the first | |
11384 geometrical passage about the squares, the <G>grammh/</G>, the ‘line’, of a square | |
11385 is its <I>side.</I></note>], it is deficient by a figure | |
11386 (rectangle) similar to the very figure which is applied, then | |
11387 one alternative seems to me to result, while again another | |
11388 results if it is impossible for what I said to be done with it. | |
11389 Accordingly, by using a hypothesis, I am ready to tell you what | |
11390 results with regard to the inscribing of the figure in the circle, | |
11391 namely, whether the problem is possible or impossible.”’ | |
11392 <p>Let <I>AEB</I> be a circle on <I>AB</I> as diameter, and let <I>AC</I> be the | |
11393 tangent at <I>A.</I> Take <I>E</I> any point on the circle and draw | |
11394 <I>ED</I> perpendicular to <I>AB.</I> Complete the rectangles <I>ACED, | |
11395 EDBF.</I> | |
11396 <p>Then it is clear that the rectangle <I>CEDA</I> is ‘applied’ to | |
11397 the diameter <I>AB,</I> and also that it ‘falls short’ by a figure, the | |
11398 rectangle <I>EDBF,</I> similar to the ‘applied’ rectangle, for | |
11399 <MATH><I>AD</I>:<I>DE</I> = <I>ED</I>:<I>DB</I></MATH>. | |
11400 <p>Also, if <I>ED</I> be produced to meet the circle again in <I>G, | |
11401 AEG</I> is an isosceles triangle bisected by the diameter <I>AB,</I> | |
11402 and therefore equal in area to the rectangle <I>ACED.</I> | |
11403 <p>If then the latter rectangle, ‘applied’ to <I>AB</I> in the manner | |
11404 <pb n=300><head>PLATO</head> | |
11405 described, is equal to the given area, that area is inscribed in | |
11406 the form of a triangle in the given circle.<note>Butcher, after giving the essentials of the interpretation of the | |
11407 passage quite correctly, finds a difficulty. ‘If’, he says, ‘the condition’ | |
11408 (as interpreted by him) ‘holds good, the given <G>xwri/on</G> can be inscribed in | |
11409 a circle. But the converse proposition is not true. The <G>xwri/on</G> can still | |
11410 be inscribed, as required, even if the condition laid down is not fulfilled; | |
11411 the true and necessary condition being that the given area is not greater | |
11412 than that of the equilateral triangle, i. e. the <I>maximum</I> triangle, which | |
11413 can be inscribed in the given circle.’ The difficulty arises in this way. | |
11414 Assuming (quite fairly) that the given area is given in the form of a rect- | |
11415 angle (for any given rectilineal figure can be transformed into a rectangle | |
11416 of equal area), Butcher seems to suppose that it is identically the given | |
11417 rectangle that is applied to <I>AB.</I> But this is not necessary. The termi- | |
11418 nology of mathematics was not quite fixed in Plato's time, and he allows | |
11419 himself some latitude of expression, so that we need not be surprised to | |
11420 find him using the phrase ‘to apply the area (<G>xwri/on</G>) to a given straight | |
11421 line’ as short for ‘to apply to a given straight line a <I>rectangle equal</I> (but not | |
11422 similar) to the given area’ (cf. Pappus vi, p. 544. 8-10 <G>mh\ pa=n to\ doqe\n | |
11423 para\ th\n doqei=san paraba/llesqai e)llei=pon tetragw/nw|</G>, ‘that it is not every | |
11424 given (area) that can be applied (in the form of a rectangle) falling short | |
11425 by a square figure’). If we interpret the expression in this way, the | |
11426 converse <I>is</I> true; if we cannot apply, in the way described, a rectangle | |
11427 <I>equal</I> to the given rectangle, it is because the given rectangle is greater | |
11428 than the equilateral, i. e. the maximum, triangle that can be inscribed in | |
11429 the circle, and the problem is therefore impossible of solution. (It was | |
11430 not till long after the above was written that my attention was drawn to | |
11431 the article on the same subject in the <I>Journal of Philology,</I> xxviii, 1903, | |
11432 pp. 222-40, by Professor Cook Wilson. I am gratified to find that my | |
11433 interpretation of the passage agrees with his.)</note> | |
11434 <p>In order, therefore, to inscribe in the circle an isosceles | |
11435 triangle equal to the given area (<I>X</I>), we have to find a point <I>E</I> | |
11436 on the circle such that, if <I>ED</I> be drawn perpendicular to <I>AB,</I> | |
11437 <FIG> | |
11438 the rectangle <I>AD. DE</I> is equal to the given area <I>X</I> (‘applying’ | |
11439 to <I>AB</I> a rectangle equal to <I>X</I> and falling short by a figure | |
11440 similar to the ‘applied’ figure is only another way of ex- | |
11441 pressing it). Evidently <I>E</I> lies on the rectangular hyperbola | |
11442 <pb n=301><head>TWO GEOMETRICAL PASSAGES IN THE <I>MENO</I></head> | |
11443 the equation of which referred to <I>AB, AC</I> as axes of <I>x, y</I> is | |
11444 <MATH><I>xy</I> = <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, where <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> is equal to the given area. For a real | |
11445 solution it is necessary that <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> should be not greater than the | |
11446 equilateral triangle inscribed in the circle, i. e. not greater than | |
11447 <MATH>3 √3.<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4</MATH>, where <I>a</I> is the radius of the circle. If <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> is equal | |
11448 to this area, there is only one solution (the hyperbola in that | |
11449 case touching the circle); if <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> is less than this area, there are | |
11450 two solutions corresponding to two points <I>E, E</I>′ in which the | |
11451 hyperbola cuts the circle. If <MATH><I>AD</I> = <I>x</I></MATH>, we have <MATH><I>OD</I> = <I>x-a</I></MATH>, | |
11452 <MATH><I>DE</I> = √(2 <I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>, and the problem is the equivalent of | |
11453 solving the equation | |
11454 <MATH><I>x</I>√(2 <I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>) = <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
11455 or | |
11456 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP> (2 <I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>) = <I>b</I><SUP>4</SUP></MATH>. | |
11457 <p>This is an equation of the fourth degree which can be solved | |
11458 by means of conics but not by means of the straight line | |
11459 and circle. The solution is given by the points of intersec- | |
11460 tion of the hyperbola <MATH><I>xy</I> = <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> and the circle <MATH><I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP> = 2 <I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> or | |
11461 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP> = 2 <I>ax</I></MATH>. In this respect therefore the problem is like | |
11462 that of finding the two mean proportionals, which was likewise | |
11463 solved, though not till later, by means of conics (Menaechmus). | |
11464 I am tempted to believe that we have here an allusion to | |
11465 another actual problem, requiring more than the straight | |
11466 line and circle for its solution, | |
11467 <FIG> | |
11468 which had exercised the minds | |
11469 of geometers by the time of | |
11470 Plato, the problem, namely, of | |
11471 inscribing in a circle a triangle | |
11472 equal to a given area, a problem | |
11473 which was still awaiting a | |
11474 solution, although it had been | |
11475 reduced to the problem of | |
11476 applying a rectangle satisfying the condition described by | |
11477 Plato, just as the duplication of the cube had been reduced | |
11478 to the problem of finding two mean proportionals. Our | |
11479 problem can, like the latter problem, easily be solved by the | |
11480 ‘mechanical’ use of a ruler. Suppose that the given rectangle | |
11481 is placed so that the side <I>AD</I> lies along the diameter <I>AB</I> of | |
11482 the circle. Let <I>E</I> be the angle of the rectangle <I>ADEC</I> opposite | |
11483 to <I>A.</I> Place a ruler so that it passes through <I>E</I> and turn | |
11484 <pb n=302><head>PLATO</head> | |
11485 it about <I>E</I> until it passes through a point <I>P</I> of the circle such | |
11486 that, if <I>EP</I> meets <I>AB</I> and <I>AC</I> produced in <I>T, R, PT</I> shall be | |
11487 equal to <I>ER.</I> Then, since <MATH><I>RE</I> = <I>PT, AD</I> = <I>MT</I></MATH>, where <I>M</I> is | |
11488 the foot of the ordinate <I>PM.</I> | |
11489 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>DT</I> = <I>AM</I></MATH>, and | |
11490 <MATH><I>AM</I>:<I>AD</I> = <I>DT</I>:<I>MT</I> | |
11491 = <I>ED</I>:<I>PM</I></MATH>, | |
11492 whence <MATH><I>PM.MA</I> = <I>ED.DA</I></MATH>, | |
11493 and <I>APM</I> is the half of the required (isosceles) triangle. | |
11494 <p>Benecke criticizes at length the similar interpretation of the | |
11495 passage given by E. F. August. So far, however, as his objec- | |
11496 tions relate to the translation of particular words in the | |
11497 Greek text, they are, in my opinion, not well founded.<note>The main point of Benecke's criticisms under this head has reference | |
11498 to <G>toiou/tw| xwri/w| oi=(on</G> in the phrase <G>e)llei/pein toiou/tw| xwri/w| oi=(on a)\n au)to\ to\ | |
11499 parat tame/non h=)|</G>. He will have it that <G>toiou/tw| oi=(on</G> cannot mean ‘similar to’, | |
11500 and he maintains that, if Plato had meant it in this sense, he should | |
11501 have added that the ‘defect’, although ‘similar’, is not similarly situated. | |
11502 I see no force in this argument in view of the want of fixity in mathe- | |
11503 matical terminology in Plato's time, and of his own habit of varying his | |
11504 phrases for literary effect. Benecke makes the words mean ‘of the same | |
11505 <I>kind</I>’, e. g. a square with a square or a rectangle with a rectangle. But | |
11506 this would have no point unless the figures are <I>squares,</I> which begs the | |
11507 whole question.</note> For | |
11508 the rest, Benecke holds that, in view of the difficulty of the | |
11509 problem which emerges, Plato is unlikely to have introduced | |
11510 it in such an abrupt and casual way into the conversation | |
11511 between Socrates and Meno. But the problem is only one | |
11512 of the same nature as that of the finding of two mean | |
11513 proportionals which was already a famous problem, and, as | |
11514 regards the form of the allusion, it is to be noted that Plato | |
11515 was fond of dark hints in things mathematical. | |
11516 <p>If the above interpretation is too difficult (which I, for one, | |
11517 do not admit), Benecke's is certainly too easy. He connects | |
11518 his interpretation of the passage with the earlier passage | |
11519 about the square of side 2 feet; according to him the problem | |
11520 <FIG> | |
11521 is, can an isosceles <I>right-angled</I> tri- | |
11522 angle equal to the said square be | |
11523 inscribed in the given circle? This | |
11524 is of course only possible if the | |
11525 radius of the circle is 2 feet in length. | |
11526 If <I>AB, DE</I> be two diameters at right | |
11527 angles, the inscribed triangle is <I>ADE</I>; | |
11528 the square <I>ACDO</I> formed by the radii | |
11529 <I>AO, OD</I> and the tangents at <I>D, A</I> | |
11530 is then the ‘applied’ rectangle, and | |
11531 the rectangle by which it falls short is also a square and equal | |
11532 <pb n=303><head>TWO GEOMETRICAL PASSAGES IN THE <I>MENO</I></head> | |
11533 to the other square. If this were the correct interpretation, | |
11534 Plato is using much too general language about the applied | |
11535 rectangle and that by which it is deficient; it would be | |
11536 extraordinary that he should express the condition in this | |
11537 elaborate way when he need only have said that the radius | |
11538 of the circle must be equal to the side of the square and | |
11539 therefore 2 feet in length. The explanation seems to me | |
11540 incredible. The criterion sought by Socrates is evidently | |
11541 intended to be a real <G>diorismo/s</G>, or determination of the | |
11542 conditions or limits of the possibility of a solution of the pro- | |
11543 blem whether in its original form or in the form to which | |
11544 it is reduced; but it is no real <G>diorismo/s</G> to say what is | |
11545 equivalent to saying that the problem is possible of solution | |
11546 if the circle is of a particular size, but impossible if the circle | |
11547 is greater or less than that size. | |
11548 <p>The passage incidentally shows that the idea of a formal | |
11549 <G>diorismo/s</G> defining the limits of possibility of solution was | |
11550 familiar even before Plato's time, and therefore that Proclus | |
11551 must be in error when he says that Leon, the pupil of | |
11552 Neoclides, ‘<I>invented</I> <G>diorismoi/</G> (determining) when the problem | |
11553 which is the subject of investigation is possible and when | |
11554 impossible’,<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 66. 20-2.</note> although Leon may have been the first to intro- | |
11555 duce the term or to recognize formally the essential part | |
11556 played by <G>diorismoi/</G> in geometry. | |
11557 <C>(<G>e</G>) <I>Plato and the doubling of the cube.</I></C> | |
11558 <p>The story of Plato's relation to the problem of doubling | |
11559 the cube has already been told (pp. 245-6, 255). Although the | |
11560 solution attributed to him is not his, it may have been with | |
11561 this problem in view that he complained that the study of | |
11562 solid geometry had been unduly neglected up to his time.<note><I>Republic</I>, vii. 528 A-C.</note> | |
11563 <pb n=304><head>PLATO</head> | |
11564 <C>(<G>z</G>) <I>Solution of <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>z</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> in integers</I></C>. | |
11565 <p>We have already seen (p. 81) that Plato is credited with | |
11566 a rule (complementary to the similar rule attributed to Pytha- | |
11567 goras) for finding a whole series of square numbers the sum | |
11568 of which is also a square; the formula is | |
11569 <MATH>(2 <I>n</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>-1)<SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>n</I><SUP>2</SUP>+1)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
11570 <C>(<G>h</G>) <I>Incommensurables</I>.</C> | |
11571 <p>On the subject of incommensurables or irrationals we have | |
11572 first the passage of the <I>Theaetetus</I> recordin that Theodorus | |
11573 proved the incommensurability of √3, √5 ... √17, after | |
11574 which Theaetetus generalized the theory of such ‘roots’. | |
11575 This passage has already been fully discussed (pp. 203-9). | |
11576 The subject of incommensurables comes up again in the <I>Laws,</I> | |
11577 where Plato inveighs against the ignorance prevailing among | |
11578 the Greeks of his time of the fact that lengths, breadths and | |
11579 depths may be incommensurable as well as commensurable | |
11580 with one another, and appears to imply that he himself had | |
11581 not learnt the fact till late (<G>a)kou/sas o)ye/ pote</G>), so that he | |
11582 was ashamed for himself as well as for his countrymen in | |
11583 general.<note><I>Laws,</I> 819 D-820 C.</note> But the irrationals known to Plato included more | |
11584 than mere ‘surds’ or the sides of non-squares; in one place | |
11585 he says that, just as an even number may be the sum of | |
11586 either two odd or two even numbers, the sum of two irra- | |
11587 tionals may be either rational or irrational.<note><I>Hippias Maior,</I> 303 B, C.</note> An obvious | |
11588 illustration of the former case is afforded by a rational straight | |
11589 line divided ‘in extreme and mean ratio’. Euclid (XIII. 6) | |
11590 proves that each of the segments is a particular kind of | |
11591 irrational straight line called by him in Book X an <I>apotome</I>; | |
11592 and to suppose that the irrationality of the two segments was | |
11593 already known to Plato is natural enough if we are correct in | |
11594 supposing that ‘the theorems which’ (in the words of Proclus) | |
11595 ‘Plato originated regarding <I>the section</I>’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 67. 6.</note> were theorems about | |
11596 what came to be called the ‘golden section’, namely the | |
11597 division of a straight line in extreme and mean ratio as in | |
11598 Eucl. II. 11 and VI. 30. The appearance of the latter problem | |
11599 in Book II, the content of which is probably all Pythagorean, | |
11600 suggests that the incommensurability of the segments with | |
11601 <pb n=305><head>INCOMMENSURABLES</head> | |
11602 the whole line was discovered before Plato's time, if not as | |
11603 early as the irrationality of √2. | |
11604 <C>(<G>q</G>) <I>The Geometrical Number</I>.</C> | |
11605 <p>This is not the place to discuss at length the famous passage | |
11606 about the Geometrical Number in the <I>Republic.</I><note><I>Republic,</I> viii. 546 B-D. The number of interpretations of this passage | |
11607 is legion. For an exhaustive discussion of the language as well as for | |
11608 one of the best interpretations that has been put forward, see Dr. Adam's | |
11609 edition of the <I>Republic,</I> vol. ii, pp. 204-8, 264-312.</note> Nor is its | |
11610 mathematical content of importance; the whole thing is | |
11611 mystic rather than mathematical, and is expressed in | |
11612 rhapsodical language, veiling by fanciful phraseology a few | |
11613 simple mathematical conceptions. The numbers mentioned | |
11614 are supposed to be two. Hultsch and Adam arrive at the | |
11615 same two numbers, though by different routes. The first | |
11616 of these numbers is 216, which according to Adam is the sum | |
11617 of three cubes 3<SUP>3</SUP>+4<SUP>3</SUP>+5<SUP>3</SUP>; 2<SUP>3</SUP>.3<SUP>3</SUP> is the form in which | |
11618 Hultsch obtains it.<note>The Greek is <G>e)n w=( prw/tw| au)xh/seis duna/menai/ te kai\ dunasteuo/menai, trei=s | |
11619 a)posta/seis, te/ttaras de\ o(/rous labou=sai o(moiou/ntwn te kai\ a)nomoiou/ntwn kai\ | |
11620 au)xo/ntwn kai\ fqino/ntwn, pa/nta prosh/gora kai\ r(hta\ pro\s a)/llhla a)pe/fhnan</G>, | |
11621 which Adam translates by ‘the first number in which root and | |
11622 square increases, comprehending three distances and four limits, of | |
11623 elements that make like and unlike and wax and wane, render all | |
11624 things conversable and rational with one another’. <G>au)xh/seis</G> are | |
11625 clearly multiplications. <G>duna/menai/ te kai\ dunasteuo/menai</G> are explained in | |
11626 this way. A straight line is said <G>du/nasqai</G> (‘to be capable of’) an area, | |
11627 e.g. a rectangle, when the square on it is equal to the rectangle; hence | |
11628 <G>duname/nh</G> should mean a side of a square. <G>dunasteuome/nh</G> represents a sort | |
11629 of passive of <G>duname/nh</G>, meaning that of which the <G>duname/nh</G> is ‘capable’; | |
11630 hence Adam takes it here to be the square of which the <G>duname/nh</G> is the | |
11631 side, and the whole expression to mean the product of a square and its | |
11632 side, i.e. simply the cube of the side. The cubes 3<SUP>3</SUP>, 4<SUP>3</SUP>, 5<SUP>3</SUP> are supposed | |
11633 to be meant because the words in the description of the second number | |
11634 ‘of which the ratio in its lowest terms 4:3 when joined to 5’ clearly | |
11635 refer to the right-angled triangle 3, 4, 5, and because at least three | |
11636 authors, Plutarch (<I>De Is. et Os.</I> 373 F), Proclus (on Eucl. I, p. 428. 1) and | |
11637 Aristides Quintilianus (<I>De mus.,</I> p. 152 Meibom. = p. 90 Jahn) say that | |
11638 <FIG> | |
11639 Plato used the Pythagorean or ‘cosmic’ triangle in | |
11640 his Number. The ‘three distances’ are regarded | |
11641 as ‘dimensions’, and the ‘three distances and | |
11642 four limits’ are held to confirm the interpretation | |
11643 ‘cube’, because a solid (parallelepiped) was said to | |
11644 have ‘three dimensions and four limits’ (<I>Theol. Ar.,</I> | |
11645 p. 16 Ast, and Iambl. <I>in Nicom.,</I> p. 93. 10), the limits | |
11646 being bounding points as <I>A, B, C, D</I> in the accom- | |
11647 panying figure. ‘Making like and unlike’ is sup- | |
11648 posed to refer to the square and oblong forms in which the second | |
11649 number is stated. | |
11650 <p>Another view of the whole passage has recently appeared (A. G. Laird, | |
11651 <I>Plato's Geometrical Number and the comment of Proclus,</I> Madison, Wiscon- | |
11652 sin, 1918). Like all other solutions, it is open to criticism in some | |
11653 details, but it is attractive in so far as it makes greater use of Proclus | |
11654 (<I>in Platonis remp.,</I> vol. ii, p. 36 seq. Kroll) and especially of the passage | |
11655 (p. 40) in which he illustrates the formation of the ‘harmonies’ by means | |
11656 of geometrical figures. According to Mr. Laird there are not <I>two</I> separ- | |
11657 ate numbers, and the description from which Hultsch and Adam derive | |
11658 the number 216 is not a description of a number but a statement of a | |
11659 general method of formation of ‘harmonies’, which is then applied to | |
11660 the triangle 3, 4, 5 as a particular case, in order to produce the one | |
11661 Geometrical Number. The basis of the whole thing is the use of figures | |
11662 like that of Eucl. VI. 8 (a right-angled triangle divided by a perpendicular | |
11663 from the right angle on the opposite side into two right-angled triangles | |
11664 similar to one another and to the original triangle). Let <I>ABC</I> be a | |
11665 right-angled triangle in which the sides <I>CB, BA</I> containing the right | |
11666 <FIG> | |
11667 angle are rational numbers <I>a, b</I> respectively. | |
11668 Draw <I>AF</I> at right angles to <I>AC</I> meeting <I>CB</I> | |
11669 produced in <I>F.</I> Then the figure <I>AFC</I> is that of | |
11670 Eucl. VI. 8, and of course <MATH><I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>CB.BF</I></MATH>. | |
11671 Complete the rectangle <I>ABFL,</I> and produce | |
11672 <I>FL, CA</I> to meet at <I>K.</I> Then, by similar tri- | |
11673 angles, <I>CB, BA, FB</I> (=<I>AL</I>) and <I>KL</I> are four | |
11674 straight lines in continued proportion, and their | |
11675 lengths are <I>a, b, b</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>a, b</I><SUP>3</SUP>/<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP> respectively. Mul- | |
11676 tiplying throughout by <I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP> in order to get rid of | |
11677 fractions, we may take the lengths to be <I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>, | |
11678 <I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b, ab</I><SUP>2</SUP>, <I>b</I><SUP>3</SUP> respectively. Now, on Mr. Laird's | |
11679 view, <G>au)xh/seis duna/menai</G> are <I>squares,</I> as <I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>, and | |
11680 <G>au)xh/seis dunasteuo/menai</G> <I>rectangles</I>, as <I>FB, BC, to | |
11681 which the squares are equal.</I> ‘Making like and | |
11682 unlike’ refers to the equal factors of <I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>, <I>b</I><SUP>3</SUP> and the unequal factors of | |
11683 <I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b, ab</I><SUP>2</SUP>; the terms <I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>, <I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>b, ab</I><SUP>2</SUP>, <I>b</I><SUP>3</SUP> are four <I>terms</I> (<G>o(/roi</G>) of a continued | |
11684 proportion with three <I>intervals</I> (<G>a)posta/seis</G>), and of course are all ‘con- | |
11685 versable and rational with one another’. (Incidentally, out of such | |
11686 terms we can even obtain the number 216, for if we put <I>a</I>=2, <I>b</I>=3, we | |
11687 have 8, 12, 18, 27, and the product of the extremes 8.27=the product | |
11688 of the means 12.18=216). Applying the method to the triangle 3, 4, 5 | |
11689 (as Proclus does) we have the terms 27, 36, 48, 64, and the first three | |
11690 numbers, multiplied respectively by 100, give the elements of the | |
11691 Geometrical Number 3600<SUP>2</SUP>=2700.4800. On this interpretation <G>tri\s | |
11692 au)xhqei/s</G> simply means raised to the third dimension or ‘made solid’ (as | |
11693 Aristotle says, <I>Politics</I> *q (E). 12, 1316 a 8), the factors being of course | |
11694 3.3.3=27, 3.3.4=36, and 3.4.4=48; and ‘the ratio 4:3 joined | |
11695 to 5’ does not mean either the product or the sum of 3, 4, 5, but simply | |
11696 the triangle 3, 4, 5.</note> | |
11697 <pb n=306><head>PLATO</head> | |
11698 <p>The second number is described thus: | |
11699 <p>‘The ratio 4:3 in its lowest terms (‘the base’, <G>puqmh/n</G>, of | |
11700 the ratio <G>e)pi/tritos</G>) joined or wedded to 5 yields two harmonies | |
11701 when thrice increased (<G>tri\s au)xhqei/s</G>), the one equal an equal | |
11702 number of times, so many times 100, the other of equal length | |
11703 one way, but oblong, consisting on the one hand of 100 squares | |
11704 of rational diameters of 5 diminished by one each or, if of | |
11705 <pb n=307><head>THE GEOMETRICAL NUMBER</head> | |
11706 irrational diameters, by two, and on the other hand of 100 | |
11707 cubes of 3.’ | |
11708 <p>The ratio 4:3 must be taken in the sense of ‘the numbers | |
11709 4 and 3’, and Adam takes ‘joined with 5’ to mean that 4, 3 | |
11710 and 5 are multiplied together, making 60; 60 ‘thrice increased’ | |
11711 he interprets as ‘60 thrice multiplied by 60’, that is to say, | |
11712 60x60x60x60 or 3600<SUP>2</SUP>; ‘so many times 100’ must then | |
11713 be the ‘equal’ side of this, or 36 times 100; this 3600<SUP>2</SUP>, or | |
11714 12960000, is one of the ‘harmonies’. The other is the same | |
11715 number expressed as the product of two unequal factors, an | |
11716 ‘oblong’ number; the first factor is 100 times a number | |
11717 which can be described either as 1 less than the square of the | |
11718 ‘rational diameter of 5’, or as 2 less than the square of | |
11719 the ‘irrational diameter’ of 5, where the irrational diameter | |
11720 of 5 is the diameter of a square of side 5, i. e. √50, and the | |
11721 rational diameter is the nearest whole number to this, namely | |
11722 7, so that the number which is multiplied by 100 is 49-1, or | |
11723 50-2, i. e. 48, and the first factor is therefore 4800; the | |
11724 second factor is 100 cubes of 3, or 2700; and of course | |
11725 <MATH>4800x2700=3600<SUP>2</SUP></MATH> or 12960000. Hultsch obtains the side, | |
11726 3600, of the first ‘harmony’ in another way; he takes 4 and 3 | |
11727 joined to 5 to be the <I>sum</I> of 4, 3 and 5, i. e. 12, and <G>tri\s au)xhqei/s</G>, | |
11728 ‘thrice increased’, to mean that the 12 is ‘multiplied by three’ | |
11729 <note>Adam maintains that <G>tri\s au)xhqei/s</G> cannot mean ‘multiplied by 3’. He | |
11730 observes (p. 278, note) that the Greek for ‘multiplied by 3’, if we | |
11731 use <G>au)xa/nw</G>, would be <G>tria/di au)xhqei/s</G>, this being the construction used by | |
11732 Nicomachus (ii. 15. 2 <G>i(/na o( q tri\s g w)\n pa/lin tria/di e)p) a)/llo dia/sthma | |
11733 au)xhqh= kai\ ge/nhtai o( kz</G>) and in <I>Theol. Ar.</I> (p. 39, Ast <G>e(xa/di au)xhqei/s</G>). Never- | |
11734 theless I think that <G>tri\s au)xhqei/s</G> would not be an unnatural expression for | |
11735 a mathematician to use for ‘multiplied by 3’, let alone Plato in a passage | |
11736 like this. It is to be noted that <G>pollaplasia/zw</G> and <G>pollapla/sios</G> are | |
11737 likewise commonly used with the dative of the multiplier; yet <G>i)sa/kis | |
11738 pollapla/sios</G> is the regular expression for ‘equimultiple’. And <G>au)xa/nw</G> is | |
11739 actually found with <G>tosauta/kis</G>: see Pappus ii, p. 28. 15, 22, where <G>tosau- | |
11740 ta/kis au)xh/somen</G> means ‘we have to multiply by such a power’ of 10000 or | |
11741 of 10 (although it is true that the chapter in which the expression occurs | |
11742 may be a late addition to Pappus's original text). On the whole, I prefer | |
11743 Hultsch's interpretation to Adam's. <G>tri\s au)xhqei/s</G> can hardly mean that | |
11744 60 is raised to the <I>fourth</I> power, 60<SUP>4</SUP>; and if it did, ‘so many times 100’, | |
11745 immediately following the expression for 3600<SUP>2</SUP>, would be pointless and | |
11746 awkward. On the other hand, ‘so many times 100’ following the ex- | |
11747 pression for 36 would naturally indicate 3600.</note> | |
11748 making 36; ‘so many times 100’ is then 36 times 100, or 3600. | |
11749 <p>But the main interest of the passage from the historical | |
11750 <pb n=308><head>PLATO</head> | |
11751 point of view lies in the terms ‘rational’ and ‘irrational | |
11752 diameter of 5’. A fair approximation to √2 was obtained | |
11753 by selecting a square number such that, if 2 be multiplied by | |
11754 it, the product is nearly a square; 25 is such a square number, | |
11755 since 25 times 2, or 50, only differs by 1 from 7<SUP>2</SUP>; conse- | |
11756 quently 7/5 is an approximation to √2. It may have been | |
11757 arrived at in the tentative way here indicated; we cannot | |
11758 doubt that it was current in Plato's time; nay, we know that | |
11759 the general solution of the equations | |
11760 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=±1</MATH> | |
11761 by means of successive ‘side-’ and ‘diameter-’ numbers was | |
11762 Pythagorean, and Plato was therefore, here as in so many | |
11763 other places, ‘Pythagorizing’. | |
11764 <p>The diameter is again mentioned in the <I>Politicus,</I> where | |
11765 Plato speaks of ‘the diameter which is in square (<G>duna/mei</G>) | |
11766 two feet’, meaning the diagonal of the square with side | |
11767 1 foot, and again of the diameter of the square on this | |
11768 diameter, i.e. the diagonal of a square 2 square feet in area, | |
11769 in other words, the side of a square 4 square feet in area, | |
11770 or a straight line 2 feet in length.<note><I>Politicus,</I> 266 B.</note> | |
11771 <p>Enough has been said to show that Plato was abreast of | |
11772 the mathematics of his day, and we can understand the | |
11773 remark of Proclus on the influence which he exerted upon | |
11774 students and workers in that field: | |
11775 <p>‘he caused mathematics in general and geometry in particular | |
11776 to make a very great advance by reason of his enthusiasm | |
11777 for them, which of course is obvious from the way in which | |
11778 he filled his books with mathematical illustrations and every- | |
11779 where tries to kindle admiration for these subjects in those | |
11780 who make a pursuit of philosophy.’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 66. 8-14.</note> | |
11781 <C>Mathematical ‘arts’</C>. | |
11782 <p>Besides the purely theoretical subjects, Plato recognizes the | |
11783 practical or applied mathematical ‘arts’; along with arith- | |
11784 metic, he mentions the art of measurement (for purposes of | |
11785 trade or craftsmanship) and that of weighing<note><I>Philebus,</I> 55 E-56 E.</note>; in the former | |
11786 connexion he speaks of the instruments of the craftsman, | |
11787 the circle-drawer (<G>to/rnos</G>), the compasses (<G>diabh/ths</G>), the rule | |
11788 <pb n=309><head>MATHEMATICAL ‘ARTS’</head> | |
11789 (<G>sta/qmh</G>) and ‘a certain elaborate <G>prosagw/gion</G>’ (? approxi- | |
11790 mator). The art of weighing, he says,<note><I>Charmides,</I> 166 B.</note> ‘is concerned with | |
11791 the heavier and lighter weight’, as ‘logistic’ deals with odd | |
11792 and even in their relation to one another, and geometry with | |
11793 magnitudes greater and less or equal; in the <I>Protagoras</I> he | |
11794 speaks of the man skilled in weighing | |
11795 <p>‘who puts together first the pleasant, and second the painful | |
11796 things, and adjusts the near and the far on the balance’<note><I>Protagoras,</I> 356 B.</note>; | |
11797 <p>the principle of the lever was therefore known to Plato, who | |
11798 was doubtless acquainted with the work of Archytas, the | |
11799 reputed founder of the science of mechanics.<note>Diog. L. viii. 83.</note> | |
11800 <C>(<I>a</I>) <I>Optics.</I></C> | |
11801 <p>In the physical portion of the <I>Timaeus</I> Plato gives his | |
11802 explanation of the working of the sense organs. The account | |
11803 of the process of vision and the relation of vision to the | |
11804 light of day is interesting,<note><I>Timaeus,</I> 45 B-46 C.</note> and at the end of it is a reference | |
11805 to the properties of mirrors, which is perhaps the first indica- | |
11806 tion of a science of optics. When, says Plato, we see a thing | |
11807 in a mirror, the fire belonging to the face combines about the | |
11808 bright surface of the mirror with the fire in the visual current; | |
11809 the right portion of the face appears as the left in the image | |
11810 seen, and vice versa, because it is the mutually opposite parts | |
11811 of the visual current and of the object seen which come into | |
11812 contact, contrary to the usual mode of impact. (That is, if you | |
11813 imagine your reflection in the mirror to be another person | |
11814 looking at you, <I>his</I> left eye is the image of your right, and the | |
11815 left side of <I>his</I> left eye is the image of the right side of your | |
11816 right.) But, on the other hand, the right side really becomes | |
11817 the right side and the left the left when the light in com- | |
11818 bination with that with which it combines is transferred from | |
11819 one side to the other; this happens when the smooth part | |
11820 of the mirror is higher at the sides than in the middle (i. e. the | |
11821 mirror is a hollow cylindrical mirror held with its axis | |
11822 vertical), and so diverts the right portion of the visual current | |
11823 to the left and vice versa. And if you turn the mirror so that | |
11824 its axis is horizontal, everything appears upside down. | |
11825 <pb n=310><head>PLATO</head> | |
11826 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>Music.</I></C> | |
11827 <p>In music Plato had the advantage of the researches of | |
11828 Archytas and the Pythagorean school into the numerical | |
11829 relations of tones. In the <I>Timaeus</I> we find an elaborate | |
11830 filling up of intervals by the interposition of arithmetic and | |
11831 harmonic means<note><I>Timaeus</I>, 35 C-36 B.</note>; Plato is also clear that higher and lower | |
11832 pitch are due to the more or less rapid motion of the air.<note><I>Ib.</I> 67 B.</note> | |
11833 In like manner the different notes in the ‘harmony of the | |
11834 spheres’, poetically turned into Sirens sitting on each of the | |
11835 eight whorls of the Spindle and each uttering a single sound, | |
11836 a single musical note, correspond to the different speeds of | |
11837 the eight circles, that of the fixed stars and those of the sun, | |
11838 the moon, and the five planets respectively.<note><I>Republic,</I> 617 B.</note> | |
11839 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Astronomy.</I></C> | |
11840 <p>This brings us to Plato's astronomy. His views are stated | |
11841 in their most complete and final form in the <I>Timaeus,</I> though | |
11842 account has to be taken of other dialogues, the <I>Phaedo,</I> the | |
11843 <I>Republic,</I> and the <I>Laws.</I> He based himself upon the early | |
11844 Pythagorean system (that of Pythagoras, as distinct from | |
11845 that of his successors, who were the first to abandon the | |
11846 geocentric system and made the earth, with the sun, the | |
11847 moon and the other planets, revolve in circles about the ‘cen- | |
11848 tral fire’); while of course he would take account of the | |
11849 results of the more and more exact observations made up | |
11850 to his own time. According to Plato, the universe has the | |
11851 most perfect of all shapes, that of a sphere. In the centre | |
11852 of this sphere rests the earth, immovable and kept there by | |
11853 the equilibrium of symmetry as it were (‘for a thing in | |
11854 equilibrium in the middle of any uniform substance will not | |
11855 have cause to incline more or less in any direction’<note><I>Phaedo,</I> 109 A.</note>). The | |
11856 axis of the sphere of the universe passes through the centre of | |
11857 the earth, which is also spherical, and the sphere revolves | |
11858 uniformly about the axis in the direction from east to west. | |
11859 The fixed stars are therefore carried round in small circles | |
11860 of the sphere. The sun, the moon and the five planets are | |
11861 also carried round in the motion of the outer sphere, but they | |
11862 have independent circular movements of their own in addition. | |
11863 <pb n=311><head>ASTRONOMY</head> | |
11864 These latter movements take place in a plane which cuts | |
11865 at an angle the equator of the heavenly sphere; the several | |
11866 orbits are parts of what Plato calls the ‘circle of the Other’, | |
11867 as distinguished from the ‘circle of the Same’, which is the | |
11868 daily revolution of the heavenly sphere as a whole and which, | |
11869 carrying the circle of the Other and the seven movements | |
11870 therein along with it, has the mastery over them. The result | |
11871 of the combination of the two movements in the case of any | |
11872 one planet is to twist its actual path in space into a spiral<note><I>Timaeus,</I> 38 E-39 B.</note>; | |
11873 the spiral is of course included between two planes parallel to | |
11874 that of the equator at a distance equal to the maximum | |
11875 deviation of the planet in its course from the equator on | |
11876 either side. The speeds with which the sun, the moon and | |
11877 the five planets describe their own orbits (independently | |
11878 of the daily rotation) are in the following order; the moon is | |
11879 the quickest; the sun is the next quickest and Venus and | |
11880 Mercury travel in company with it, each of the three taking | |
11881 about a year to describe its orbit; the next in speed is Mars, | |
11882 the next Jupiter, and the last and slowest is Saturn; the | |
11883 speeds are of course angular speeds, not linear. The order | |
11884 of distances from the earth is, beginning with the nearest, | |
11885 as follows: moon, sun, Venus, Mercury, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn. | |
11886 In the <I>Republic</I> all these heavenly bodies describe their own | |
11887 orbits in a sense opposite to that of the daily rotation, i. e. in | |
11888 the direction from west to east; this is what we should | |
11889 expect; but in the <I>Timaeus</I> we are distinctly told, in one | |
11890 place, that the seven circles move ‘in opposite senses to one | |
11891 another’,<note><I>Ib.</I> 36 D.</note> and, in another place, that Venus and Mercury | |
11892 have ‘the contrary tendency’ to the sun.<note><I>Ib.</I> 38 D.</note> This peculiar | |
11893 phrase has not been satisfactorily interpreted. The two state- | |
11894 ments taken together in their literal sense appear to imply | |
11895 that Plato actually regarded Venus and Mercury as describing | |
11896 their orbits the contrary way to the sun, incredible as this | |
11897 may appear (for on this hypothesis the angles of divergence | |
11898 between the two planets and the sun would be capable of any | |
11899 value up to 180°, whereas observation shows that they are | |
11900 never far from the sun). Proclus and others refer to attempts | |
11901 to explain the passages by means of the theory of epicycles; | |
11902 Chalcidius in particular indicates that the sun's motion on its | |
11903 <pb n=312><head>PLATO</head> | |
11904 epicycle (which is from east to west) is in the contrary sense | |
11905 to the motion of Venus and Mercury on their epicycles | |
11906 respectively (which is from west to east)<note>Chalcidius on <I>Timaeus,</I> cc. 81, 109, 112.</note>; and this would | |
11907 be a satisfactory explanation if Plato could be supposed to | |
11908 have been acquainted with the theory of epicycles. But the | |
11909 probabilities are entirely against the latter supposition. All, | |
11910 therefore, that can be said seems to be this. Heraclides of | |
11911 Pontus, Plato's famous pupil, is known on clear evidence to | |
11912 have discovered that Venus and Mercury revolve round the | |
11913 sun like satellites. He may have come to the same conclusion | |
11914 about the superior planets, but this is not certain; and in any | |
11915 case he must have made the discovery with reference to | |
11916 Mercury and Venus first. Heraclides's discovery meant that | |
11917 Venus and Mercury, while accompanying the sun in its annual | |
11918 motion, described what are really epicycles about it. Now | |
11919 discoveries of this sort are not made without some preliminary | |
11920 seeking, and it may have been some vague inkling of the | |
11921 truth that prompted the remark of Plato, whatever the precise | |
11922 meaning of the words. | |
11923 <p>The differences between the angular speeds of the planets | |
11924 account for the overtakings of one planet by another, and | |
11925 the combination of their independent motions with that of the | |
11926 daily rotation causes one planet to <I>appear</I> to be overtaking | |
11927 another when it is really being overtaken by it and vice | |
11928 versa.<note><I>Timaeus,</I> 39 A.</note> The sun, moon and planets are instruments for | |
11929 measuring time.<note><I>Ib.</I> 41 E, 42 D.</note> Even the earth is an instrument for making | |
11930 night and day by virtue of its <I>not</I> rotating about its axis, | |
11931 while the rotation of the fixed stars carrying the sun with | |
11932 it is completed once in twenty-four hours; a month has passed | |
11933 when the moon after completing her own orbit overtakes the | |
11934 sun (the ‘month’ being therefore the <I>synodic</I> month), and | |
11935 a year when the sun has completed its own circle. According | |
11936 to Plato the time of revolution of the other planets (except | |
11937 Venus and Mercury, which have the same speed as the sun) | |
11938 had not been exactly calculated; nevertheless the Perfect | |
11939 Year is completed ‘when the relative speeds of all the eight | |
11940 revolutions [the seven independent revolutions and the daily | |
11941 rotation] accomplish their course together and reach their | |
11942 <pb n=313><head>ASTRONOMY</head> | |
11943 starting-point’.<note><I>Timaeus,</I> 39 B-D.</note> There was apparently a tradition that the | |
11944 Great Year of Plato was 36000 years: this corresponds to | |
11945 the minimum estimate of the precession of the equinoxes | |
11946 quoted by Ptolemy from Hipparchus's treatise on the length | |
11947 of the year, namely at least one-hundredth of a degree in | |
11948 a year, or 1° in 100 years,<note>Ptolemy, <I>Syntaxis,</I> vii. 2, vol. ii, p. 15. 9-17, Heib.</note> that is to say, 360° in 36000 years. | |
11949 The period is connected by Adam with the Geometrical Num- | |
11950 ber 12960000 because this number of days, at the rate of 360 | |
11951 days in the year, makes 36000 years. The coincidence may, | |
11952 it is true, have struck Ptolemy and made him describe the | |
11953 Great Year arrived at on the basis of 1° per 100 years | |
11954 as the ‘Platonic’ year; but there is nothing to show that | |
11955 Plato himself calculated a Great Year with reference to pre- | |
11956 cession: on the contrary, precession was first discovered by | |
11957 Hipparchus. | |
11958 <p>As regards the distances of the sun, moon and planets | |
11959 Plato has nothing more definite than that the seven circles | |
11960 are ‘in the proportion of the double intervals, three of each’<note><I>Timaeus,</I> 36 D.</note>: | |
11961 the reference is to the Pythagorean <G>tetraktu/s</G> represented in | |
11962 <FIG> | |
11963 the annexed figure, the numbers after 1 being | |
11964 on the one side successive powers of 2, and on | |
11965 the other side successive powers of 3. This | |
11966 gives 1, 2, 3, 4, 8, 9, 27 in ascending order. | |
11967 What precise estimate of relative distances | |
11968 Plato based upon these figures is uncertain. | |
11969 It is generally supposed (1) that the radii of the successive | |
11970 orbits are in the ratio of the numbers; but (2) Chalcidius | |
11971 considered that 2, 3, 4 ... are the successive differences | |
11972 between these radii,<note>Chalcidius on <I>Timaeus,</I> c. 96, p. 167, Wrobel</note> so that the radii themselves are in | |
11973 the ratios of 1, <MATH>1+2=3, 1+2+3=6</MATH>, &c.; and again (3), | |
11974 according to Macrobius,<note>Macrobius, <I>In somn. Scip.</I> ii. 3. 14.</note> the Platonists held that the successive | |
11975 radii are as 1, 1.2=2, 1.2.3=6, 6.4=24, 24.9=216, | |
11976 216.8=1728 and 1728.27=46656. In any case the | |
11977 figures have no basis in observation. | |
11978 <p>We have said that Plato made the earth occupy the centre | |
11979 of the universe and gave it no movement of any kind. Other | |
11980 <pb n=314><head>PLATO</head> | |
11981 views, however, have been attributed to Plato by later writers. | |
11982 In the <I>Timacus</I> Plato had used of the earth the expression | |
11983 which has usually been translated ‘our nurse, globed (<G>i)llo- | |
11984 me/nhn</G>) round the axis stretched from pole to pole through | |
11985 the universe’.<note><I>Timaeus,</I> 40 B.</note> It is well known that Aristotle refers to the | |
11986 passage in these terms: | |
11987 <p>‘Some say that the earth, actually lying at the centre (<G>kai\ | |
11988 keime/nhn e)pi\ tou= ke/ntrou</G>), is yet wound <I>and moves</I> (<G>i)/llesqai | |
11989 kai\ kinei=sqai</G>) about the axis stretched through the universe | |
11990 from pole to pole.’<note>Arist. <I>De caelo,</I> ii. 13, 293 b 20; cf. ii. 14, 296 a 25.</note> | |
11991 <p>This naturally implies that Aristotle attributed to Plato | |
11992 the view that the earth rotates about its axis. Such a view | |
11993 is, however, entirely inconsistent with the whole system | |
11994 described in the <I>Timaeus</I> (and also in the <I>Laws,</I> which Plato | |
11995 did not live to finish), where it is the sphere of the fixed | |
11996 stars which by its revolution about the earth in 24 hours | |
11997 makes night and day; moreover, there is no reason to doubt | |
11998 the evidence that it was Heraclides of Pontus who was the | |
11999 first to affirm the rotation of the earth about its own axis | |
12000 in 24 hours. The natural inference seems to be that Aristotle | |
12001 either misunderstood or misrepresented Plato, the ambiguity | |
12002 of the word <G>i)llome/nhn</G> being the contributing cause or the | |
12003 pretext as the case may be. There are, however, those who | |
12004 maintain that Aristotle <I>must</I> have known what Plato meant | |
12005 and was incapable of misrepresenting him on a subject like | |
12006 this. Among these is Professor Burnet,<note><I>Greek Philosophy,</I> Part I, Thales to Plato, pp. 347-8.</note> who, being satisfied | |
12007 that Aristotle understood <G>i)llome/nhn</G> to mean motion of some | |
12008 sort, and on the strength of a new reading which he has | |
12009 adopted from two MSS. of the first class, has essayed a new | |
12010 interpretation of Plato's phrase. The new reading differs | |
12011 from the former texts in having the article <G>th\n</G> after | |
12012 <G>i)llome/nhn</G>, which makes the phrase run thus, <G>gh=n de\ trofo\n | |
12013 me\n h(mete/ran, i)llome/nhn de\ th\n peri\ to\n dia\ panto\s po/lon | |
12014 tetame/non</G>. Burnet, holding that we can only supply with | |
12015 <G>th\n</G> some word like <G>o(do/n</G>, understands <G>peri/odon</G> or <G>perifora/n</G>, | |
12016 and translates ‘earth our nurse going to and fro on its path | |
12017 round the axis which stretches right through the universe’. | |
12018 <pb n=315><head>ASTRONOMY</head> | |
12019 In confirmation of this Burnet cites the ‘unimpeachable | |
12020 testimony’ of Theophrastus, who said that | |
12021 ‘Plato in his old age repented of having given the earth | |
12022 the central place in the universe, to which it had no right’<note>Plutarch, <I>Quaest. Plat.</I> 8. 1, 1006 c; cf. <I>Life of Numa,</I> c. 11.</note>; | |
12023 and he concludes that, according to Plato in the <I>Timaeus,</I> | |
12024 the earth is not the centre of the universe. But the sentences | |
12025 in which Aristotle paraphrases the <G>i)llome/nhn</G> in the <I>Timaeus</I> | |
12026 by the words <G>i)/llesqai kai\ kinei=sqai</G> both make it clear that | |
12027 the persons who held the view in question also declared | |
12028 that the earth <I>lies</I> or <I>is placed at the centre</I> (<G>keime/nhn e)pi\ | |
12029 tou= ke/ntrou</G>), or ‘placed the earth at the centre’ (<G>e)pi\ tou= me/sou | |
12030 qe/ntes</G>). Burnet's explanation is therefore in contradiction to | |
12031 part of Aristotle's statement, if not to the rest; so that he | |
12032 does not appear to have brought the question much nearer | |
12033 to a solution. Perhaps some one will suggest that the rotation | |
12034 or oscillation about the axis of the universe is <I>small,</I> so small | |
12035 as to be fairly consistent with the statement that the earth | |
12036 remains at the centre. Better, I think, admit that, on our | |
12037 present information, the puzzle is insoluble. | |
12038 <p>The dictum of Theophrastus that Plato in his old age | |
12039 repented of having placed the earth in the centre is incon- | |
12040 sistent with the theory of the <I>Timaeus,</I> as we have said. | |
12041 Boeckh explained it as a misapprehension. There appear | |
12042 to have been among Plato's immediate successors some who | |
12043 altered Plato's system in a Pythagorean sense and who may | |
12044 be alluded to in another passage of the <I>De caelo</I><note>Arist. <I>De caelo,</I> ii. 13, 293 a 27-b 1.</note>; Boeckh | |
12045 suggested, therefore, that the views of these Pythagorizing | |
12046 Platonists may have been put down to Plato himself. But | |
12047 the tendency now seems to be to accept the testimony of | |
12048 Theophrastus literally. Heiberg does so, and so does Burnet, | |
12049 who thinks it probable that Theophrastus heard the statement | |
12050 which he attributes to Plato from Plato himself. But I would | |
12051 point out that, if the <I>Timaeus,</I> as Burnet contends, contained | |
12052 Plato's explicit recantation of his former view that the earth | |
12053 was at the centre, there was no need to supplement it by an | |
12054 oral communication to Theophrastus. In any case the question | |
12055 has no particular importance in comparison with the develop- | |
12056 ments which have next to be described. | |
12057 <pb><C>X | |
12058 FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</C> | |
12059 <p>WHATEVER original work Plato himself did in mathematics | |
12060 (and it may not have been much), there is no doubt that his | |
12061 enthusiasm for the subject in all branches and the pre-eminent | |
12062 place which he gave it in his system had enormous influence | |
12063 upon its development in his lifetime and the period following. | |
12064 In astronomy we are told that Plato set it as a problem to | |
12065 all earnest students to find ‘what are the uniform and ordered | |
12066 movements by the assumption of which the apparent move- | |
12067 ments of the planets can be accounted for’; our authority for | |
12068 this is Sosigenes, who had it from Eudemus.<note>Simpl. on <I>De caelo</I>, ii. 12 (292 b 10), p. 488. 20-34, Heib.</note> One answer | |
12069 to this, representing an advance second to none in the history | |
12070 of astronomy, was given by Heraclides of Pontus, one of | |
12071 Plato's pupils (<I>circa</I> 388-310 B.C.); the other, which was | |
12072 by Eudoxus and on purely mathematical lines, constitutes | |
12073 one of the most remarkable achievements in pure geometry | |
12074 that the whole of the history of mathematics can show. | |
12075 Both were philosophers of extraordinary range. Heraclides | |
12076 wrote works of the highest class both in matter and style: | |
12077 the catalogue of them covers subjects ethical, grammatical, | |
12078 musical and poetical, rhetorical, historical; and there were | |
12079 geometrical and dialectical treatises as well. Similarly | |
12080 Eudoxus, celebrated as philosopher, geometer, astronomer, | |
12081 geographer, physician and legislator, commanded and enriched | |
12082 almost the whole field of learning. | |
12083 <C>Heraclides of Pontus: astronomical discoveries.</C> | |
12084 <p>Heraclides held that the apparent daily revolution of the | |
12085 heavenly bodies round the earth was accounted for, not by | |
12086 <pb n=317><head>HERACLIDES. ASTRONOMICAL DISCOVERIES</head> | |
12087 the circular motion of the stars round the earth, but by the | |
12088 rotation of the earth about its own axis; several passages | |
12089 attest this, e.g. | |
12090 <p>‘Heraclides of Pontus supposed that the earth is in the | |
12091 centre and rotates (lit. ‘moves in a circle’) while the heaven | |
12092 is at rest, and he thought by this supposition to save the | |
12093 phenomena.’<note>Simpl. on <I>De caelo</I>, p. 519. 9-11, Heib.; cf.pp.441. 31-445. 5, pp. 541. | |
12094 27-542. 2; Proclus <I>in Tim.</I> 281 E.</note> | |
12095 <p>True, Heraclides may not have been alone in holding this | |
12096 view, for we are told that Ecphantus of Syracuse, a Pytha- | |
12097 gorean, also asserted that ‘the earth, being in the centre | |
12098 of the universe, moves about its own centre in an eastward | |
12099 direction’<note>Hippolytus, <I>Refut.</I> i. 15 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 340. 31), cf. Aëtius, iii. 13. 3 | |
12100 (<I>Vors.</I> i<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 341. 8-10).</note>; when Cicero<note>Cic. <I>Acad. Pr.</I> ii. 39, 123.</note> says the same thing of Hicetas, also | |
12101 of Syracuse, this is probably due to a confusion. But there | |
12102 is no doubt of the originality of the other capital discovery | |
12103 made by Heraclides, namely that Venus and Mercury revolve, | |
12104 like satellites, round the sun as centre. If, as Schiaparelli | |
12105 argued, Heraclides also came to the same conclusion about | |
12106 Mars, Jupiter and Saturn, he anticipated the hypothesis of | |
12107 Tycho Brahe (or rather improved on it), but the evidence is | |
12108 insufficient to establish this, and I think the probabilities are | |
12109 against it; there is some reason for thinking that it was | |
12110 Apollonius of Perga who thus completed what Heraclides had | |
12111 begun and put forward the full Tychonic hypothesis.<note><I>Aristarchus of Samos, the ancient Copernicus</I>, ch. xviii.</note> But | |
12112 there is nothing to detract from the merit of Heraclides in | |
12113 having pointed the way to it. | |
12114 <p>Eudoxus's theory of concentric spheres is even more re- | |
12115 markable as a mathematical achievement; it is worthy of the | |
12116 man who invented the great theory of proportion set out | |
12117 in Euclid, Book V, and the powerful <I>method of exhaustion</I> | |
12118 which not only enabled the areas of circles and the volumes | |
12119 of pyramids, cones, spheres, &c., to be obtained, but is at the | |
12120 root of all Archimedes's further developments in the mensura- | |
12121 tion of plane and solid figures. But, before we come to | |
12122 Eudoxus, there are certain other names to be mentioned. | |
12123 <pb n=318><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12124 <C>Theory of numbers (Speusippus, Xenocrates).</C> | |
12125 <p>To begin with arithmetic or the theory of numbers. SPEU- | |
12126 SIPPUS, nephew of Plato, who succeeded him as head of the | |
12127 school, is said to have made a particular study of Pythagorean | |
12128 doctrines, especially of the works of Philolaus, and to have | |
12129 written a small treatise <I>On the Pythagorean Numbers</I> of | |
12130 which a fragment, mentioned above (pp. 72, 75, 76) is pre- | |
12131 served in the <I>Theologumena Arithmetices.</I><note><I>Theol. Ar.</I>, Ast, p. 61.</note> To judge by the | |
12132 fragment, the work was not one of importance. The arith- | |
12133 metic in it was evidently of the geometrical type (polygonal | |
12134 numbers, for example, being represented by dots making up | |
12135 the particular figures). The portion of the book dealing with | |
12136 ‘the five figures (the regular solids) which are assigned to the | |
12137 cosmic elements, their particularity and their community | |
12138 with one another’, can hardly have gone beyond the putting | |
12139 together of the figures by faces, as we find it in the <I>Timaeus.</I> | |
12140 To Plato's distinction of the fundamental triangles, the equi- | |
12141 lateral, the isosceles right-angled, and the half of an equilateral | |
12142 triangle cut off by a perpendicular from a vertex on the | |
12143 opposite side, he adds a distinction (‘passablement futile’, | |
12144 as is the whole fragment in Tannery's opinion) of four | |
12145 pyramids (1) the regular pyramid, with an equilateral triangle | |
12146 for base and all the edges equal, (2) the pyramid on a square | |
12147 base, and (evidently) having its four edges terminating at the | |
12148 corners of the base equal, (3) the pyramid which is the half of | |
12149 the preceding one obtained by drawing a plane through the | |
12150 vertex so as to cut the base perpendicularly in a diagonal | |
12151 of the base, (4) a pyramid constructed on the half of an | |
12152 equilateral triangle as base; the object was, by calling these | |
12153 pyramids a monad, a dyad, a triad and a tetrad respectively, | |
12154 to make up the number 10, the special properties and virtues | |
12155 of which as set forth by the Pythagoreans were the subject of | |
12156 the second half of the work. Proclus quotes a few opinions | |
12157 of Speusippus; e.g., in the matter of theorems and problems, | |
12158 he differed from Menaechmus, since he regarded both alike | |
12159 as being more properly <I>theorems</I>, while Menaechmus would | |
12160 call both alike <I>problems.</I><note>Proclus on Eucl. I, pp. 77. 16; 78. 14.</note> | |
12161 <pb n=319><head>THEORY OF NUMBERS</head> | |
12162 <p>XENOCRATES of Chalcedon (396-314 B.C.), who succeeded | |
12163 Speusippus as head of the school, having been elected by | |
12164 a majority of only a few votes over Heraclides, is also said | |
12165 to have written a book <I>On Numbers</I> and a <I>Theory of Numbers</I>, | |
12166 besides books on geometry.<note>Diog. L. iv. 13, 14.</note> These books have not survived, | |
12167 but we learn that Xenocrates upheld the Platonic tradition in | |
12168 requiring of those who would enter the school a knowledge of | |
12169 music, geometry and astronomy; to one who was not pro- | |
12170 ficient in these things he said ‘Go thy way, for thou hast not | |
12171 the means of getting a grip of philosophy’. Plutarch says | |
12172 that he put at 1,002,000,000,000 the number of syllables which | |
12173 could be formed out of the letters of the alphabet.<note>Plutarch, <I>Quaest. Conviv.</I> viii. 9. 13, 733 A.</note> If the | |
12174 story is true, it represents the first attempt on record to solve | |
12175 a difficult problem in permutations and combinations. Xeno- | |
12176 crates was a supporter of ‘indivisible lines’(and magnitudes) | |
12177 by which he thought to get over the paradoxical arguments | |
12178 of Zeno.<note>Simpl. <I>in Phys.</I>, p. 138. 3, &c.</note> | |
12179 <C>The Elements. Proclus's summary (<I>continued</I>).</C> | |
12180 <p>In geometry we have more names mentioned in the sum- | |
12181 mary of Proclus.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 66. 18-67. 1.</note> | |
12182 <p>‘Younger than Leodamas were Neoclides and his pupil Leon, | |
12183 who added many things to what was known before their | |
12184 time, so that Leon was actually able to make a collection | |
12185 of the elements more carefully designed in respect both of | |
12186 the number of propositions proved and of their utility, besides | |
12187 which he invented <I>diorismi</I> (the object of which is to deter- | |
12188 mine) when the problem under investigation is possible of | |
12189 solution and when impossible.’ | |
12190 <p>Of Neoclides and Leon we know nothing more than what | |
12191 is here stated; but the definite recognition of the <G>diorismo/s</G>, | |
12192 that is, of the necessity of finding, as a preliminary to the | |
12193 solution of a problem, the conditions for the possibility of | |
12194 a solution, represents an advance in the philosophy and | |
12195 technology of mathematics. Not that the thing itself had | |
12196 not been met with before: there is, as we have seen, a | |
12197 <pb n=320><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12198 <G>diorismo/s</G> indicated in the famous geometrical passage of the | |
12199 <I>Meno</I><note>Plato, <I>Meno</I>, 87 A.</note>; no doubt, too, the geometrical solution by the Pytha- | |
12200 goreans of the quadratic equation would incidentally make | |
12201 clear to them the limits of possibility corresponding to the | |
12202 <G>diorismo/s</G> in the solution of the most general form of quad- | |
12203 ratic in Eucl. VI. 27-9, where, in the case of the ‘deficient’ | |
12204 parallelogram (Prop. 28), the enunciation states that ‘the | |
12205 given rectilineal figure must not be greater than the parallelo- | |
12206 gram described on half of the straight line and similar to the | |
12207 defect’. Again, the condition of the possibility of constructing | |
12208 a triangle out of three given straight lines (Eucl. I. 22), | |
12209 namely that any two of them must be together greater than | |
12210 the third, must have been perfectly familiar long before Leon | |
12211 or Plato. | |
12212 <p>Proclus continues:<note>Proclus on Eucl. I., p. 67. 2-68. 4.</note> | |
12213 <p>‘Eudoxus of Cnidos, a little younger than Leon, who had | |
12214 been associated with the school of Plato, was the first to | |
12215 increase the number of the so-called general theorems; he | |
12216 also added three other proportions to the three already known, | |
12217 and multiplied the theorems which originated with Plato | |
12218 about the section, applying to them the method of analysis. | |
12219 Amyclas [more correctly Amyntas] of Heraclea, one of the | |
12220 friends of Plato, Menaechmus, a pupil of Eudoxus who had | |
12221 also studied with Plato, and Dinostratus, his brother, made | |
12222 the whole of geometry still more perfect. Theudius of | |
12223 Magnesia had the reputation of excelling in mathematics as | |
12224 well as in the other branches of philosophy; for he put | |
12225 together the elements admirably and made many partial (or | |
12226 limited) theorems more general. Again, Athenaeus of Cyzicus, | |
12227 who lived about the same time, became famous in other | |
12228 branches of mathematics and most of all in geometry. These | |
12229 men consorted together in the Academy and conducted their | |
12230 investigations in common. Hermotimus of Colophon carried | |
12231 further the investigations already opened up by Eudoxus and | |
12232 Theaetetus, discovered many propositions of the Elements | |
12233 and compiled some portion of the theory of Loci. Philippus | |
12234 of Medma, who was a pupil of Plato and took up mathematics | |
12235 at his instance, not only carried out his investigations in | |
12236 accordance with Plato's instructions but also set himself to | |
12237 do whatever in his view contributed to the philosophy of | |
12238 Plato.’ | |
12239 <pb n=321><head>THE ELEMENTS</head> | |
12240 <p>It will be well to dispose of the smaller names in this | |
12241 list before taking up Eudoxus, the principal subject of | |
12242 this chapter. The name of Amyclas should apparently be | |
12243 Amyntas,<note>See <I>Ind. Hercul.</I>, ed. B cheler, <I>Ind. Schol. Gryphisw.</I>, 1869/70, col. | |
12244 6 in.</note> although Diogenes Laertius mentions Amyclos of | |
12245 Heraclea in Pontus as a pupil of Plato<note>Diog. L. iii. 46.</note> and has elsewhere an | |
12246 improbable story of one Amyclas, a Pythagorean, who with | |
12247 Clinias is supposed to have dissuaded Plato from burning the | |
12248 works of Democritus in view of the fact that there were | |
12249 many other copies in circulation.<note><I>Ib.</I> ix. 40.</note> Nothing more is known | |
12250 of Amyntas, Theudius, Athenaeus and Hermotimus than what | |
12251 is stated in the above passage of Proclus. It is probable, | |
12252 however, that the propositions, &c., in elementary geometry | |
12253 which are quoted by Aristotle were taken from the Elements | |
12254 of Theudius, which would no doubt be the text-book of the | |
12255 time just preceding Euclid. Of Menaechmus and Dinostratus | |
12256 we have already learnt that the former discovered conic | |
12257 sections, and used them for finding two mean proportionals, | |
12258 and that the latter applied the quadratrix to the squaring | |
12259 of the circle. Philippus of Medma (vulg. Mende) is doubtless | |
12260 the same person as Philippus of Opus, who is said to have | |
12261 revised and published the <I>Laws</I> of Plato which had been left | |
12262 unfinished, and to have been the author of the <I>Epinomis.</I> | |
12263 He wrote upon astronomy chiefly; the astronomy in the | |
12264 <I>Epinomis</I> follows that of the <I>Laws</I> and the <I>Timaeus</I>; but | |
12265 Suidas records the titles of other works by him as follows: | |
12266 <I>On the distance of the sun and moon, On the eclipse of the | |
12267 moon, On the size of the sun, the moon and the earth, On | |
12268 the planets.</I> A passage of Aëtius<note><I>Dox. Gr.</I>, p. 360.</note> and another of Plutarch<note><I>Non posse suaviter vivi secundum Epicurum</I>, c. 11, 1093 E.</note> | |
12269 alluding to his <I>proofs</I> about the shape of the moon may | |
12270 indicate that Philippus was the first to establish the complete | |
12271 theory of the phases of the moon. In mathematics, accord- | |
12272 ing to the same notice by Suidas, he wrote <I>Arithmetica, | |
12273 Means, On polygonal numbers, Cyclica, Optics, Enoptrica</I> | |
12274 (On mirrors); but nothing is known of the contents of these | |
12275 works. | |
12276 <pb n=322><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12277 <p>According to Apollodorus, EUDOXUS flourished in Ol. 103 = | |
12278 368-365 B.C., from which we infer that he was born about 408 | |
12279 B.C., and (since he lived 53 years) died about 355 B.C. In his | |
12280 23rd year he went to Athens with the physician Theomedon, | |
12281 and there for two months he attended lectures on philosophy | |
12282 and oratory, and in particular the lectures of Plato; so poor | |
12283 was he that he took up his abode at the Piraeus and trudged | |
12284 to Athens and back on foot each day. It would appear that | |
12285 his journey to Italy and Sicily to study geometry with | |
12286 Archytas, and medicine with Philistion, must have been | |
12287 earlier than the first visit to Athens, for from Athens he | |
12288 returned to Cnidos, after which he went to Egypt with | |
12289 a letter of introduction to King Nectanebus, given him by | |
12290 Agesilaus; the date of this journey was probably 381-380 B.C. | |
12291 or a little later, and he stayed in Egypt sixteen months. | |
12292 After that he went to Cyzicus, where he collected round him | |
12293 a large school which he took with him to Athens in 368 B.C. | |
12294 or a little later. There is apparently no foundation for the | |
12295 story mentioned by Diogenes Laertius that he took up a hostile | |
12296 attitude to Plato,<note>Diog. L. viii. 87.</note> nor on the other side for the statements | |
12297 that he went with Plato to Egypt and spent thirteen years | |
12298 in the company of the Egyptian priests, or that he visited | |
12299 Plato when Plato was with the younger Dionysius on his | |
12300 third visit to Sicily in 361 B.C. Returning later to his native | |
12301 place, Eudoxus was by a popular vote entrusted with legisla- | |
12302 tive office. | |
12303 <p>When in Egypt Eudoxus assimilated the astronomical | |
12304 knowledge of the priests of Heliopolis and himself made | |
12305 observations. The observatory between Heliopolis and Cerce- | |
12306 sura used by him was still pointed out in Augustus's time; | |
12307 he also had one built at Cnidos, and from there he observed | |
12308 the star Canopus which was not then visible in higher | |
12309 latitudes. It was doubtless to record the observations thus | |
12310 made that he wrote the two books attributed to him by | |
12311 Hipparchus, the <I>Mirror</I> and the <I>Phaenomena</I><note>Hipparchus, <I>in Arati et Eudoxi phaenomena commentarii</I>, i. 2. 2, p. 8. | |
12312 15-20 Manitius.</note>; it seems, how- | |
12313 ever, unlikely that there could have been two independent | |
12314 works dealing with the same subject, and the latter, from which | |
12315 <pb n=323><head>EUDOXUS</head> | |
12316 the poem of Aratus was drawn, so far as verses 19-732 are | |
12317 concerned, may have been a revision of the former work and | |
12318 even, perhaps, posthumous. | |
12319 <p>But it is the theoretical side of Eudoxus's astronomy rather | |
12320 than the observational that has importance for us; and, | |
12321 indeed, no more ingenious and attractive hypothesis than | |
12322 that of Eudoxus's system of concentric spheres has ever been | |
12323 put forward to account for the apparent motions of the sun, | |
12324 moon and planets. It was the first attempt at a purely | |
12325 mathematical theory of astronomy, and, with the great and | |
12326 immortal contributions which he made to geometry, puts him | |
12327 in the very first rank of mathematicians of all time. He | |
12328 was a <I>man of science</I> if there ever was one. No occult or | |
12329 superstitious lore appealed to him; Cicero says that Eudoxus, | |
12330 ‘in astrologia iudicio doctissimorum hominum facile princeps’, | |
12331 expressed the opinion and left it on record that no sort of | |
12332 credence should be given to the Chaldaeans in their predic- | |
12333 tions and their foretelling of the life of individuals from the | |
12334 day of their birth.<note>Cic., <I>De div.</I> ii. 42.</note> Nor would he indulge in vain physical | |
12335 speculations on things which were inaccessible to observation | |
12336 and experience in his time; thus, instead of guessing at | |
12337 the nature of the sun, he said that he would gladly be | |
12338 burnt up like Phaethon if at that price he could get to the | |
12339 sun and so ascertain its form, size, and nature.<note>Plutarch, <I>Non posse suaviter vivi secundum Epicurum</I>, c. 11, 1094 B.</note> Another | |
12340 story (this time presumably apocryphal) is to the effect | |
12341 that he grew old at the top of a very high mountain in | |
12342 the attempt to discover the movements of the stars and the | |
12343 heavens.<note>Petronius Arbiter, <I>Satyricon</I>, 88.</note> | |
12344 <p>In our account of his work we will begin with the sentence | |
12345 about him in Proclus's summary. First, he is said to have | |
12346 increased ‘the number of the <I>so-called general</I> theorems’. | |
12347 ‘So-called general theorems’ is an odd phrase; it occurred to | |
12348 me whether this could mean theorems which were true of | |
12349 everything falling under the conception of magnitude, as are | |
12350 the definitions and theorems forming part of Eudoxus's own | |
12351 theory of proportion, which applies to numbers, geometrical | |
12352 magnitudes of all sorts, times, &c. A number of propositions | |
12353 <pb n=324><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12354 at the beginning of Euclid's Book X similarly refer to magni- | |
12355 tudes in general, and the proposition X. 1 or its equivalent | |
12356 was actually used by Eudoxus in his <I>method of exhaustion</I>, | |
12357 as it is by Euclid in his application of the same method to the | |
12358 theorem (among others) of XII. 2 that circles are to one | |
12359 another as the squares on their diameters. | |
12360 <p>The three ‘proportions’ or means added to the three pre- | |
12361 viously known (the arithmetic, geometric and harmonic) have | |
12362 already been mentioned (p. 86), and, as they are alterna- | |
12363 tively attributed to others, they need not detain us here. | |
12364 <p>Thirdly, we are told that Eudoxus ‘extended’ or ‘increased | |
12365 the number of the (propositions) about <I>the section</I> (<G>ta\ peri\ | |
12366 th\n tomh/n</G>) which originated with Plato, applying to them | |
12367 the method of analysis’. What is <I>the section</I>? The sugges- | |
12368 tion which has been received with most favour is that of | |
12369 Bretschneider,<note>Bretschneider, <I>Die Geometrie und die Geometer vor Eukleides</I>, pp. | |
12370 167-9.</note> who pointed out that up to Plato's time there | |
12371 was only one ‘section’ that had any real significance in | |
12372 geometry, namely the section of a straight line in extreme | |
12373 and mean ratio which is obtained in Eucl. II. 11 and is used | |
12374 again in Eucl. IV. 10-14 for the construction of a pentagon. | |
12375 These theorems were, as we have seen, pretty certainly Pytha- | |
12376 gorean, like the whole of the substance of Euclid, Book II. | |
12377 Plato may therefore, says Bretschneider, have directed atten- | |
12378 tion afresh to this subject and investigated the metrical rela- | |
12379 tions between the segments of a straight line so cut, while | |
12380 Eudoxus may have continued the investigation where Plato | |
12381 left off. Now the passage of Proclus says that, in extending | |
12382 the theorems about ‘the section’, Eudoxus applied the method | |
12383 of analysis; and we actually find in Eucl. XIII. 1-5 five | |
12384 propositions about straight lines cut in extreme and mean | |
12385 ratio followed, in the MSS., by definitions of analysis and | |
12386 synthesis, and alternative proofs of the same propositions | |
12387 in the form of analysis followed by synthesis. Here, then, | |
12388 Bretschneider thought he had found a fragment of some actual | |
12389 work by Eudoxus corresponding to Proclus's description. | |
12390 But it is certain that the definitions and the alternative proofs | |
12391 were interpolated by some scholiast, and, judging by the | |
12392 figures (which are merely straight lines) and by comparison | |
12393 <pb n=325><head>EUDOXUS</head> | |
12394 with the remarks on analysis and synthesis quoted from | |
12395 Heron by An-Nairīzī at the beginning of his commentary on | |
12396 Eucl. Book II, it seems most likely that the interpolated defini- | |
12397 tions and proofs were taken from Heron. Bretschneider's | |
12398 argument based on Eucl. XIII. 1-5 accordingly breaks down, | |
12399 and all that can be said further is that, if Eudoxus investi- | |
12400 gated the relation between the segments of the straight line, | |
12401 he would find in it a case of incommensurability which would | |
12402 further enforce the necessity for a theory of proportion which | |
12403 should be applicable to incommensurable as well as to com- | |
12404 mensurable magnitudes. Proclus actually observes that | |
12405 ‘theorems about sections like those in Euclid's Second Book | |
12406 are common to both [arithmetic and geometry] <I>except that in | |
12407 which the straight line is cut in extreme and mean ratio</I>’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 60. 16-19.</note> | |
12408 (cf. Eucl. XIII. 6 for the actual proof of the irrationality | |
12409 in this case). Opinion, however, has not even in recent years | |
12410 been unanimous in favour of Bretschneider's interpretation; | |
12411 Tannery<note>Tannèry, <I>La géométrie grecque</I>, p. 76.</note> in particular preferred the old view, which pre- | |
12412 vailed before Bretschneider, that ‘section’ meant section <I>of | |
12413 solids</I>, e.g. by planes, a line of investigation which would | |
12414 naturally precede the discovery of conics; he pointed out that | |
12415 the use of the singular, <G>th\n tomh/n</G>, which might no doubt | |
12416 be taken as ‘section’ in the abstract, is no real objection, that | |
12417 there is no other passage which speaks of a certain section | |
12418 <I>par excellence</I>, and that Proclus in the words just quoted | |
12419 expresses himself quite differently, speaking of ‘sections’ of | |
12420 which the particular section in extreme and mean ratio is | |
12421 only one. Presumably the question will never be more defi- | |
12422 nitely settled unless by the discovery of new documents. | |
12423 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Theory of proportion.</I></C> | |
12424 <p>The anonymous author of a scholium to Euclid's Book V, | |
12425 who is perhaps Proclus, tells us that ‘some say’ that this | |
12426 Book, containing the general theory of proportion which is | |
12427 equally applicable to geometry, arithmetic, music and all | |
12428 mathematical science, ‘is the discovery of Eudoxus, the teacher | |
12429 of Plato’.<note>Euclid, ed. Heib., vol. v, p. 280.</note> There is no reason to doubt the truth of this | |
12430 <pb n=326><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12431 statement. The new theory appears to have been already | |
12432 familiar to Aristotle. Moreover, the fundamental principles | |
12433 show clear points of contact with those used in the <I>method | |
12434 of exhaustion</I>, also due to Eudoxus. I refer to the definition | |
12435 (Eucl. V, Def. 4) of magnitudes having a ratio to one another, | |
12436 which are said to be ‘such as are capable, when (sufficiently) | |
12437 multiplied, of exceeding one another’; compare with this | |
12438 Archimedes's ‘lemma’ by means of which he says that the | |
12439 theorems about the volume of a pyramid and about circles | |
12440 being to one another as the squares on their diameters were | |
12441 proved, namely that ‘of unequal lines, unequal surfaces, or | |
12442 unequal solids, the greater exceeds the less by such a | |
12443 magnitude as is capable, if added (continually) to itself, of | |
12444 exceeding any magnitude of those which are comparable to | |
12445 one another’, i.e. of magnitudes of the same kind as the | |
12446 original magnitudes. | |
12447 <p>The essence of the new theory was that it was applicable | |
12448 to incommensurable as well as commensurable quantities; | |
12449 and its importance cannot be overrated, for it enabled | |
12450 geometry to go forward again, after it had received the blow | |
12451 which paralysed it for the time. This was the discovery of | |
12452 the irrational, at a time when geometry still depended on the | |
12453 Pythagorean theory of proportion, that is, the numerical | |
12454 theory which was of course applicable only to commensurables. | |
12455 The discovery of incommensurables must have caused what | |
12456 Tannery described as ‘un véritable scandale logique’ in | |
12457 geometry, inasmuch as it made inconclusive all the proofs | |
12458 which had depended on the old theory of proportion. One | |
12459 effect would naturally be to make geometers avoid the use | |
12460 of proportions as much as possible; they would have to use | |
12461 other methods wherever they could. Euclid's Books I-IV no | |
12462 doubt largely represent the result of the consequent remodel- | |
12463 ling of fundamental propositions; and the ingenuity of the | |
12464 substitutes devised is nowhere better illustrated than in I. 44, | |
12465 45, where the equality of the complements about the diagonal | |
12466 of a parallelogram is used (instead of the construction, as | |
12467 in Book VI, of a fourth proportional) for the purpose of | |
12468 applying to a given straight line a parallelogram in a given | |
12469 angle and equal to a given triangle or rectilineal area. | |
12470 <p>The greatness of the new theory itself needs no further | |
12471 <pb n=327><head>EUDOXUS'S THEORY OF PROPORTION</head> | |
12472 argument when it is remembered that the definition of equal | |
12473 ratios in Eucl. V, Def. 5 corresponds exactly to the modern | |
12474 theory of irrationals due to Dedekind, and that it is word for | |
12475 word the same as Weierstrass's definition of equal numbers. | |
12476 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The method of exhaustion.</I></C> | |
12477 <p>In the preface to Book I of his treatise <I>On the Sphere and | |
12478 Cylinder</I> Archimedes attributes to Eudoxus the proof of the | |
12479 theorems that the volume of a pyramid is one-third of | |
12480 the volume of the prism which has the same base and equal | |
12481 height, and that the volume of a cone is one-third of the | |
12482 cylinder with the same base and height. In the <I>Method</I> he | |
12483 says that these facts were discovered, though not proved | |
12484 (i. e. in Archimedes's sense of the word), by Democritus, | |
12485 who accordingly deserved a great part of the credit for the | |
12486 theorems, but that Eudoxus was the first to supply the | |
12487 scientific proof. In the preface to the <I>Quadrature of the Para- | |
12488 bola</I> Archimedes gives further details. He says that for the | |
12489 proof of the theorem that the area of a segment of a parabola | |
12490 cut off by a chord is (4/3)rds of the triangle on the same base and | |
12491 of equal height with the segment he himself used the ‘lemma’ | |
12492 quoted above (now known as the Axiom of Archimedes), and | |
12493 he goes on: | |
12494 <p>‘The earlier geometers have also used this lemma; for it is | |
12495 by the use of this lemma that they have proved the proposi- | |
12496 tions (1) that circles are to one another in the duplicate ratio | |
12497 of their diameters, (2) that spheres are to one another in the | |
12498 triplicate ratio of their diameters, and further (3) that every | |
12499 pyramid is one third part of the prism which has the same | |
12500 base with the pyramid and equal height; also (4) that every | |
12501 cone is one third part of the cylinder having the same base | |
12502 with the cone and equal height they proved by assuming | |
12503 a certain lemma similar to that aforesaid.’ | |
12504 <p>As, according to the other passage, it was Eudoxus who | |
12505 first proved the last two of these theorems, it is a safe | |
12506 inference that he used for this purpose the ‘lemma’ in ques- | |
12507 tion or its equivalent. But was he the first to use the lemma? | |
12508 This has been questioned on the ground that one of the | |
12509 theorems mentioned as having been proved by ‘the earlier | |
12510 geometers’ in this way is the theorem that circles are to one | |
12511 <pb n=328><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12512 another as the squares on their diameters, which proposition, | |
12513 as we are told on the authority of Eudemus, was proved | |
12514 (<G>dei=xai</G>) by Hippocrates of Chios. This suggested to Hankel | |
12515 that the lemma in question must have been formulated by | |
12516 Hippocrates and used in his proof.<note>Hankel, <I>Zur Geschichte der Mathematik in Alterthum und Mittelalter</I>, | |
12517 p. 122.</note> But seeing that, accord- | |
12518 ing to Archimedes, ‘the earlier geometers’ proved by means | |
12519 of the same lemma <I>both</I> Hippocrates's proposition, (1) above, | |
12520 and the theorem (3) about the volume of a pyramid, while | |
12521 the first proof of the latter was certainly given by Eudoxus, | |
12522 it is simplest to suppose that it was Eudoxus who first formu- | |
12523 lated the ‘lemma’ and used it to prove both propositions, and | |
12524 that Hippocrates's ‘proof’ did not amount to a rigorous | |
12525 demonstration such as would have satisfied Eudoxus or | |
12526 Archimedes. Hippocrates may, for instance, have proceeded | |
12527 on the lines of Antiphon's ‘quadrature’, gradually exhausting | |
12528 the circles and <I>taking the limit</I>, without clinching the proof | |
12529 by the formal <I>reductio ad absurdum</I> used in the method of | |
12530 exhaustion as practised later. Without therefore detracting | |
12531 from the merit of Hippocrates, whose argument may have | |
12532 contained the germ of the method of exhaustion, we do not | |
12533 seem to have any sufficient reason to doubt that it was | |
12534 Eudoxus who established this method as part of the regular | |
12535 machinery of geometry. | |
12536 <p>The ‘lemma’ itself, we may observe, is not found in Euclid | |
12537 in precisely the form that Archimedes gives it, though it | |
12538 is equivalent to Eucl. V, Def. 4 (Magnitudes are said to have | |
12539 a ratio to one another which are capable, when multiplied, | |
12540 of exceeding one another). When Euclid comes to prove the | |
12541 propositions about the content of circles, pyramids and cones | |
12542 (XII. 2, 4-7 Por., and 10), he does not use the actual lemma of | |
12543 Archimedes, but another which forms Prop. 1 of Book X, to | |
12544 the effect that, if there are two unequal magnitudes and from | |
12545 the greater there be subtracted more than its half (or the | |
12546 half itself), from the remainder more than its half (or the half), | |
12547 and if this be done continually, there will be left some magni- | |
12548 tude which will be less than the lesser of the given magnitudes. | |
12549 This last lemma is frequently used by Archimedes himself | |
12550 (notably in the second proof of the proposition about the area | |
12551 <pb n=329><head>EUDOXUS. METHOD OF EXHAUSTION</head> | |
12552 of a parabolic segment), and it may be the ‘lemma similar | |
12553 to the aforesaid’ which he says was used in the case of the | |
12554 cone. But the existence of the two lemmas constitutes no | |
12555 real difficulty, because Archimedes's lemma (under the form | |
12556 of Eucl. V, Def. 4) is in effect used by Euclid to prove X. 1. | |
12557 <p>We are not told whether Eudoxus proved the theorem that | |
12558 spheres are to one another in the triplicate ratio of their | |
12559 diameters. As the proof of this in Eucl. XII. 16-18 is likewise | |
12560 based on X. 1 (which is used in XII. 16), it is probable enough | |
12561 that this proposition, mentioned along with the others by | |
12562 Archimedes, was also first proved by Eudoxus. | |
12563 <p>Eudoxus, as we have seen, is said to have solved the problem | |
12564 of the two mean proportionals by means of ‘curved lines’. | |
12565 This solution has been dealt with above (pp. 249-51). | |
12566 <p>We pass on to the | |
12567 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Theory of concentric spheres.</I></C> | |
12568 <p>This was the first attempt to account by purely geometrical | |
12569 hypotheses for the apparent irregularities of the motions of | |
12570 the planets; it included similar explanations of the apparently | |
12571 simpler movements of the sun and moon. The ancient | |
12572 evidence of the details of the system of concentric spheres | |
12573 (which Eudoxus set out in a book entitled <I>On speeds</I>, <G>*peri\ | |
12574 taxw=n</G>, now lost) is contained in two passages. The first is in | |
12575 Aristotle's <I>Metaphysics</I>, where a short notice is given of the | |
12576 numbers and relative positions of the spheres postulated by | |
12577 Eudoxus for the sun, moon and planets respectively, the | |
12578 additions which Callippus thought it necessary to make to | |
12579 the numbers of those spheres, and lastly the modification | |
12580 of the system which Aristotle himself considers necessary | |
12581 ‘if the phenomena are to be produced by all the spheres | |
12582 acting in combination’.<note>Aristotle, <I>Metaph.</I> A. 8. 1073 b 17-1074 a 14.</note> A more elaborate and detailed | |
12583 account of the system is contained in Simplicius's commentary | |
12584 on the <I>De caelo</I> of Aristotle<note>Simpl. on <I>De caelo</I>, p. 488. 18-24, pp. 493. 4-506. 18 Heib.; p. 498 | |
12585 a 45-b 3, pp. 498 b 27-503 a 33.</note>; Simplicius quotes largely from | |
12586 Sosigenes the Peripatetic (second century A. D.), observing that | |
12587 Sosigenes drew from Eudemus, who dealt with the subject | |
12588 in the second book of his <I>History of Astronomy.</I> Ideler was | |
12589 <pb n=330><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12590 the first to appreciate the elegance of the theory and to | |
12591 attempt to explain its working (1828, 1830); E. F. Apelt, too, | |
12592 gave a fairly full exposition of it in a paper of 1849. But it | |
12593 was reserved for Schiaparelli to work out a complete restora- | |
12594 tion of the theory and to investigate in detail the extent | |
12595 to which it could be made to account for the phenomena; his | |
12596 paper has become a classic,<note>Schiaparelli, <I>Le sfere omocentriche di Eudosso, di Callippo e di Aristotele</I>, | |
12597 Milano 1875; Germ. trans. by W. Horn in <I>Abh. zur Gesch. d. Math.</I>, i. | |
12598 Heft, 1877, pp. 101-98.</note> and all accounts must necessarily | |
12599 follow his. | |
12600 <p>I shall here only describe the system so far as to show its | |
12601 mathematical interest. I have given fuller details elsewhere.<note><I>Aristarchus of Samos, the ancient Copernicus</I>, pp. 193-224.</note> | |
12602 Eudoxus adopted the view which prevailed from the earliest | |
12603 times to the time of Kepler, that circular motion was sufficient | |
12604 to account for the movements of all the heavenly bodies. | |
12605 With Eudoxus this circular motion took the form of the | |
12606 revolution of different spheres, each of which moves about | |
12607 a diameter as axis. All the spheres were concentric, the | |
12608 common centre being the centre of the earth; hence the name | |
12609 of ‘homocentric’ spheres used in later times to describe the | |
12610 system. The spheres were of different sizes, one inside the | |
12611 other. Each planet was fixed at a point in the equator of | |
12612 the sphere which carried it, the sphere revolving at uniform | |
12613 speed about the diameter joining the corresponding poles; | |
12614 that is, the planet revolved uniformly in a great circle of the | |
12615 sphere perpendicular to the axis of rotation. But one such | |
12616 circular motion was not enough; in order to explain the | |
12617 changes in the apparent speed of the planets' motion, their | |
12618 stations and retrogradations, Eudoxus had to assume a number | |
12619 of such circular motions working on each planet and producing | |
12620 by their combination that single apparently irregular motion | |
12621 which observation shows us. He accordingly held that the | |
12622 poles of the sphere carrying the planet are not fixed, but | |
12623 themselves move on a greater sphere concentric with the | |
12624 carrying sphere and moving about two different poles with | |
12625 uniform speed. The poles of the second sphere were simi- | |
12626 larly placed on a third sphere concentric with and larger | |
12627 than the first and second, and moving about separate poles | |
12628 <pb n=331><head>THEORY OF CONCENTRIC SPHERES</head> | |
12629 of its own with a speed peculiar to itself. For the planets | |
12630 yet a fourth sphere was required, similarly related to the | |
12631 others; for the sun and moon Eudoxus found that, by a | |
12632 suitable choice of the positions of the poles and of speeds | |
12633 of rotation, he could make three spheres suffice. Aristotle | |
12634 and Simplicius describe the spheres in the reverse order, the | |
12635 sphere carrying the planet being the last; this makes the | |
12636 description easier, because we begin with the sphere represent- | |
12637 ing the daily rotaton of the heavens. The spheres which | |
12638 move each planet Eudoxus made quite separate from those | |
12639 which move the others; but one sphere sufficed to produce | |
12640 the daily rotation of the heavens. The hypothesis was purely | |
12641 mathematical; Eudoxus did not trouble himself about the | |
12642 material of the spheres or their mechanical connexion. | |
12643 <p>The moon has a motion produced by three spheres; the | |
12644 first or outermost moves in the same sense as the fixed stars | |
12645 from east to west in 24 hours; the second moves about an | |
12646 axis perpendicular to the plane of the zodiac circle or the | |
12647 ecliptic, and in the sense of the daily rotation, i.e. from | |
12648 east to west; the third again moves about an axis inclined | |
12649 to the axis of the second at an angle equal to the highest | |
12650 latitude attained by the moon, and from west to east; | |
12651 the moon is fixed on the equator of this third sphere. The | |
12652 speed of the revolution of the second sphere was very slow | |
12653 (a revolution was completed in a period of 223 lunations); | |
12654 the third sphere produced the revolution of the moon from | |
12655 west to east in the draconitic or nodal month (of 27 days, | |
12656 5 hours, 5 minutes, 36 seconds) round a circle inclined to | |
12657 the ecliptic at an angle equal to the greatest latitude of the | |
12658 moon.<note>Simplicius (and presumably Aristotle also) confused the motions of | |
12659 the second and third spheres. The above account represents what | |
12660 Eudoxus evidently intended.</note> The moon described the latter circle, while the | |
12661 circle itself was carried round by the second sphere in | |
12662 a retrograde sense along the ecliptic in a period of 223 | |
12663 lunations; and both the inner spheres were bodily carried | |
12664 round by the first sphere in 24 hours in the sense of the daily | |
12665 rotation. The three spheres thus produced the motion of the | |
12666 moon in an orbit inclined to the ecliptic, and the retrogression | |
12667 of the nodes, completed in a period of about 181/2 years. | |
12668 <pb n=332><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12669 <p>The system of three spheres for the sun was similar, except | |
12670 that the orbit was less inclined to the ecliptic than that of the | |
12671 moon, and the second sphere moved from west to east instead | |
12672 of from east to west, so that the nodes moved slowly forward | |
12673 in the direct order of the signs instead of backward. | |
12674 <p>But the case to which the greatest mathematical interest | |
12675 attaches is that of the planets, the motion of which is pro- | |
12676 duced by sets of four spheres for each. Of each set the first | |
12677 and outermost produced the daily rotation in 24 hours; the | |
12678 second, the motion round the zodiac in periods which in the | |
12679 case of superior planets are equal to the sidereal periods of | |
12680 revolution, and for Mercury and Venus (on a geocentric | |
12681 system) one year. The third sphere had its poles fixed at two | |
12682 opposite points on the zodiac circle, the poles being carried | |
12683 round in the motion of the second sphere; the revolution | |
12684 of the third sphere about its poles was again uniform and | |
12685 was completed in the synodic period of the planet or the time | |
12686 which elapsed between two successive oppositions or conjunc- | |
12687 tions with the sun. The poles of the third sphere were the | |
12688 same for Mercury and Venus but different for all the other | |
12689 planets. On the surface of the third sphere the poles of the | |
12690 fourth sphere were fixed, the axis of the latter being inclined | |
12691 to that of the former at an angle which was constant for each | |
12692 planet but different for the different planets. The rotation of | |
12693 the fourth sphere about its axis took place in the same time | |
12694 as the rotation of the third about its axis but in the opposite | |
12695 sense. On the equator of the fourth sphere the planet was | |
12696 fixed. Consider now the actual path of a planet subject to | |
12697 the rotations of the third and fourth spheres only, leaving out | |
12698 of account for the moment the first two spheres the motion of | |
12699 which produces the daily rotation and the motion along the | |
12700 zodiac respectively. The problem is the following. A sphere | |
12701 rotates uniformly about the fixed diameter <I>AB. P, P</I>′ are | |
12702 two opposite poles on this sphere, and a second sphere con- | |
12703 centric with the first rotates uniformly about the diameter | |
12704 <I>PP</I>′ in the same time as the former sphere rotates about <I>AB,</I> | |
12705 but in the opposite direction. <I>M</I> is a point on the second | |
12706 sphere equidistant from <I>P, P</I>′, i. e. a point on the equator | |
12707 of the second sphere. Required to find the path of the | |
12708 point <I>M.</I> This is not difficult nowadays for any one familiar | |
12709 <pb n=333><head>THEORY OF CONCENTRIC SPHERES</head> | |
12710 with spherical trigonometry and analytical geometry; but | |
12711 Schiaparelli showed, by means of a series of seven propositions | |
12712 or problems involving only elementary geometry, that it was | |
12713 well within the powers of such a geometer as Eudoxus. The | |
12714 path of <I>M</I> in space turns out in fact to be a curve like | |
12715 a lemniscate or figure-of-eight described on the surface of a | |
12716 sphere, namely the fixed sphere about <I>AB</I> as diameter. This | |
12717 <FIG> | |
12718 ‘spherical lemniscate’ is roughly shown in the second figure | |
12719 above. The curve is actually the intersection of the sphere | |
12720 with a certain cylinder touching it internally at the double | |
12721 point <I>O,</I> namely a cylinder with diameter equal to <I>AS</I> the | |
12722 <I>sagitta</I> (shown in the other figure) of the diameter of the | |
12723 small circle on which <I>P</I> revolves. But the curve is also | |
12724 the intersection of <I>either</I> the sphere <I>or</I> the cylinder with | |
12725 a certain cone with vertex <I>O,</I> axis parallel to the axis of the | |
12726 cylinder (i. e. touching the circle <I>AOB</I> at <I>O</I>) and vertical angle | |
12727 equal to the ‘inclination’ (the angle <I>AO</I>′<I>P</I> in the first figure). | |
12728 That this represents the actual result obtained by Eudoxus | |
12729 himself is conclusively proved by the facts that Eudoxus | |
12730 called the curve described by the planet about the zodiac | |
12731 circle the <I>hippopede</I> or <I>horse-fetter,</I> and that the same term | |
12732 <I>hippopede</I> is used by Proclus to describe the plane curve of | |
12733 similar shape formed by a plane section of an anchor-ring or | |
12734 <I>tore</I> touching the tore internally and parallel to its axis.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 112. 5.</note> | |
12735 <p>So far account has only been taken of the motion due to | |
12736 the combination of the rotations of the third and fourth | |
12737 <pb n=334><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12738 spheres. But <I>A, B,</I> the poles of the third sphere, are carried | |
12739 round the zodiac or ecliptic by the motion of the second | |
12740 sphere in a time equal to the ‘zodiacal’ period of the planet. | |
12741 Now the axis of symmetry of the ‘spherical lemniscate’ (the | |
12742 arc of the great circle bisecting it longitudinally) always lies | |
12743 on the ecliptic. We may therefore substitute for the third | |
12744 and fourth spheres the ‘lemniscate’ moving bodily round | |
12745 the ecliptic. The combination of the two motions (that of the | |
12746 ‘lemniscate’ and that of the planet on it) gives the motion of | |
12747 the planet through the constellations. The motion of the | |
12748 planet round the curve is an oscillatory motion, now forward in | |
12749 acceleration of the motion round the ecliptic due to the motion | |
12750 of the second sphere, now backward in retardation of the same | |
12751 motion; the period of the oscillation is the period of the syno- | |
12752 dic revolution, and the acceleration and retardation occupy | |
12753 half the period respectively. When the retardation in the | |
12754 sense of longitude due to the backward oscillation is greater | |
12755 than the speed of the forward motion of the lemniscate itself, | |
12756 the planet will for a time have a retrograde motion, at the | |
12757 beginning and end of which it will appear stationary for a little | |
12758 while, when the two opposite motions balance each other. | |
12759 <p>It will be admitted that to produce the retrogradations | |
12760 in this theoretical way by superimposed axial rotations of | |
12761 spheres was a remarkable stroke of genius. It was no slight | |
12762 geometrical achievement, for those days, to demonstrate the | |
12763 <I>effect</I> of the hypotheses; but this is nothing in comparison | |
12764 with the speculative power which enabled the man to invent | |
12765 the hypothesis which would produce the effect. It was, of | |
12766 course, a much greater achievement than that of Eudoxus's | |
12767 teacher Archytas in finding the two mean proportionals by | |
12768 means of the intersection of three surfaces in space, a <I>tore</I> | |
12769 with internal diameter <I>nil,</I> a cylinder and a cone; the problem | |
12770 solved by Eudoxus was much more difficult, and yet there | |
12771 is the curious resemblance between the two solutions that | |
12772 Eudoxus's <I>hippopede</I> is actually the section of a sphere with | |
12773 a cylinder touching it internally and also with a certain | |
12774 cone; the two cases together show the freedom with which | |
12775 master and pupil were accustomed to work with figures in | |
12776 three dimensions, and in particular with surfaces of revolution, | |
12777 their intersections, &c. | |
12778 <pb n=335><head>THEORY OF CONCENTRIC SPHERES</head> | |
12779 <p>Callippus (about 370-300 B.C.) tried to make the system of | |
12780 concentric spheres suit the phenomena more exactly by adding | |
12781 other spheres; he left the number of the spheres at four in | |
12782 the case of Jupiter and Saturn, but added one each to the | |
12783 other planets and two each in the case of the sun and moon | |
12784 (making five in all). This would substitute for the hippopede | |
12785 a still more complicated elongated figure, and the matter is | |
12786 not one to be followed out here. Aristotle modified the system | |
12787 in a mechanical sense by introducing between each planet | |
12788 and the one below it reacting spheres one less in number than | |
12789 those acting on the former planet, and with motions equal | |
12790 and opposite to each of them, except the outermost, respec- | |
12791 tively; by neutralizing the motions of all except the outermost | |
12792 sphere acting on any planet he wished to enable that outer- | |
12793 most to be the outermost acting on the planet below, so that | |
12794 the spheres became one connected system, each being in actual | |
12795 contact with the one below and acting on it, whereas with | |
12796 Eudoxus and Callippus the spheres acting on each planet | |
12797 formed a separate set independent of the others. Aristotle's | |
12798 modification was not an improvement, and has no mathe- | |
12799 matical interest. | |
12800 <p>The works of ARISTOTLE are of the greatest importance to | |
12801 the history of mathematics and particularly of the Elements. | |
12802 His date (384-322/1) comes just before that of Euclid, so | |
12803 that from the differences between his statement of things | |
12804 corresponding to what we find in Euclid and Euclid's own we | |
12805 can draw a fair inference as to the innovations which were | |
12806 due to Euclid himself. Aristotle was no doubt a competent | |
12807 mathematician, though he does not seem to have specialized | |
12808 in mathematics, and fortunately for us he was fond of mathe- | |
12809 matical illustrations. His allusions to particular definitions, | |
12810 propositions, &c., in geometry are in such a form as to suggest | |
12811 that his pupils must have had at hand some text-book where | |
12812 they could find the things he mentions. The particular text- | |
12813 book then in use would presumably be that which was the | |
12814 immediate predecessor of Euclid's, namely the Elements of | |
12815 Theudius; for Theudius is the latest of pre-Euclidean | |
12816 geometers whom the summary of Proclus mentions as a com- | |
12817 piler of Elements.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 67. 12-16.</note> | |
12818 <pb n=336><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12819 <C>The mathematics in Aristotle comes under the | |
12820 following heads.</C> | |
12821 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>First principles.</I></C> | |
12822 <p>On no part of the subject does Aristotle throw more light | |
12823 than on the first principles as then accepted. The most | |
12824 important passages dealing with this subject are in the | |
12825 <I>Posterior Analytics.</I><note><I>Anal. Post.</I> i. 6. 74 b 5, i. 10. 76 a 31-77 a 4.</note> While he speaks generally of ‘demon- | |
12826 strative sciences’, his illustrations are mainly mathematical, | |
12827 doubtless because they were readiest to his hand. He gives | |
12828 the clearest distinctions between axioms (which are common | |
12829 to all sciences), definitions, hypotheses and postulates (which | |
12830 are different for different sciences since they relate to the | |
12831 subject-matter of the particular science). If we exclude from | |
12832 Euclid's axioms (1) the assumption that two straight lines | |
12833 cannot enclose a space, which is interpolated, and (2) the | |
12834 so-called ‘Parallel-Axiom’ which is the 5th Postulate, Aris- | |
12835 totle's explanation of these terms fits the classification of | |
12836 Euclid quite well. Aristotle calls the axioms by various | |
12837 terms, ‘<I>common</I> (things)’, ‘common axioms’, ‘common opinions’, | |
12838 and this seems to be the origin of ‘common notions’ (<G>koinai\ | |
12839 e)/nnoiai</G>), the term by which they are described in the text | |
12840 of Euclid; the particular axiom which Aristotle is most fond | |
12841 of quoting is No. 3, stating that, if equals be subtracted from | |
12842 equals, the remainders are equal. Aristotle does not give any | |
12843 instance of a geometrical postulate. From this we may fairly | |
12844 make the important inference that Euclid's Postulates are all | |
12845 his own, the momentous Postulate 5 as well as Nos. 1, 2, 3 | |
12846 relating to constructions of lines and circles, and No. 4 that | |
12847 all right angles are equal. These postulates as well as those | |
12848 which Archimedes lays down at the beginning of his book | |
12849 <I>On Plane Equilibriums</I> (e.g. that ‘equal weights balance at | |
12850 equal lengths, but equal weights at unequal lengths do not | |
12851 balance but incline in the direction of the weight which is | |
12852 at the greater length’) correspond exactly enough to Aristotle's | |
12853 idea of a postulate. This is something which, e.g., the | |
12854 geometer assumes (for reasons known to himself) without | |
12855 demonstration (though properly a subject for demonstration) | |
12856 <pb n=337><head>ARISTOTLE</head> | |
12857 and without any assent on the part of the learner, or even | |
12858 against his opinion rather than otherwise. As regards defini- | |
12859 tions, Aristotle is clear that they do not assert existence or | |
12860 non-existence; they only require to be understood. The only | |
12861 exception he makes is in the case of the <I>unit</I> or <I>monad</I> and | |
12862 <I>magnitude,</I> the existence of which has to be assumed, while | |
12863 the existence of everything else has to be proved; the things | |
12864 actually necessary to be assumed in geometry are points and | |
12865 lines only; everything constructed out of them, e.g. triangles, | |
12866 squares, tangents, and their properties, e.g. incommensura- | |
12867 bility, has to be <I>proved</I> to exist. This again agrees sub- | |
12868 stantially with Euclid's procedure. Actual construction is | |
12869 with him the proof of existence. If triangles other than the | |
12870 equilateral triangle constructed in I. 1 are assumed in I. 4-21, | |
12871 it is only provisionally, pending the construction of a triangle | |
12872 out of three straight lines in I. 22; the drawing and producing | |
12873 of straight lines and the describing of circles is postulated | |
12874 (Postulates 1-3). Another interesting statement on the | |
12875 philosophical side of geometry has reference to the geometer's | |
12876 hypotheses. It is untrue, says Aristotle, to assert that a | |
12877 geometer's hypotheses are false because he assumes that a line | |
12878 which he has drawn is a foot long when it is not, or straight | |
12879 when it is not straight. The geometer bases no conclusion on | |
12880 the particular line being that which he has assumed it to be; | |
12881 he argues about what it <I>represents,</I> the figure itself being | |
12882 a mere illustration.<note>Arist. <I>Anal. Post.</I> i. 10. 76 b 39-77 a 2; cf. <I>Anal. Prior.</I> i. 41. 49 b 34 sq.; | |
12883 <I>Metaph.</I> N. 2. 1089 a 20-5.</note> | |
12884 <p>Coming now to the first definitions of Euclid, Book I, we | |
12885 find that Aristotle has the equivalents of Defs. 1-3 and 5, 6. | |
12886 But for a straight line he gives Plato's definition only: | |
12887 whence we may fairly conclude that Euclid's definition | |
12888 was his own, as also was his definition of a plane which | |
12889 he adapted from that of a straight line. Some terms seem | |
12890 to have been defined in Aristotle's time which Euclid leaves | |
12891 undefined, e.g. <G>kekla/sqai</G>, ‘to be inflected’, <G>neu/ein</G>, to ‘verge’.<note><I>Anal. Post.</I> i. 10. 76 b 9.</note> | |
12892 Aristotle seems to have known Eudoxus's new theory of pro- | |
12893 portion, and he uses to a considerable extent the usual | |
12894 <pb n=338><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12895 terminology of proportions; he defines similar figures as | |
12896 Euclid does. | |
12897 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>Indications of proofs differing from Euclid's.</I></C> | |
12898 <p>Coming to theorems, we find in Aristotle indications of | |
12899 proofs differing entirely from those of Euclid. The most | |
12900 remarkable case is that of the theorem of I. 5. For the | |
12901 purpose of illustrating the statement that in any syllogism | |
12902 one of the propositions must be affirmative and universal | |
12903 he gives a proof of the proposition as follows.<note><I>Anal. Prior.</I> i. 24. 41 b 13-22.</note> | |
12904 <p>‘For let <I>A, B</I> be drawn [i. e. joined] to the centre. | |
12905 <p>‘If then we assumed (1) that the angle <I>AC</I> [i. e. <I>A</I>+<I>C</I>] | |
12906 is equal to the angle <I>BD</I> [i. e. <I>B</I>+<I>D</I>] without asserting | |
12907 generally that <I>the angles of semicircles are equal,</I> and again | |
12908 <FIG> | |
12909 (2) that the angle <I>C</I> is equal to the | |
12910 angle <I>D</I> without making the further | |
12911 assumption that <I>the two angles of all | |
12912 segments are equal,</I> and if we then | |
12913 inferred, lastly, that since the whole | |
12914 angles are equal, and equal angles are | |
12915 subtracted from them, the angles which | |
12916 remain, namely <I>E, F,</I> are equal, without | |
12917 assuming generally that, if equals be | |
12918 subtracted from equals, the remainders are equal, we should | |
12919 commit a <I>petitio principii.</I>’ | |
12920 <p>There are obvious peculiarities of notation in this extract; | |
12921 the angles are indicated by single letters, and sums of two | |
12922 angles by two letters in juxtaposition (cf. <I>DE</I> for <I>D</I>+<I>E</I> in | |
12923 the proof cited from Archytas above, p. 215). The angles | |
12924 <I>A, B</I> are the angles at <I>A, B</I> of the <I>isosceles triangle OAB,</I> the | |
12925 same angles as are afterwards spoken of as <I>E, F.</I> But the | |
12926 differences of substance between this and Euclid's proof are | |
12927 much more striking. First, it is clear that ‘mixed’ angles | |
12928 (‘angles’ formed by straight lines with circular arcs) played | |
12929 a much larger part in earlier text-books than they do in | |
12930 Euclid, where indeed they only appear once or twice as a | |
12931 survival. Secondly, it is remarkable that the equality of | |
12932 the two ‘angles’ of a semicircle and of the two ‘angles’ of any | |
12933 segment is assumed as a means of proving a proposition so | |
12934 <pb n=339><head>ARISTOTLE</head> | |
12935 elementary as I. 5, although one would say that the assump- | |
12936 tions are no more obvious than the proposition to be proved; | |
12937 indeed some kind of proof, e.g. by superposition, would | |
12938 doubtless be considered necessary to justify the assumptions. | |
12939 It is a natural inference that Euclid's proof of I. 5 was his | |
12940 own, and it would appear that his innovations as regards | |
12941 order of propositions and methods of proof began at the very | |
12942 threshold of the subject. | |
12943 <p>There are two passages<note><I>Anal. Post.</I> i. 5. 74 a 13-16; <I>Anal. Prior.</I> ii. 17. 66 a 11-15.</note> in Aristotle bearing on the theory | |
12944 of parallels which seem to show that the theorems of Eucl. | |
12945 I. 27, 28 are pre-Euclidean; but another passage<note><I>Anal. Prior.</I> ii. 16. 65 a 4.</note> appears to | |
12946 indicate that there was some vicious circle in the theory of | |
12947 parallels then current, for Aristotle alludes to a <I>petitio prin- | |
12948 cipii</I> committed by ‘those who think that they draw parallels’ | |
12949 (or ‘establish the theory of parallels’, <G>ta\s parallh/lous | |
12950 gra/fein</G>), and, as I have tried to show elsewhere,<note>See <I>The Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements,</I> vol. i, pp. 191-2 (cf. | |
12951 pp. 308-9).</note> a note of | |
12952 Philoponus makes it possible that Aristotle is criticizing a | |
12953 <I>direction</I>-theory of parallels such as has been adopted so | |
12954 often in modern text-books. It would seem, therefore, to have | |
12955 been Euclid who first got rid of the <I>petitio principii</I> in earlier | |
12956 text-books by formulating the famous Postulate 5 and basing | |
12957 I. 29 upon it. | |
12958 <p>A difference of method is again indicated in regard to the | |
12959 theorem of Eucl. III. 31 that the angle in a semicircle is right. | |
12960 Two passages of Aristotle taken together<note><I>Anal. Post.</I> ii. 11. 94 a 28; <I>Metaph.</I> <G>*q</G>. 9. 1051 a 26.</note> show that before | |
12961 Euclid the proposition was proved by means of the radius | |
12962 drawn to the middle point of the | |
12963 <FIG> | |
12964 arc of the semicircle. Joining the | |
12965 extremity of this radius to the ex- | |
12966 tremities of the diameter respec- | |
12967 tively, we have two isosceles right- | |
12968 angled triangles, and the two angles, | |
12969 one in each triangle, which are at the middle point of the arc, | |
12970 being both of them halves of right angles, make the angle in | |
12971 the semicircle <I>at that point</I> a right angle. The proof of the | |
12972 theorem must have been completed by means of the theorem | |
12973 <pb n=340><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
12974 of III. 21 that angles in the same segment are equal, a proposi- | |
12975 tion which Euclid's more general proof does not need to use. | |
12976 <p>These instances are sufficient to show that Euclid was far | |
12977 from taking four complete Books out of an earlier text-book | |
12978 without change; his changes began at the very beginning, | |
12979 and there are probably few, if any, groups of propositions in | |
12980 which he did not introduce some improvements of arrange- | |
12981 ment or method. | |
12982 <p>It is unnecessary to go into further detail regarding | |
12983 Euclidean theorems found in Aristotle except to note the | |
12984 interesting fact that Aristotle already has the principle of | |
12985 the method of exhaustion used by Eudoxus: ‘If I continually | |
12986 add to a finite magnitude, I shall exceed every assigned | |
12987 (‘defined’, <G>w(risme/nou</G>) magnitude, and similarly, if I subtract, | |
12988 I shall fall short (of any assigned magnitude).’<note>Arist. <I>Phys.</I> viii. 10. 266 b 2.</note> | |
12989 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Propositions not found in Euclid.</I></C> | |
12990 <p>Some propositions found in Aristotle but not in Euclid | |
12991 should be mentioned. (1) The exterior angles of any polygon | |
12992 are together equal to four right angles<note><I>Anal. Post.</I> i. 24. 85 b 38; ii. 17. 99 a 19.</note>; although omitted | |
12993 in Euclid and supplied by Proclus, this is evidently a Pytha- | |
12994 gorean proposition. (2) The locus of a point such that its | |
12995 distances from two given points are in a given ratio (not | |
12996 being a ratio of equality) is a circle<note><I>Meteorologica,</I> iii. 5. 376 a 3 sq.</note>; this is a proposition | |
12997 quoted by Eutocius from Apollonius's <I>Plane Loci,</I> but the | |
12998 proof given by Aristotle differs very little from that of | |
12999 Apollonius as reproduced by Eutocius, which shows that the | |
13000 proposition was fully known and a standard proof of it was in | |
13001 existence before Euclid's time. (3) Of all closed lines starting | |
13002 from a point, returning to it again, and including a given | |
13003 area, the circumference of a circle is the shortest<note><I>De caelo,</I> ii. 4. 287 a 27.</note>; this shows | |
13004 that the study of isoperimetry (comparison of the perimeters | |
13005 of different figures having the same area) began long before | |
13006 the date of Zenodorus's treatise quoted by Pappus and Theon | |
13007 of Alexandria. (4) Only two solids can fill up space, namely | |
13008 the pyramid and the cube<note><I>Ib.</I> iii. 8. 306 b 7.</note>; this is the complement of the | |
13009 Pythagorean statement that the only three figures which can | |
13010 <pb n=341><head>ARISTOTLE</head> | |
13011 by being put together fill up space in a plane are the equi- | |
13012 lateral triangle, the square and the regular hexagon. | |
13013 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>Curves and solids known to Aristotle.</I></C> | |
13014 <p>There is little beyond elementary plane geometry in Aris- | |
13015 totle. He has the distinction between straight and ‘curved’ | |
13016 lines (<G>kampu/lai grammai/</G>), but the only curve mentioned | |
13017 specifically, besides circles, seems to be the spiral<note><I>Phys.</I> v. 4. 228 b 24.</note>; this | |
13018 term may have no more than the vague sense which it has | |
13019 in the expression ‘the spirals of the heaven’<note><I>Metaph.</I> B. 2. 998 a 5.</note>; if it really | |
13020 means the cylindrical helix, Aristotle does not seem to have | |
13021 realized its property, for he includes it among things which | |
13022 are not such that ‘any part will coincide with any other | |
13023 part’, whereas Apollonius later proved that the cylindrical | |
13024 helix has precisely this property. | |
13025 <p>In solid geometry he distinguishes clearly the three dimen- | |
13026 sions belonging to ‘body’, and, in addition to parallelepipedal | |
13027 solids, such as cubes, he is familiar with spheres, cones and | |
13028 cylinders. A sphere he defines as the figure which has all its | |
13029 radii (‘lines from the centre’) equal,<note><I>Phys.</I> ii. 4. 287 a 19.</note> from which we may infer | |
13030 that Euclid's definition of it as the solid generated by the revo- | |
13031 lution of a semicircle about its diameter is his own (Eucl. XI, | |
13032 Def. 14). Referring to a cone, he says<note><I>Meteorologica,</I> iii. 5. 375 b 21.</note> ‘the straight lines | |
13033 thrown out from <I>K</I> in the form of a cone make <I>GK as a sort | |
13034 of axis</I> (<G>w(/sper a)/xona</G>)’, showing that the use of the word | |
13035 ‘axis’ was not yet quite technical; of conic sections he does | |
13036 not seem to have had any knowledge, although he must have | |
13037 been contemporary with Menaechmus. When he alludes to | |
13038 ‘two cubes being a cube’ he is not speaking, as one might | |
13039 suppose, of the duplication of the cube, for he is saying that | |
13040 no science is concerned to prove anything outside its own | |
13041 subject-matter; thus geometry is not required to prove ‘that | |
13042 two cubes are a cube’<note><I>Anal. Post.</I> i. 7. 75 b 12.</note>; hence the sense of this expression | |
13043 must be not geometrical but arithmetical, meaning that the | |
13044 product of two cube numbers is also a cube number. In the | |
13045 Aristotelian <I>Problems</I> there is a question which, although not | |
13046 mathematical in intention, is perhaps the first suggestion of | |
13047 <pb n=342><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
13048 a certain class of investigation. If a book in the form of a | |
13049 cylindrical roll is cut by a plane and then unrolled, why is it | |
13050 that the cut edge appears as a straight line if the section | |
13051 is parallel to the base (i. e. is a right section), but as a crooked | |
13052 line if the section is obliquely inclined (to the axis).<note><I>Probl.</I> xvi. 6. 914 a 25.</note> The | |
13053 <I>Problems</I> are not by Aristotle; but, whether this one goes | |
13054 back to Aristotle or not, it is unlikely that he would think of | |
13055 investigating the form of the curve mathematically. | |
13056 <C>(<G>e</G>) <I>The continuous and the infinite.</I></C> | |
13057 <p>Much light was thrown by Aristotle on certain general | |
13058 conceptions entering into mathematics such as the ‘continuous’ | |
13059 and the ‘infinite’. The continuous, he held, could not be | |
13060 made up of indivisible parts; the continuous is that in which | |
13061 the boundary or limit between two consecutive parts, where | |
13062 they touch, is one and the same, and which, as the name | |
13063 itself implies, is <I>kept together,</I> which is not possible if the | |
13064 extremities are two and not one.<note><I>Phys.</I> v. 3. 227 a 11; vii. 1. 231 a 24.</note> The ‘infinite’ or ‘un- | |
13065 limited’ only exists potentially, not in actuality. The infinite | |
13066 is so in virtue of its endlessly changing into something else, | |
13067 like day or the Olympic games, and is manifested in different | |
13068 forms, e.g. in time, in Man, and in the division of magnitudes. | |
13069 For, in general, the infinite consists in something new being | |
13070 continually taken, that something being itself always finite | |
13071 but always different. There is this distinction between the | |
13072 forms above mentioned that, whereas in the case of magnitudes | |
13073 what is once taken remains, in the case of time and Man it | |
13074 passes or is destroyed, but the succession is unbroken. The | |
13075 case of addition is in a sense the same as that of division; | |
13076 in the finite magnitude the former takes place in the converse | |
13077 way to the latter; for, as we see the finite magnitude divided | |
13078 <I>ad infinitum,</I> so we shall find that addition gives a sum | |
13079 tending to a definite limit. Thus, in the case of a finite | |
13080 magnitude, you may take a definite fraction of it and add to | |
13081 it continually in the same ratio; if now the successive added | |
13082 terms do not include one and the same magnitude, whatever | |
13083 it is [i. e. if the successive terms diminish in geometrical | |
13084 progression], you will not come to the end of the finite | |
13085 magnitude, but, if the ratio is increased so that each term | |
13086 <pb n=343><head>ARISTOTLE ON THE INFINITE</head> | |
13087 does include one and the same magnitude, whatever it is, you | |
13088 will come to the end of the finite magnitude, for every finite | |
13089 magnitude is exhausted by continually taking from it any | |
13090 definite fraction whatever. In no other sense does the infinite | |
13091 exist but only in the sense just mentioned, that is, potentially | |
13092 and by way of diminution.<note><I>Phys.</I> iii. 6. 206 a 15-6 13.</note> And in this sense you may have | |
13093 potentially infinite addition, the process being, as we say, in | |
13094 a manner the same as with division <I>ad infinitum</I>; for in the | |
13095 case of addition you will always be able to find something | |
13096 outside the total for the time being, but the total will never | |
13097 exceed every definite (or assigned) magnitude in the way that, | |
13098 in the direction of division, the result will pass every definite | |
13099 magnitude, that is, by becoming smaller than it. The infinite | |
13100 therefore cannot exist, even potentially, in the sense of exceed- | |
13101 ing every finite magnitude as the result of successive addition. | |
13102 It follows that the correct view of the infinite is the opposite | |
13103 of that commonly held; it is not that which has nothing | |
13104 outside it, but that which always has something outside it.<note><I>Ib.</I> iii. 6. 206 b 16-207 a 1.</note> | |
13105 Aristotle is aware that it is essentially of physical magnitudes | |
13106 that he is speaking: it is, he says, perhaps a more general | |
13107 inquiry that would be necessary to determine whether the | |
13108 infinite is possible in mathematics and in the domain of | |
13109 thought and of things which have no magnitude.<note><I>Ib.</I> iii. 5. 204 a 34.</note> | |
13110 <p>‘But’, he says, ‘my argument does not anyhow rob | |
13111 mathematicians of their study, although it denies the existence | |
13112 of the infinite in the sense of actual existence as something | |
13113 increased to such an extent that it cannot be gone through | |
13114 (<G>a)diexi/thton</G>); for, as it is, they do not even need the infinite | |
13115 or use it, but only require that the finite (straight line) shall | |
13116 be as long <I>as they please.</I> . . . Hence it will make no difference | |
13117 to them for the purpose of demonstration.’<note><I>Ib.</I> iii. 7. 207 b 27.</note> | |
13118 <p>The above disquisition about the infinite should, I think, | |
13119 be interesting to mathematicians for the distinct expression | |
13120 of Aristotle's view that the existence of an infinite series the | |
13121 terms of which are <I>magnitudes</I> is impossible unless it is | |
13122 convergent and (with reference to Riemann's developments) | |
13123 that it does not matter to geometry if the straight line is not | |
13124 infinite in length provided that it is as long as we please. | |
13125 <pb n=344><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
13126 Aristotle's denial of even the potential existence of a sum | |
13127 of magnitudes which shall exceed every definite magnitude | |
13128 was, as he himself implies, inconsistent with the lemma or | |
13129 assumption used by Eudoxus in his method of exhaustion. | |
13130 We can, therefore, well understand why, a century later, | |
13131 Archimedes felt it necessary to justify his own use of the | |
13132 lemma: | |
13133 <p>‘the earlier geometers too have used this lemma: for it is by | |
13134 its help that they have proved that circles have to one another | |
13135 the duplicate ratio of their diameters, that spheres have to | |
13136 one another the triplicate ratio of their diameters, and so on. | |
13137 And, in the result, each of the said theorems has been accepted | |
13138 no less than those proved without the aid of this lemma.’<note>Archimedes, <I>Quadrature of a Parabola,</I> Preface.</note> | |
13139 <C>(<G>z</G>) <I>Mechanics.</I></C> | |
13140 <p>An account of the mathematics in Aristotle would be incom- | |
13141 plete without a reference to his ideas in mechanics, where he | |
13142 laid down principles which, even though partly erroneous, | |
13143 held their ground till the time of Benedetti (1530-90) and | |
13144 Galilei (1564-1642). The <I>Mechanica</I> included in the Aris- | |
13145 totelian writings is not indeed Aristotle's own work, but it is | |
13146 very close in date, as we may conclude from its terminology; | |
13147 this shows more general agreement with the terminology of | |
13148 Euclid than is found in Aristotle's own writings, but certain | |
13149 divergences from Euclid's terms are common to the latter and | |
13150 to the <I>Mechanica</I>; the conclusion from which is that the | |
13151 <I>Mechanica</I> was written before Euclid had made the termino- | |
13152 logy of mathematics more uniform and convenient, or, in the | |
13153 alternative, that it was composed after Euclid's time by persons | |
13154 who, though they had partly assimilated Euclid's terminology, | |
13155 were close enough to Aristotle's date to be still influenced | |
13156 by his usage. But the Aristotelian origin of many of the | |
13157 ideas in the <I>Mechanica</I> is proved by their occurrence in | |
13158 Aristotle's genuine writings. Take, for example, the principle | |
13159 of the lever. In the <I>Mechanica</I> we are told that, | |
13160 <p>‘as the weight moved is to the moving weight, so is the | |
13161 length (or distance) to the length inversely. In fact the mov- | |
13162 ing weight will more easily move (the system) the farther it | |
13163 is away from the fulcrum. The reason is that aforesaid, | |
13164 <pb n=345><head>ARISTOTELIAN MECHANICS</head> | |
13165 namely that the line which is farther from the centre describes | |
13166 the greater circle, so that, if the power applied is the same, | |
13167 that which moves (the system) will change its position the | |
13168 more, the farther it is away from the fulcrum.’<note><I>Mechanica,</I> 3. 850 b 1.</note> | |
13169 <p>The idea then is that the greater power exerted by the | |
13170 weight at the greater distance corresponds to its greater | |
13171 velocity. Compare with this the passage in the <I>De caelo</I> | |
13172 where Aristotle is speaking of the speeds of the circles of | |
13173 the stars: | |
13174 <p>‘it is not at all strange, nay it is inevitable, that the speeds of | |
13175 circles should be in the proportion of their sizes.’<note><I>De caelo,</I> ii. 8. 289 b 15.</note> . . . ‘Since | |
13176 in two concentric circles the segment (sector) of the outer cut | |
13177 off between two radii common to both circles is greater than | |
13178 that cut off on the inner, it is reasonable that the greater circle | |
13179 should be carried round in the same time.’<note><I>Ib.</I> 290 a 2.</note> | |
13180 <p>Compare again the passage of the <I>Mechanica</I>: | |
13181 <p>‘what happens with the balance is reduced to (the case of the) | |
13182 circle, the case of the lever to that of the balance, and | |
13183 practically everything concerning mechanical movements to | |
13184 the case of the lever. Further it is the fact that, given | |
13185 a radius of a circle, no two points of it move at the same | |
13186 speed (as the radius itself revolves), but the point more distant | |
13187 from the centre always moves more quickly, and this is the | |
13188 reason of many remarkable facts about the movements of | |
13189 circles which will appear in the sequel.’<note><I>Mechanica,</I> 848 a 11.</note> | |
13190 <p>The axiom which is regarded as containing the germ of the | |
13191 principle of virtual velocities is enunciated, in slightly different | |
13192 forms, in the <I>De caelo</I> and the <I>Physics</I>: | |
13193 <p>‘A smaller and lighter weight will be given more movement | |
13194 if the force acting on it is the same. . . . The speed of the | |
13195 lesser body will be to that of the greater as the greater body | |
13196 is to the lesser.’<note><I>De caelo,</I> iii. 2. 301 b 4, 11.</note> | |
13197 <p>‘If <I>A</I> be the movent, <I>B</I> the thing moved, <I>C</I> the length | |
13198 through which it is moved, <I>D</I> the time taken, then | |
13199 <p><I>A</I> will move 1/2<I>B</I> over the distance 2 <I>C</I> in the time <I>D,</I> | |
13200 and <I>A</I> ” 1/2<I>B</I> ” ” <I>C</I> ” ” 1/2<I>D</I>; | |
13201 thus proportion is maintained.’<note><I>Phys.</I> vii. 5. 249 b 30-250 a 4.</note> | |
13202 <pb n=346><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
13203 <p>Again, says Aristotle, | |
13204 <p><I>A</I> will move <I>B</I> over the distance 1/2<I>C</I> in the time 1/2<I>D,</I> | |
13205 and 1/2<I>A</I> ” 1/2<I>B</I> a distance <I>C</I> ” ” <I>D</I>;<note><I>Phys.</I> vii. 5. 250 a 4-7.</note> | |
13206 and so on. | |
13207 <p>Lastly, we have in the <I>Mechanica</I> the parallelogram of | |
13208 velocities: | |
13209 <p>‘When a body is moved in a certain ratio (i. e. has two linear | |
13210 movements in a constant ratio to one another), the body must | |
13211 move in a straight line, and this straight line is the diameter | |
13212 of the figure (parallelogram) formed from the straight lines | |
13213 which have the given ratio.’<note><I>Mechanica,</I> 2. 848 b 10.</note> | |
13214 <p>The author goes on to say<note><I>Ib.</I> 848 b 26 sq.</note> that, if the ratio of the two | |
13215 movements does not remain the same from one instant to the | |
13216 next, the motion will not be in a straight line but in a curve. | |
13217 He instances a circle in a vertical plane with a point moving | |
13218 along it downwards from the topmost point; the point has | |
13219 two simultaneous movements; one is in a vertical line, the | |
13220 other displaces this vertical line parallel to itself away from | |
13221 the position in which it passes through the centre till it | |
13222 reaches the position of a tangent to the circle; if during this | |
13223 time the ratio of the two movements were constant, say one of | |
13224 equality, the point would not move along the circumference | |
13225 at all but along the diagonal of a rectangle. | |
13226 <p>The parallelogram of <I>forces</I> is easily deduced from the | |
13227 parallelogram of velocities combined with Aristotle's axiom | |
13228 that the force which moves a given weight is directed along | |
13229 the line of the weight's motion and is proportional to the | |
13230 distance described by the weight in a given time. | |
13231 <p>Nor should we omit to mention the Aristotelian tract <I>On | |
13232 indivisible lines.</I> We have seen (p. 293) that, according to | |
13233 Aristotle, Plato objected to the genus ‘point’ as a geometrical | |
13234 fiction, calling a point the beginning of a line, and often | |
13235 positing ‘indivisible lines’ in the same sense.<note><I>Metaph.</I> A. 9. 992 a 20.</note> The idea of | |
13236 indivisible lines appears to have been only vaguely conceived | |
13237 by Plato, but it took shape in his school, and with Xenocrates | |
13238 <pb n=347><head>THE TRACT ON INDIVISIBLE LINES</head> | |
13239 became a definite doctrine. There is plenty of evidence for | |
13240 this<note>Cf. Zeller, ii. 1<SUP>4</SUP>, p. 1017.</note>; Proclus, for instance, tells us of ‘a discourse or argu- | |
13241 ment by Xenocrates introducing indivisible lines’.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 279. 5.</note> The tract | |
13242 <I>On indivisible lines</I> was no doubt intended as a counterblast | |
13243 to Xenocrates. It can hardly have been written by Aristotle | |
13244 himself; it contains, for instance, some expressions without | |
13245 parallel in Aristotle. But it is certainly the work of some | |
13246 one belonging to the school; and we can imagine that, having | |
13247 on some occasion to mention ‘indivisible lines’, Aristotle may | |
13248 well have set to some pupil, as an exercise, the task of refuting | |
13249 Xenocrates. According to Simplicius and Philoponus, the | |
13250 tract was attributed by some to Theophrastus<note>See Zeller, ii. 2<SUP>3</SUP>, p. 90, note.</note>; and this | |
13251 seems the most likely supposition, especially as Diogenes | |
13252 Laertius mentions, in a list of works by Theophrastus, ‘<I>On | |
13253 indivisible lines,</I> one Book’. The text is in many places | |
13254 corrupt, so that it is often difficult or impossible to restore the | |
13255 argument. In reading the book we feel that the writer is | |
13256 for the most part chopping logic rather than contributing | |
13257 seriously to the philosophy of mathematics. The interest | |
13258 of the work to the historian of mathematics is of the slightest. | |
13259 It does indeed cite the equivalent of certain definitions and | |
13260 propositions in Euclid, especially Book X (on irrationals), and | |
13261 in particular it mentions the irrationals called ‘binomial’ or | |
13262 ‘apotome’, though, as far as irrationals are concerned, the | |
13263 writer may have drawn on Theaetetus rather than Euclid. | |
13264 The mathematical phraseology is in many places similar to | |
13265 that of Euclid, but the writer shows a tendency to hark back | |
13266 to older and less fixed terminology such as is usual in | |
13267 Aristotle. The tract begins with a section stating the argu- | |
13268 ments for indivisible lines, which we may take to represent | |
13269 Xenocrates's own arguments. The next section purports to | |
13270 refute these arguments one by one, after which other con- | |
13271 siderations are urged against indivisible lines. It is sought to | |
13272 show that the hypothesis of indivisible lines is not reconcilable | |
13273 with the principles assumed, or the conclusions proved, in | |
13274 mathematics; next, it is argued that, if a line is made up | |
13275 of indivisible lines (whether an odd or even number of such | |
13276 lines), or if the indivisible line has any point in it, or points | |
13277 <pb n=348><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
13278 terminating it, the indivisible line must be divisible; and, | |
13279 lastly, various arguments are put forward to show that a line | |
13280 can no more be made up of points than of indivisible lines, | |
13281 with more about the relation of points to lines, &c.<note>A revised text of the work is included in Aristotle, <I>De plantis,</I> edited | |
13282 by O. Apelt, who also gave a German translation of it in <I>Beiträge zur | |
13283 Geschichte der griechischen Philosophie</I> (1891), pp. 271-86. A translation | |
13284 by H. H. Joachim has since appeared (1908) in the series of Oxford | |
13285 Translations of Aristotle's works.</note> | |
13286 <C>Sphaeric.</C> | |
13287 <p>AUTOLYCUS of Pitane was the teacher of Arcesilaus (about | |
13288 315-241/40 B.C.), also of Pitane, the founder of the so-called | |
13289 Middle Academy. He may be taken to have flourished about | |
13290 310 B.C. or a little earlier, so that he was an elder con- | |
13291 temporary of Euclid. We hear of him in connexion with | |
13292 Eudoxus's theory of concentric spheres, to which he adhered. | |
13293 The great difficulty in the way of this theory was early seen, | |
13294 namely the impossibility of reconciling the assumption of the | |
13295 invariability of the distance of each planet with the observed | |
13296 differences in the brightness, especially of Mars and Venus, | |
13297 at different times, and the apparent differences in the relative | |
13298 sizes of the sun and moon. We are told that no one before | |
13299 Autolycus had even attempted to deal with this difficulty | |
13300 ‘by means of hypotheses’, i. e. (presumably) in a theoretical | |
13301 manner, and even he was not successful, as clearly appeared | |
13302 from his controversy with Aristotherus<note>Simplicius on <I>De caelo,</I> p. 504. 22-5 Heib.</note> (who was the teacher | |
13303 of Aratus); this implies that Autolycus's argument was in | |
13304 a written treatise. | |
13305 <p>Two works by Autolycus have come down to us. They | |
13306 both deal with the geometry of the sphere in its application | |
13307 to astronomy. The definite place which they held among | |
13308 Greek astronomical text-books is attested by the fact that, as | |
13309 we gather from Pappus, one of them, the treatise <I>On the | |
13310 moving Sphere,</I> was included in the list of works forming | |
13311 the ‘Little Astronomy’, as it was called afterwards, to distin- | |
13312 guish it from the ‘Great Collection’ (<G>mega/lh su/ntaxis</G>) of | |
13313 Ptolemy; and we may doubtless assume that the other work | |
13314 <I>On Risings and Settings</I> was similarly included. | |
13315 <pb n=349><head>AUTOLYCUS OF PITANE</head> | |
13316 <p>Both works have been well edited by Hultsch with Latin | |
13317 translation.<note><I>Autolyci De sphaera quae movetur liber, De ortibus et occasibus libri duo</I> | |
13318 edidit F. Hultsch (Teubner 1885).</note> They are of great interest for several reasons. | |
13319 First, Autolycus is the earliest Greek mathematician from | |
13320 whom original treatises have come down to us entire, the next | |
13321 being Euclid, Aristarchus and Archimedes. That he wrote | |
13322 earlier than Euclid is clear from the fact that Euclid, in his | |
13323 similar work, the <I>Phaenomena,</I> makes use of propositions | |
13324 appearing in Autolycus, though, as usual in such cases, giving | |
13325 no indication of their source. The form of Autolycus's proposi- | |
13326 tions is exactly the same as that with which we are familiar | |
13327 in Euclid; we have first the enunciation of the proposition in | |
13328 general terms, then the particular enunciation with reference | |
13329 to a figure with letters marking the various points in it, then | |
13330 the demonstration, and lastly, in some cases but not in all, the | |
13331 conclusion in terms similar to those of the enunciation. This | |
13332 shows that Greek geometrical propositions had already taken | |
13333 the form which we recognize as classical, and that Euclid did | |
13334 not invent this form or introduce any material changes. | |
13335 <C>A lost text-book on Sphaeric.</C> | |
13336 <p>More important still is the fact that Autolycus, as well as | |
13337 Euclid, makes use of a number of propositions relating to the | |
13338 sphere without giving any proof of them or quoting any | |
13339 authority. This indicates that there was already in existence | |
13340 in his time a text-book of the elementary geometry of the | |
13341 sphere, the propositions of which were generally known to | |
13342 mathematicians. As many of these propositions are proved | |
13343 in the <I>Sphaerica</I> of Theodosius, a work compiled two or three | |
13344 centuries later, we may assume that the lost text-book proceeded | |
13345 on much the same lines as that of Theodosius, with much the | |
13346 same order of propositions. Like Theodosius's <I>Sphaerica</I> | |
13347 it treated of the stationary sphere, its sections (great and | |
13348 small circles) and their properties. The geometry of the | |
13349 sphere at rest is of course prior to the consideration of the | |
13350 sphere in motion, i. e. the sphere rotating about its axis, which | |
13351 is the subject of Autolycus's works. Who was the author of | |
13352 the lost pre-Euclidean text-book it is impossible to say; | |
13353 <pb n=350><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
13354 Tannery thought that we could hardly help attributing it to | |
13355 Eudoxus. The suggestion is natural, seeing that Eudoxus | |
13356 showed, in his theory of concentric spheres, an extraordinary | |
13357 mastery of the geometry of the sphere; on the other hand, | |
13358 as Loria observes, it is, speaking generally, dangerous to | |
13359 assume that a work of an unknown author appearing in | |
13360 a certain country at a certain time must have been written | |
13361 by a particular man of science simply because he is the only | |
13362 man of the time of whom we can certainly say that he was | |
13363 capable of writing it.<note>Loria, <I>Le scienze esatte nell' antica Grecia,</I> 1914, p. 496-7.</note> The works of Autolycus also serve to | |
13364 confirm the pre-Euclidean origin of a number of propositions | |
13365 in the <I>Elements.</I> Hultsch<note><I>Berichte der Kgl. Sächs. Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Leipzig,</I> | |
13366 Phil.-hist. Classe, 1886, pp. 128-55.</note> examined this question in detail | |
13367 in a paper of 1886. There are (1) the propositions pre- | |
13368 supposed in one or other of Autolycus's theorems. We have | |
13369 also to take account of (2) the propositions which would be | |
13370 required to establish the propositions in sphaeric assumed by | |
13371 Autolycus as known. The best clue to the propositions under | |
13372 (2) is the actual course of the proofs of the corresponding | |
13373 propositions in the <I>Sphaerica</I> of Theodosius; for Theodosius | |
13374 was only a compiler, and we may with great probability | |
13375 assume that, where Theodosius uses propositions from Euclid's | |
13376 <I>Elements,</I> propositions corresponding to them were used to | |
13377 prove the analogous propositions in the fourth-century | |
13378 <I>Sphaeric.</I> The propositions which, following this criterion, | |
13379 we may suppose to have been directly used for this purpose | |
13380 are, roughly, those represented by Eucl. I. 4, 8, 17, 19, 26, 29, | |
13381 47; III. 1-3, 7, 10, 16 Cor., 26, 28, 29; IV. 6; XI. 3, 4, 10, 11, | |
13382 12, 14, 16, 19, and the interpolated 38. It is, naturally, the | |
13383 subject-matter of Books I, III, and XI that is drawn upon, | |
13384 but, of course, the propositions mentioned by no means | |
13385 exhaust the number of pre-Euclidean propositions even in | |
13386 those Books. When, however, Hultsch increased the list of | |
13387 propositions by adding the whole chain of propositions (in- | |
13388 cluding Postulate 5) leading up to them in Euclid's arrange- | |
13389 ment, he took an unsafe course, because it is clear that many | |
13390 of Euclid's proofs were on different lines from those used | |
13391 by his predecessors. | |
13392 <pb n=351><head>AUTOLYCUS AND EUCLID</head> | |
13393 <p>The work <I>On the moving Sphere</I> assumes abstractly a | |
13394 sphere moving about the axis stretching from pole to pole, | |
13395 and different series of circular sections, the first series being | |
13396 great circles passing through the poles, the second small | |
13397 circles (as well as the equator) which are sections of the | |
13398 sphere by planes at right angles to the axis and are called | |
13399 the ‘parallel circles’, while the third kind are great circles | |
13400 inclined obliquely to the axis of the sphere; the motion of | |
13401 points on these circles is then considered in relation to the | |
13402 section by a fixed plane through the centre of the sphere. | |
13403 It is easy to recognize in the oblique great circle in the sphere | |
13404 the ecliptic or zodiac circle, and in the section made by the | |
13405 fixed plane the horizon, which is described as the circle | |
13406 in the sphere ‘which defines (<G>o(ri/zwn</G>) the visible and the | |
13407 invisible portions of the sphere’. To give an idea of the | |
13408 content of the work, I will quote a few enunciations from | |
13409 Autolycus and along with two of them, for the sake of | |
13410 comparison with Euclid, the corresponding enunciations from | |
13411 the <I>Phaenomena.</I> | |
13412 <table> | |
13413 <tr><th>Autolycus.</th><th>Euclid.</th></tr> | |
13414 <tr><td>1. If a sphere revolve uni-</td><td></td></tr> | |
13415 <tr><td>formly about its own axis, all</td><td></td></tr> | |
13416 <tr><td>the points on the surface of the</td><td></td></tr> | |
13417 <tr><td>sphere which are not on the</td><td></td></tr> | |
13418 <tr><td>axis will describe parallel</td><td></td></tr> | |
13419 <tr><td>circles which have the same</td><td></td></tr> | |
13420 <tr><td>poles as the sphere and are</td><td></td></tr> | |
13421 <tr><td>also at right angles to the axis.</td><td></td></tr> | |
13422 <tr><td>7. If the circle in the sphere</td><td>3. The circles which are at</td></tr> | |
13423 <tr><td>defining the visible and the</td><td>right angles to the axis and</td></tr> | |
13424 <tr><td>invisible portions of the sphere</td><td>cut the horizon make both</td></tr> | |
13425 <tr><td>be obliquely inclined to the</td><td>their risings and settings at</td></tr> | |
13426 <tr><td>axis, the circles which are at</td><td>the same points of the horizon.</td></tr> | |
13427 <tr><td>right angles to the axis and cut</td><td></td></tr> | |
13428 <tr><td>the defining circle [horizon]</td><td></td></tr> | |
13429 <tr><td>always make both their risings</td><td></td></tr> | |
13430 <tr><td>and settings at the same points</td><td></td></tr> | |
13431 <tr><td>of the defining circle [horizon]</td><td></td></tr> | |
13432 <tr><td>and further will also be simi-</td><td></td></tr> | |
13433 <tr><td>larly inclined to that circle.</td><td></td></tr> | |
13434 </table> | |
13435 <pb n=352><head>FROM PLATO TO EUCLID</head> | |
13436 <table> | |
13437 <tr><th>Autolycus.</th><th>Euclid.</th></tr> | |
13438 <tr><td>9. If in a sphere a great</td><td></td></tr> | |
13439 <tr><td>circle which is obliquely in-</td><td></td></tr> | |
13440 <tr><td>clined to the axis define the</td><td></td></tr> | |
13441 <tr><td>visible and the invisible por-</td><td></td></tr> | |
13442 <tr><td>tions of the sphere, then, of</td><td></td></tr> | |
13443 <tr><td>the points which rise at the</td><td></td></tr> | |
13444 <tr><td>same time, those towards the</td><td></td></tr> | |
13445 <tr><td>visible pole set later and, of</td><td></td></tr> | |
13446 <tr><td>those which set at the same</td><td></td></tr> | |
13447 <tr><td>time, those towards the visible</td><td></td></tr> | |
13448 <tr><td>pole rise earlier.</td><td></td></tr> | |
13449 <tr><td>11. If in a sphere a great</td><td>7. That the circle of the</td></tr> | |
13450 <tr><td>circle which is obliquely in-</td><td>zodiac rises and sets over the</td></tr> | |
13451 <tr><td>clined to the axis define the</td><td>whole extent of the horizon</td></tr> | |
13452 <tr><td>visible and the invisible por-</td><td>between the tropics is mani-</td></tr> | |
13453 <tr><td>tions of the sphere, and any</td><td>fest, forasmuch as it touches</td></tr> | |
13454 <tr><td>other oblique great circle</td><td>circles greater than those</td></tr> | |
13455 <tr><td>touch greater (parallel) circles</td><td>which the horizon touches.</td></tr> | |
13456 <tr><td>than those which the defin-</td><td></td></tr> | |
13457 <tr><td>ing circle (horizon) touches,</td><td></td></tr> | |
13458 <tr><td>the said other oblique circle</td><td></td></tr> | |
13459 <tr><td>makes its risings and settings</td><td></td></tr> | |
13460 <tr><td>over the whole extent of the</td><td></td></tr> | |
13461 <tr><td>circumference (arc) of the de-</td><td></td></tr> | |
13462 <tr><td>fining circle included between</td><td></td></tr> | |
13463 <tr><td>the parallel circles which it</td><td></td></tr> | |
13464 <tr><td>touches.</td><td></td></tr> | |
13465 </table> | |
13466 <p>It will be noticed that Autolycus's propositions are more | |
13467 abstract in so far as the ‘other oblique circle’ in Autolycus | |
13468 is any other oblique circle, whereas in Euclid it definitely | |
13469 becomes the zodiac circle. In Euclid ‘the great circle defining | |
13470 the visible and the invisible portions of the sphere’ is already | |
13471 shortened into the technical term ‘horizon’ (<G>o(ri/zwn</G>), which is | |
13472 defined as if for the first time; ‘Let the name <I>horizon</I> be | |
13473 given to the plane through us (as observers) passing through | |
13474 the universe and separating off the hemisphere which is visible | |
13475 above the earth.’ | |
13476 <p>The book <I>On Risings and Settings</I> is of astronomical interest | |
13477 only, and belongs to the region of <I>Phaenomena</I> as understood | |
13478 by Eudoxus and Aratus, that is, observational astronomy. | |
13479 It begins with definitions distinguishing between ‘true’ and | |
13480 <pb n=353><head>AUTOLYCUS ON RISINGS AND SETTINGS</head> | |
13481 ‘apparent’ morning- and evening-risings and settings of fixed | |
13482 stars. The ‘true’ morning-rising (setting) is when the star | |
13483 rises (sets) at the moment of the sun's rising; the ‘true’ | |
13484 morning-rising (setting) is, therefore invisible to us, and so is | |
13485 the ‘true’ evening-rising (setting) which takes place at the | |
13486 moment when the sun is setting. The ‘apparent’ morning- | |
13487 rising (setting) takes place when the star is first seen rising | |
13488 (setting) before the sun rises, and the ‘apparent’ evening- | |
13489 rising (setting) when the star is last seen rising (setting) after | |
13490 the sun has set. The following are the enunciations of a few | |
13491 of the propositions in the treatise. | |
13492 <p>I. 1. In the case of each of the fixed stars the apparent | |
13493 morning-risings and settings are later than the true, and | |
13494 the apparent evening-risings and settings are earlier than | |
13495 the true. | |
13496 <p>I. 2. Each of the fixed stars is seen rising each night from | |
13497 the (time of its) apparent morning-rising to the time of its | |
13498 apparent evening-rising but at no other period, and the time | |
13499 during which the star is seen rising is less than half a year. | |
13500 <p>I. 5. In the case of those of the fixed stars which are on the | |
13501 zodiac circle, the interval from the time of their apparent | |
13502 evening-rising to the time of their apparent evening-setting is | |
13503 half a year, in the case of those north of the zodiac circle | |
13504 more than half a year, and in the case of those south of the | |
13505 zodiac circle less than half a year. | |
13506 <p>II. 1. The twelfth part of the zodiac circle in which the | |
13507 sun is, is neither seen rising nor setting, but is hidden; and | |
13508 similarly the twelfth part which is opposite to it is neither | |
13509 seen setting nor rising but is visible above the earth the whole | |
13510 of the nights. | |
13511 <p>II. 4. Of the fixed stars those which are cut off by the | |
13512 zodiac circle in the northerly or the southerly direction will | |
13513 reach their evening-setting at an interval of five months from | |
13514 their morning-rising. | |
13515 <p>II. 9. Of the stars which are carried on the same (parallel-) | |
13516 circle those which are cut off by the zodiac circle in the | |
13517 northerly direction will be hidden a shorter time than those | |
13518 on the southern side of the zodiac. | |
13519 <pb><C>XI | |
13520 EUCLID | |
13521 Date and traditions.</C> | |
13522 <p>WE have very few particulars of the lives of the great | |
13523 mathematicians of Greece. Even Euclid is no exception. | |
13524 Practically all that is known about him is contained in a few | |
13525 sentences of Proclus's summary: | |
13526 <p>‘Not much younger than these (sc. Hermotimus of Colophon | |
13527 and Philippus of Mende or Medma) is Euclid, who put to- | |
13528 gether the Elements, collecting many of Eudoxus's theorems, | |
13529 perfecting many of Theaetetus's, and also bringing to irre- | |
13530 fragable demonstration the things which were only somewhat | |
13531 loosely proved by his predecessors. This man lived in the | |
13532 time of the first Ptolemy. For Archimedes, who came | |
13533 immediately after the first (Ptolemy), makes mention of | |
13534 Euclid; and further they say that Ptolemy once asked him if | |
13535 there was in geometry any shorter way than that of the | |
13536 Elements, and he replied that there was no royal road to | |
13537 geometry. He is then younger than the pupils of Plato, but | |
13538 older than Eratosthenes and Archimedes, the latter having | |
13539 been contemporaries, as Eratosthenes somewhere says.’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 68. 6-20.</note> | |
13540 <p>This passage shows that even Proclus had no direct know- | |
13541 ledge of Euclid's birthplace, or of the dates of his birth and | |
13542 death; he can only infer generally at what period he flourished. | |
13543 All that is certain is that Euclid was later than the first | |
13544 pupils of Plato and earlier than Archimedes. As Plato died | |
13545 in 347 B.C. and Archimedes lived from 287 to 212 B.C., Euclid | |
13546 must have flourished about 300 B.C., a date which agrees well | |
13547 with the statement that he lived under the first Ptolemy, who | |
13548 reigned from 306 to 283 B.C. | |
13549 <pb n=355><head>DATE AND TRADITIONS</head> | |
13550 <p>More particulars are, it is true, furnished by Arabian | |
13551 authors. We are told that | |
13552 <p>‘Euclid, son of Naucrates, and grandson of Zenarchus [the | |
13553 <I>Fihrist</I> has ‘son of Naucrates, the son of Berenice (?)’], called | |
13554 the author of geometry, a philosopher of somewhat ancient | |
13555 date, a Greek by nationality, domiciled at Damascus, born at | |
13556 Tyre, most learned in the science of geometry, published | |
13557 a most excellent and most useful work entitled the foundation | |
13558 or elements of geometry, a subject in which no more general | |
13559 treatise existed before among the Greeks: nay, there was no | |
13560 one even of later date who did not walk in his footsteps and | |
13561 frankly profess his doctrine. Hence also Greek, Roman, | |
13562 and Arabian geometers not a few, who undertook the task of | |
13563 illustrating this work, published commentaries, scholia, and | |
13564 notes upon it, and made an abridgement of the work itself. | |
13565 For this reason the Greek philosophers used to post up on the | |
13566 doors of their schools the well-known notice, “Let no one | |
13567 come to our school, who has not first learnt the elements | |
13568 of Euclid”.’<note>Casiri, <I>Bibliotheca Arabico-Hispana Escurialensis</I>, i, p. 339 (Casiri's | |
13569 source is the <I>Ta)rīkh al-&Hdot;ukamā</I> of al-Qif⃛ī (d. 1248).</note> | |
13570 <p>This shows the usual tendency of the Arabs to romance. | |
13571 They were in the habit of recording the names of grand- | |
13572 fathers, while the Greeks were not; Damascus and Tyre were | |
13573 no doubt brought in to gratify the desire which the Arabians | |
13574 always showed to connect famous Greeks in some way or other | |
13575 with the east (thus they described Pythagoras as a pupil of the | |
13576 wise Salomo, and Hipparchus as ‘the Chaldaean’). We recog- | |
13577 nize the inscription over the doors of the schools of the Greek | |
13578 philosophers as a variation of Plato's <G>mhdei\s a)gewme/trhtos | |
13579 ei)si/tw</G>; the philosopher has become Greek philosophers in | |
13580 general, the school their schools, while geometry has become | |
13581 the <I>Elements</I> of Euclid. The Arabs even explained that the | |
13582 name of Euclid, which they pronounced variously as <I>Uclides</I> or | |
13583 <I>Icludes</I>, was compounded of <I>Ucli</I>, a key, and <I>Dis</I>, a measure, or, | |
13584 as some say, geometry, so that Uclides is equivalent to the | |
13585 <I>key of geometry</I>! | |
13586 <p>In the Middle Ages most translators and editors spoke of | |
13587 Euclid as Euclid <I>of Megara</I>, confusing our Euclid with Euclid | |
13588 the philosopher, and the contemporary of Plato, who lived about | |
13589 400 B.C. The first trace of the confusion appears in Valerius | |
13590 <pb n=356><head>EUCLID</head> | |
13591 Maximus (in the time of Tiberius) who says<note>viii. 12, ext. 1.</note> that Plato, | |
13592 on being appealed to for a solution of the problem of doubling | |
13593 the cube, sent the inquirers to ‘Euclid the geometer’. The | |
13594 mistake was seen by one Constantinus Lascaris (d. about | |
13595 1493), and the first translator to point it out clearly was | |
13596 Commandinus (in his translation of Euclid published in 1572). | |
13597 <p>Euclid may have been a Platonist, as Proclus says, though | |
13598 this is not certain. In any case, he probably received his | |
13599 mathematical training in Athens from the pupils of Plato; | |
13600 most of the geometers who could have taught him were of | |
13601 that school. But he himself taught and founded a school | |
13602 at Alexandria, as we learn from Pappus's statement that | |
13603 Apollonius ‘spent a very long time with the pupils of Euclid | |
13604 at Alexandria’.<note>Pappus, vii, p. 678. 10-12.</note> Here again come in our picturesque | |
13605 Arabians,<note>The authorities are al-Kindī, <I>De instituto libri Euclidis</I> and a commen- | |
13606 tary by Qā&ddot;īzāde on the <I>Ashkal at-ta)sīs</I> of Ashraf Shamsaddīn as-Samar- | |
13607 qandī (quoted by Casiri and &Hdot;ājī Khalfa).</note> who made out that the <I>Elements</I> were originally | |
13608 written by a man whose name was Apollonius, a carpenter, | |
13609 who wrote the work in fifteen books or sections (this idea | |
13610 seems to be based on some misunderstanding of Hypsicles's | |
13611 preface to the so-called Book XIV of Euclid), and that, as | |
13612 some of the work was lost in course of time and the rest | |
13613 disarranged, one of the kings at Alexandria who desired to | |
13614 study geometry and to master this treatise in particular first | |
13615 questioned about it certain learned men who visited him, and | |
13616 then sent for Euclid, who was at that time famous as a | |
13617 geometer, and asked him to revise and complete the work | |
13618 and reduce it to order, upon which Euclid rewrote the work | |
13619 in thirteen books, thereafter known by his name. | |
13620 <p>On the character of Euclid Pappus has a remark which, | |
13621 however, was probably influenced by his obvious animus | |
13622 against Apollonius, whose preface to the <I>Conics</I> seemed to him | |
13623 to give too little credit to Euclid for his earlier work in the same | |
13624 subject. Pappus contrasts Euclid's attitude to his predecessors. | |
13625 Euclid, he says, was no such boaster or controversialist: thus | |
13626 he regarded Aristaeus as deserving credit for the discoveries | |
13627 he had made in conics, and made no attempt to anticipate | |
13628 him or to construct afresh the same system, such was his | |
13629 scrupulous fairness and his exemplary kindliness to all who | |
13630 <pb n=357><head>DATE AND TRADITIONS</head> | |
13631 could advance mathematical science to however small an | |
13632 extent.<note>Pappus, vii, pp. 676. 25-678. 6.</note> Although, as I have indicated, Pappus's motive was | |
13633 rather to represent Apollonius in a relatively unfavourable | |
13634 light than to state a historical fact about Euclid, the state- | |
13635 ment accords well with what we should gather from Euclid's | |
13636 own works. These show no sign of any claim to be original; | |
13637 in the <I>Elements</I>, for instance, although it is clear that he | |
13638 made great changes, altering the arrangement of whole Books, | |
13639 redistributing propositions between them, and inventing new | |
13640 proofs where the new order made the earlier proofs inappli- | |
13641 cable, it is safe to say that he made no more alterations than | |
13642 his own acumen and the latest special investigations (such as | |
13643 Eudoxus's theory of proportion) showed to be imperative in | |
13644 order to make the exposition of the whole subject more | |
13645 scientific than the earlier efforts of writers of elements. His | |
13646 respect for tradition is seen in his retention of some things | |
13647 which were out of date and useless, e. g. certain definitions | |
13648 never afterwards used, the solitary references to the angle | |
13649 of a semicircle or the angle of a segment, and the like; he | |
13650 wrote no sort of preface to his work (would that he had!) | |
13651 such as those in which Archimedes and Apollonius introduced | |
13652 their treatises and distinguished what they claimed as new in | |
13653 them from what was already known: he plunges at once into | |
13654 his subject, ‘<I>A point is that which has no part</I>’! | |
13655 <p>And what a teacher he must have been! One story enables | |
13656 us to picture him in that capacity. According to Stobaeus, | |
13657 <p>‘some one who had begun to read geometry with Euclid, | |
13658 when he had learnt the first theorem, asked Euclid, “what | |
13659 shall I get by learning these things?” Euclid called his slave | |
13660 and said, “Give him threepence, since he must make gain out | |
13661 of what he learns”.’<note>Stobaeus, <I>Floril.</I> iv. p. 205.</note> | |
13662 <p>Ancient commentaries, criticisms, and references. | |
13663 <p>Euclid has, of course, always been known almost exclusively | |
13664 as the author of the <I>Elements.</I> From Archimedes onwards | |
13665 the Greeks commonly spoke of him as <G>o( stoixeiw/ths</G>, the | |
13666 writer of the <I>Elements</I>, instead of using his name. This | |
13667 wonderful book, with all its imperfections, which indeed are | |
13668 slight enough when account is taken of the date at which | |
13669 <pb n=358><head>EUCLID</head> | |
13670 it appeared, is and will doubtless remain the greatest mathe- | |
13671 matical text-book of all time. Scarcely any other book | |
13672 except the Bible can have circulated more widely the world | |
13673 over, or been more edited and studied. Even in Greek times | |
13674 the most accomplished mathematicians occupied themselves | |
13675 with it; Heron, Pappus, Porphyry, Proclus and Simplicius | |
13676 wrote commentaries; Theon of Alexandria re-edited it, alter- | |
13677 ing the language here and there, mostly with a view to | |
13678 greater clearness and consistency, and interpolating inter- | |
13679 mediate steps, alternative proofs, separate ‘cases’, porisms | |
13680 (corollaries) and lemmas (the most important addition being | |
13681 the second part of VI. 33 relating to <I>sectors</I>). Even the great | |
13682 Apollonius was moved by Euclid's work to discuss the first | |
13683 principles of geometry; his treatise on the subject was in | |
13684 fact a criticism of Euclid, and none too successful at that; | |
13685 some alternative definitions given by him have point, but his | |
13686 alternative solutions of some of the easy problems in Book I | |
13687 do not constitute any improvement, and his attempt to prove | |
13688 the axioms (if one may judge by the case quoted by Proclus, | |
13689 that of Axiom 1) was thoroughly misconceived. | |
13690 <p>Apart from systematic commentaries on the whole work or | |
13691 substantial parts of it, there were already in ancient times | |
13692 discussions and controversies on special subjects dealt with by | |
13693 Euclid, and particularly his theory of parallels. The fifth | |
13694 Postulate was a great stumbling-block. We know from | |
13695 Aristotle that up to his time the theory of parallels had not | |
13696 been put on a scientific basis<note><I>Anal. Prior.</I> ii. 16. 65 a 4.</note>: there was apparently some | |
13697 <I>petitio principii</I> lurking in it. It seems therefore clear that | |
13698 Euclid was the first to apply the bold remedy of laying down | |
13699 the indispensable principle of the theory in the form of an | |
13700 indemonstrable Postulate. But geometers were not satisfied | |
13701 with this solution. Posidonius and Geminus tried to get | |
13702 over the difficulty by substituting an <I>equidistance</I> theory of | |
13703 parallels. Ptolemy actually tried to prove Euclid's postulate, | |
13704 as also did Proclus, and (according to Simplicius) one Diodorus, | |
13705 as well as ‘Aganis’; the attempt of Ptolemy is given by | |
13706 Proclus along with his own, while that of ‘Aganis’ is repro- | |
13707 duced from Simplicius by the Arabian commentator an- | |
13708 Nairīzī. | |
13709 <pb n=359><head>COMMENTARIES, CRITICISMS & REFERENCES</head> | |
13710 <p>Other very early criticisms there were, directed against the | |
13711 very first steps in Euclid's work. Thus Zeno of Sidon, an | |
13712 Epicurean, attacked the proposition I. 1 on the ground that it | |
13713 is not conclusive unless it be first assumed that neither two | |
13714 straight lines nor two circumferences can have a common | |
13715 segment; and this was so far regarded as a serious criticism | |
13716 that Posidonius wrote a whole book to controvert Zeno.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 200. 2.</note> | |
13717 Again, there is the criticism of the Epicureans that I. 20, | |
13718 proving that any two sides in a triangle are together greater | |
13719 than the third, is evident even to an ass and requires no | |
13720 proof. I mention these isolated criticisms to show that the | |
13721 <I>Elements</I>, although they superseded all other Elements and | |
13722 never in ancient times had any rival, were not even at the | |
13723 first accepted without question. | |
13724 <p>The first Latin author to mention Euclid is Cicero; but | |
13725 it is not likely that the <I>Elements</I> had then been translated | |
13726 into Latin. Theoretical geometry did not appeal to the | |
13727 Romans, who only cared for so much of it as was useful for | |
13728 measurements and calculations. Philosophers studied Euclid, | |
13729 but probably in the original Greek; Martianus Capella speaks | |
13730 of the effect of the mention of the proposition ‘how to con- | |
13731 struct an equilateral triangle on a given straight line’ among | |
13732 a company of philosophers, who, recognizing the first pro- | |
13733 position of the <I>Elements</I>, straightway break out into encomiums | |
13734 on Euclid.<note>Mart. Capella, vi. 724.</note> Beyond a fragment in a Verona palimpsest of | |
13735 a free rendering or rearrangement of some propositions from | |
13736 Books XII and XIII dating apparently from the fourth century, | |
13737 we have no trace of any Latin version before Boëtius (born | |
13738 about A.D. 480), to whom Magnus Aurelius Cassiodorus and | |
13739 Theodoric attribute a translation of Euclid. The so-called | |
13740 geometry of Boëtius which has come down to us is by no | |
13741 means a translation of Euclid; but even the redaction of this | |
13742 in two Books which was edited by Friedlein is not genuine, | |
13743 having apparently been put together in the eleventh century | |
13744 from various sources; it contains the definitions of Book I, | |
13745 the Postulates (five in number), the Axioms (three only), then | |
13746 some definitions from Eucl. II, III, IV, followed by the | |
13747 <I>enunciations</I> only (without proofs) of Eucl. I, ten propositions | |
13748 <pb n=360><head>EUCLID</head> | |
13749 of Book II, and a few of Books III and IV, and lastly a | |
13750 passage indicating that the editor will now give something of | |
13751 his own, which turns out to be a literal translation of the | |
13752 proofs of Eucl. I. 1-3. This proves that the Pseudo-Boëtius | |
13753 had a Latin translation of Euclid from which he extracted | |
13754 these proofs; moreover, the text of the definitions from | |
13755 Book I shows traces of perfectly correct readings which are | |
13756 not found even in the Greek manuscripts of the tenth century, | |
13757 but which appear in Proclus and other ancient sources. | |
13758 Fragments of such a Latin translation are also found in | |
13759 the <I>Gromatici veteres.</I><note>Ed. Lachmann, pp. 377 sqq.</note> | |
13760 <C>The text of the Elements.</C> | |
13761 <p>All our Greek texts of the <I>Elements</I> up to a century ago | |
13762 depended upon manuscripts containing Theon's recension of the | |
13763 work; these manuscripts purport, in their titles, to be either | |
13764 ‘from the edition of Theon’ (<G>e)k th=s *qe/wnos e)kdo/sews</G>) or | |
13765 ‘from the lectures of Theon’ (<G>a)po\ sunousiw=n tou= *qe/wnos</G>). | |
13766 Sir Henry Savile in his <I>Praelectiones</I> had drawn attention | |
13767 to the passage in Theon's Commentary on Ptolemy<note>I, p. 201, ed. Halma.</note> quoting | |
13768 the second part of VI. 33 about sectors as having been proved | |
13769 by <I>himself</I> in his edition of the <I>Elements</I>; but it was not | |
13770 till Peyrard discovered in the Vatican the great MS. | |
13771 gr. 190, containing neither the words from the titles of the | |
13772 other manuscripts quoted above nor the addition to VI. 33, | |
13773 that scholars could get back from Theon's text to what thus | |
13774 represents, on the face of it, a more ancient edition than | |
13775 Theon's. It is also clear that the copyist of P (as the manu- | |
13776 script is called after Peyrard), or rather of its archetype, | |
13777 had before him the two recensions and systematically gave | |
13778 the preference to the earlier one; for at XIII. 6 in P the first | |
13779 hand has a marginal note, ‘This theorem is not given in most | |
13780 copies of the <I>new edition</I>, but is found in those of the old’. | |
13781 The <I>editio princeps</I> (Basel, 1533) edited by Simon Grynaeus | |
13782 was based on two manuscripts (Venetus Marcianus 301 and | |
13783 Paris. gr. 2343) of the sixteenth century, which are among | |
13784 the worst. The Basel edition was again the foundation | |
13785 of the text of Gregory (Oxford, 1703), who only consulted the | |
13786 <pb n=361><head>THE TEXT OF THE ELEMENTS</head> | |
13787 manuscripts bequeathed by Savile to the University in | |
13788 places where the Basel text differed from the Latin version | |
13789 of Commandinus which he followed in the main. It was | |
13790 a pity that even Peyrard in his edition (1814-18) only | |
13791 corrected the Basel text by means of P, instead of rejecting | |
13792 it altogether and starting afresh; but he adopted many of the | |
13793 readings of P and gave a conspectus of them in an appendix. | |
13794 E. F. August's edition (1826-9) followed P more closely, and | |
13795 he consulted the Viennese MS. gr. 103 also; but it was | |
13796 left for Heiberg to bring out a new and definitive Greek text | |
13797 (1883-8) based on P and the best of the Theonine manuscripts, | |
13798 and taking account of external sources such as Heron and | |
13799 Proclus. Except in a few passages, Proclus's manuscript does | |
13800 not seem to have been of the best, but authors earlier than | |
13801 Theon, e.g. Heron, generally agree with our best manuscripts. | |
13802 Heiberg concludes that the <I>Elements</I> were most spoiled by | |
13803 interpolations about the third century, since Sextus Empiricus | |
13804 had a correct text, while Iamblicus had an interpolated one. | |
13805 <p>The differences between the inferior Theonine manuscripts | |
13806 and the best sources are perhaps best illustrated by the arrange- | |
13807 ment of postulates and axioms in Book I. Our ordinary | |
13808 editions based on Simson have three postulates and twelve | |
13809 axioms. Of these twelve axioms the eleventh (stating that | |
13810 all right angles are equal) is, in the genuine text, the fourth | |
13811 Postulate, and the twelfth Axiom (the Parallel-Postulate) is | |
13812 the fifth Postulate; the Postulates were thus originally five | |
13813 in number. Of the ten remaining Axioms or Common | |
13814 Notions Heron only recognized the first three, and Proclus | |
13815 only these and two others (that things which coincide are | |
13816 equal, and that the whole is greater than the part); it is fairly | |
13817 certain, therefore, that the rest are interpolated, including the | |
13818 assumption that two straight lines cannot enclose a space | |
13819 (Euclid himself regarded this last fact as involved in Postu- | |
13820 late 1, which implies that a straight line joining one point | |
13821 to another is <I>unique</I>). | |
13822 <C>Latin and Arabic translations.</C> | |
13823 <p>The first Latin translations which we possess in a complete | |
13824 form were made not from the Greek but from the Arabic. | |
13825 It was as early as the eighth century that the <I>Elements</I> found | |
13826 <pb n=362><head>EUCLID</head> | |
13827 their way to Arabia. The Caliph al-Man⋅ūr (754-75), as the | |
13828 result of a mission to the Byzantine Emperor, obtained a copy | |
13829 of Euclid among other Greek books, and the Caliph al-Ma'mūn | |
13830 (813-33) similarly obtained manuscripts of Euclid, among | |
13831 others, from the Byzantines. Al-Hajjāj b. Yūsuf b. Ma⃛ar made | |
13832 two versions of the <I>Elements</I>, the first in the reign of Hārūn | |
13833 ar-Rashīd (786-809), the second for al-Ma)mūn; six Books of | |
13834 the second of these versions survive in a Leyden manuscript | |
13835 (Cod. Leidensis 399. 1) which is being edited along with | |
13836 an-Nairīzī's commentary by Besthorn and Heiberg<note>Parts I, i. 1893, I, ii. 1897, II, i. 1900, II, ii. 1905, III, i. 1910 (Copen- | |
13837 hagen).</note>; this | |
13838 edition was abridged, with corrections and explanations, but | |
13839 without change of substance, from the earlier version, which | |
13840 appears to be lost. The work was next translated by Abū | |
13841 Ya`qūb Is&hdot;āq b. &Hdot;unain b. Is&hdot;āq al-(Ibādī (died 910), evidently | |
13842 direct from the Greek; this translation seems itself to have | |
13843 perished, but we have it as revised by Thābit b. Qurra (died | |
13844 901) in two manuscripts (No. 279 of the year 1238 and No. 280 | |
13845 written in 1260-1) in the Bodleian Library; Books I-XIII in | |
13846 these manuscripts are in the Is&hdot;āq-Thābit version, while the | |
13847 non-Euclidean Books XIV, XV are in the translation of Qus⃛ā | |
13848 b. Lūqā al-Ba`labakkī (died about 912). Is&hdot;āq's version seems | |
13849 to be a model of good translation; the technical terms are | |
13850 simply and consistently rendered, the definitions and enun- | |
13851 ciations differ only in isolated cases from the Greek, and the | |
13852 translator's object seems to have been only to get rid of | |
13853 difficulties and unevennesses in the Greek text while at the | |
13854 same time giving a faithful reproduction of it. The third | |
13855 Arabic version still accessible to us is that of Na⋅īraddīn | |
13856 a⃛-&Tdot;ūsī (born in 1201 at &Tdot;ūs in Khurāsān); this, however, | |
13857 is not a translation of Euclid but a rewritten version based | |
13858 upon the older Arabic translations. On the whole, it appears | |
13859 probable that the Arabic tradition (in spite of its omission | |
13860 of lemmas and porisms, and, except in a very few cases, of | |
13861 the interpolated alternative proofs) is not to be preferred | |
13862 to that of the Greek manuscripts, but must be regarded as | |
13863 inferior in authority. | |
13864 <p>The known Latin translations begin with that of Athelhard, | |
13865 an Englishman, of Bath; the date of it is about 1120. That | |
13866 <pb n=363><head>LATIN AND ARABIC TRANSLATIONS</head> | |
13867 it was made from the Arabic is clear from the occurrence | |
13868 of Arabic words in it; but Athelhard must also have had | |
13869 before him a translation of (at least) the enunciations of | |
13870 Euclid based ultimately upon the Greek text, a translation | |
13871 going back to the old Latin version which was the common | |
13872 source of the passage in the <I>Gromatici</I> and ‘Boëtius’. But | |
13873 it would appear that even before Athelhard's time some sort | |
13874 of translation, or at least fragments of one, were available | |
13875 even in England if one may judge by the Old English verses: | |
13876 ‘The clerk Euclide on this wyse hit fonde<lb> | |
13877 Thys craft of gemetry yn Egypte londe<lb> | |
13878 Yn Egypte he tawghte hyt ful wyde,<lb> | |
13879 In dyvers londe on every syde.<lb> | |
13880 Mony erys afterwarde y understonde<lb> | |
13881 Yer that the craft com ynto thys londe.<lb> | |
13882 Thys craft com into England, as y yow say,<lb> | |
13883 Yn tyme of good Kyng Adelstone's day’,<lb> | |
13884 which would put the introduction of Euclid into England | |
13885 as far back as A.D. 924-40. | |
13886 <p>Next, Gherard of Cremona (1114—87) is said to have | |
13887 translated the ‘15 Books of Euclid’ from the Arabic as he | |
13888 undoubtedly translated an-Nairīzī's commentary on Books | |
13889 I-X; this translation of the <I>Elements</I> was till recently | |
13890 supposed to have been lost, but in 1904 A. A. Björnbo dis- | |
13891 covered in manuscripts at Paris, Boulogne-sur-Mer and Bruges | |
13892 the whole, and at Rome Books X-XV, of a translation which | |
13893 he gives good ground for identifying with Gherard's. This | |
13894 translation has certain Greek words such as <I>rombus, romboides</I>, | |
13895 where Athelhard keeps the Arabic terms; it was thus clearly | |
13896 independent of Athelhard's, though Gherard appears to have | |
13897 had before him, in addition, an old translation of Euclid from | |
13898 the Greek which Athelhard also used. Gherard's translation | |
13899 is much clearer than Athelhard's; it is neither abbreviated | |
13900 nor ‘edited’ in the same way as Athelhard's, but it is a word | |
13901 for word translation of an Arabic manuscript containing a | |
13902 revised and critical edition of Thābit's version. | |
13903 <p>A third translation from the Arabic was that of Johannes | |
13904 Campanus, which came some 150 years after that of Athelhard, | |
13905 That Campanus's translation was not independent of Athel- | |
13906 hard's is proved by the fact that, in all manuscripts and | |
13907 <pb n=364><head>EUCLID</head> | |
13908 editions, the definitions, postulates and axioms, and the 364 | |
13909 enunciations are word for word identical in Athelhard and | |
13910 Campanus. The exact relation between the two seems even | |
13911 yet not to have been sufficiently elucidated. Campanus may | |
13912 have used Athelhard's translation and only developed the | |
13913 proofs by means of another redaction of the Arabian Euclid. | |
13914 Campanus's translation is the clearer and more complete, | |
13915 following the Greek text more closely but still at some | |
13916 distance; the arrangement of the two is different; in Athel- | |
13917 hard the proofs regularly precede the enunciations, while | |
13918 Campanus follows the usual order. How far the differences | |
13919 in the proofs and the additions in each are due to the | |
13920 translators themselves or go back to Arabic originals is a | |
13921 moot question; but it seems most probable that Campanus | |
13922 stood to Athelhard somewhat in the relation of a commen- | |
13923 tator, altering and improving his translation by means of | |
13924 other Arabic originals. | |
13925 <C>The first printed editions.</C> | |
13926 <p>Campanus's translation had the luck to be the first to be | |
13927 put into print. It was published at Venice by Erhard Ratdolt | |
13928 in 1482. This beautiful and very rare book was not only | |
13929 the first printed edition of Euclid, but also the first printed | |
13930 mathematical book of any importance. It has margins of | |
13931 2 1/2 inches and in them are placed the figures of the proposi- | |
13932 tions. Ratdolt says in his dedication that, at that time, | |
13933 although books by ancient and modern authors were being | |
13934 printed every day in Venice, little or nothing mathematical | |
13935 had appeared; this fact he puts down to the difficulty involved | |
13936 by the figures, which no one had up to that time succeeded in | |
13937 printing; he adds that after much labour he had discovered | |
13938 a method by which figures could be produced as easily as | |
13939 letters. Experts do not seem even yet to be agreed as to the | |
13940 actual way in which the figures were made, whether they | |
13941 were woodcuts or whether they were made by putting together | |
13942 lines and circular arcs as letters are put together to make | |
13943 words. How eagerly the opportunity of spreading geometrical | |
13944 knowledge was seized upon is proved by the number of | |
13945 editions which followed in the next few years. Even the | |
13946 <pb n=365><head>THE FIRST PRINTED EDITIONS</head> | |
13947 year 1482 saw two forms of the book, though they only differ | |
13948 in the first sheet. Another edition came out at Ulm in 1486, | |
13949 and another at Vicenza in 1491. | |
13950 <p>In 1501 G. Valla gave in his encyclopaedic work <I>De ex- | |
13951 petendis et fugiendis rebus</I> a number of propositions with | |
13952 proofs and scholia translated from a Greek manuscript which | |
13953 was once in his possession; but Bartolomeo Zamberti (Zam- | |
13954 bertus) was the first to bring out a translation from the | |
13955 Greek text of the whole of the <I>Elements</I>, which appeared | |
13956 at Venice in 1505. The most important Latin translation | |
13957 is, however, that of Commandinus (1509-75), who not only | |
13958 followed the Greek text more closely than his predecessors, | |
13959 but added to his translation some ancient scholia as well | |
13960 as good notes of his own; this translation, which appeared | |
13961 in 1572, was the foundation of most translations up to the | |
13962 time of Peyrard, including that of Simson, and therefore of | |
13963 all those editions, numerous in England, which gave Euclid | |
13964 ‘chiefly after the text of Dr. Simson’. | |
13965 <C>The study of Euclid in the Middle Ages.</C> | |
13966 <p>A word or two about the general position of geometry in | |
13967 education during the Middle Ages will not be out of place in | |
13968 a book for English readers, in view of the unique place which | |
13969 Euclid has till recently held as a text-book in this country. | |
13970 From the seventh to the tenth century the study of geometry | |
13971 languished: ‘We find in the whole literature of that time | |
13972 hardly the slightest sign that any one had gone farther | |
13973 in this department of the Quadrivium than the definitions | |
13974 of a triangle, a square, a circle, or of a pyramid or cone, as | |
13975 Martianus Capella and Isidorus (Hispalensis, died as Bishop | |
13976 of Seville in 636) left them.’<note>Hankel, <I>op. cit.</I>, pp. 311-12.</note> (Isidorus had disposed of the | |
13977 four subjects of Arithmetic, Geometry, Music and Astronomy | |
13978 in <I>four pages</I> of his encyclopaedic work <I>Origines</I> or <I>Ety- | |
13979 mologiae</I>). In the tenth century appeared a ‘reparator | |
13980 studiorum’ in the person of the great Gerbert, who was born | |
13981 at Aurillac, in Auvergne, in the first half of the tenth century, | |
13982 and after a very varied life ultimately (in 999) became Pope | |
13983 Sylvester II; he died in 1003. About 967 he went on | |
13984 <pb n=366><head>EUCLID</head> | |
13985 a journey to Spain, where he studied mathematics. In 970 he | |
13986 went to Rome with Bishop Hatto of Vich (in the province of | |
13987 Barcelona), and was there introduced by Pope John XIII | |
13988 to the German king Otto I. To Otto, who wished to find | |
13989 him a post as a teacher, he could say that ‘he knew enough of | |
13990 mathematics for this, but wished to improve his knowledge | |
13991 of logic’. With Otto's consent he went to Reims, where he | |
13992 became Scholasticus or teacher at the Cathedral School, | |
13993 remaining there for about ten years, 972 to 982. As the result | |
13994 of a mathematico-philosophic argument in public at Ravenna | |
13995 in 980, he was appointed by Otto II to the famous monastery | |
13996 at Bobbio in Lombardy, which, fortunately for him, was rich | |
13997 in valuable manuscripts of all sorts. Here he found the | |
13998 famous ‘Codex Arcerianus’ containing fragments of the | |
13999 works of the <I>Gromatici</I>, Frontinus, Hyginus, Balbus, Nipsus, | |
14000 Epaphroditus and Vitruvius Rufus. Although these frag- | |
14001 ments are not in themselves of great merit, there are things | |
14002 in them which show that the authors drew upon Heron of | |
14003 Alexandria, and Gerbert made the most of them. They | |
14004 formed the basis of his own ‘Geometry’, which may have | |
14005 been written between the years 981 and 983. In writing this | |
14006 book Gerbert evidently had before him Boëtius's <I>Arithmetic</I>, | |
14007 and in the course of it he mentions Pythagoras, Plato's | |
14008 <I>Timaeus</I>, with Chalcidius's commentary thereon, and Eratos- | |
14009 thenes. The geometry in the book is mostly practical; the | |
14010 theoretical part is confined to necessary preliminary matter, | |
14011 definitions, &c., and a few proofs; the fact that the sum of the | |
14012 angles of a triangle is equal to two right angles is proved in | |
14013 Euclid's manner. A great part is taken up with the solution | |
14014 of triangles, and with heights and distances. The Archimedean | |
14015 value of <G>p</G> (22/7) is used in stating the area of a circle; the | |
14016 surface of a sphere is given as 11/21 <I>D</I><SUP>3</SUP>. The plan of the book | |
14017 is quite different from that of Euclid, showing that Gerbert | |
14018 could neither have had Euclid's <I>Elements</I> before him, nor, | |
14019 probably, Boëtius's <I>Geometry</I>, if that work in its genuine | |
14020 form was a version of Euclid. When in a letter written | |
14021 probably from Bobbio in 983 to Adalbero, Archbishop of | |
14022 Reims, he speaks of his expectation of finding ‘eight volumes | |
14023 of Boëtius on astronomy, also the most famous of figures | |
14024 (presumably propositions) in geometry and other things not | |
14025 <pb n=367><head>STUDY OF EUCLID IN THE MIDDLE AGES</head> | |
14026 less admirable’, it is not clear that he actually found these | |
14027 things, and it is still less certain that the geometrical matter | |
14028 referred to was Boëtius's <I>Geometry.</I> | |
14029 <p>From Gerbert's time, again, no further progress was made | |
14030 until translations from the Arabic began with Athelhard and | |
14031 the rest. Gherard of Cremona (died 1187), who translated | |
14032 the <I>Elements</I> and an-Nairīzī's commentary thereon, is credited | |
14033 with a whole series of translations from the Arabic of Greek | |
14034 authors; they included the <I>Data</I> of Euclid, the <I>Sphaerica</I> of | |
14035 Theodosius, the <I>Sphaerica</I> of Menelaus, the <I>Syntaxis</I> of Ptolemy; | |
14036 besides which he translated Arabian geometrical works such | |
14037 as the <I>Liber trium fratrum</I>, and also the algebra of Mu&hdot;ammad | |
14038 b. Mūsā. One of the first results of the interest thus aroused | |
14039 in Greek and Arabian mathematics was seen in the very | |
14040 remarkable works of Leonardo of Pisa (Fibonacci). Leonardo | |
14041 first published in 1202, and then brought out later (1228) an | |
14042 improved edition of, his <I>Liber abaci</I> in which he gave the | |
14043 whole of arithmetic and algebra as known to the Arabs, but | |
14044 in a free and independent style of his own; in like manner in | |
14045 his <I>Practica geometriae</I> of 1220 he collected (1) all that the | |
14046 <I>Elements</I> of Euclid and Archimedes's books on the <I>Measure- | |
14047 ment of a Circle</I> and <I>On the Sphere and Cylinder</I> had taught | |
14048 him about the measurement of plane figures bounded by | |
14049 straight lines, solid figures bounded by planes, the circle and | |
14050 the sphere respectively, (2) divisions of figures in different | |
14051 proportions, wherein he based himself on Euclid's book <I>On the | |
14052 divisions of figures</I>, but carried the subject further, (3) some | |
14053 trigonometry, which he got from Ptolemy and Arabic sources | |
14054 (he uses the terms <I>sinus rectus</I> and <I>sinus versus</I>); in the | |
14055 treatment of these varied subjects he showed the same mastery | |
14056 and, in places, distinct originality. We should have expected | |
14057 a great general advance in the next centuries after such a | |
14058 beginning, but, as Hankel says, when we look at the work of | |
14059 Luca Paciuolo nearly three centuries later, we find that the | |
14060 talent which Leonardo had left to the Latin world had lain | |
14061 hidden in a napkin and earned no interest. As regards the | |
14062 place of geometry in education during this period we have | |
14063 the evidence of Roger Bacon (1214-94), though he, it | |
14064 is true, seems to have taken an exaggerated view of the | |
14065 incompetence of the mathematicians and teachers of his | |
14066 <pb n=368><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14067 time; the philosophers of his day, he says, despised geo- | |
14068 metry, languages, &c., declaring that they were useless; | |
14069 people in general, not finding utility in any science such as | |
14070 geometry, at once recoiled, unless they were boys forced to | |
14071 it by the rod, from the idea of studying it, so that they | |
14072 would hardly learn as much as three or four propositions; | |
14073 the fifth proposition of Euclid was called <I>Elefuga</I> or <I>fuga | |
14074 miserorum.</I><note>Roger Bacon, <I>Opus Tertium</I>, cc. iv, vi.</note> | |
14075 <p>As regards Euclid at the Universities, it may be noted that | |
14076 the study of geometry seems to have been neglected at the | |
14077 University of Paris. At the reformation of the University in | |
14078 1336 it was only provided that no one should take a Licentiate | |
14079 who had not attended lectures on some mathematical books; | |
14080 the same requirement reappears in 1452 and 1600. From the | |
14081 preface to a commentary on Euclid which appeared in 1536 | |
14082 we learn that a candidate for the degree of M.A. had to take | |
14083 a solemn oath that he had attended lectures on the first six | |
14084 Books; but it is doubtful whether for the examinations more | |
14085 than Book I was necessary, seeing that the proposition I. 47 | |
14086 was known as <I>Magister matheseos.</I> At the University of | |
14087 Prague (founded in 1348) mathematics were more regarded. | |
14088 Candidates for the Baccalaureate had to attend lectures on | |
14089 the <I>Tractatus de Sphaera materiali</I>, a treatise on the funda- | |
14090 mental ideas of spherical astronomy, mathematical geography | |
14091 and the ordinary astronomical phenomena, but without the | |
14092 help of mathematical propositions, written by Johannes de | |
14093 Sacrobosco (i. e. of Holywood, in Yorkshire) in 1250, a book | |
14094 which was read at all Universities for four centuries and | |
14095 many times commented upon; for the Master's degree lectures | |
14096 on the first six Books of Euclid were compulsory. Euclid | |
14097 was lectured upon at the Universities of Vienna (founded 1365), | |
14098 Heidelberg (1386), Cologne (1388); at Heidelberg an oath was | |
14099 required from the candidate for the Licentiate corresponding | |
14100 to M.A. that he had attended lectures on some whole books and | |
14101 not merely parts of several books (not necessarily, it appears, | |
14102 of Euclid); at Vienna, the first five Books of Euclid were | |
14103 required; at Cologne, no mathematics were required for the | |
14104 Baccalaureate, but the candidate for M.A. must have attended | |
14105 <pb n=369><head>STUDY OF EUCLID IN THE MIDDLE AGES</head> | |
14106 lectures on the <I>Sphaera mundi</I>, planetary theory, three Books | |
14107 of Euclid, optics and arithmetic. At Leipzig (founded 1409), | |
14108 as at Vienna and Prague, there were lectures on Euclid for | |
14109 some time at all events, though Hankel says that he found no | |
14110 mention of Euclid in a list of lectures given in the consecutive | |
14111 years 1437-8, and Regiomontanus, when he went to Leipzig, | |
14112 found no fellow-students in geometry. At Oxford, in the | |
14113 middle of the fifteenth century, the first two Books of Euclid | |
14114 were read, and doubtless the Cambridge course was similar. | |
14115 <C>The first English editions.</C> | |
14116 <p>After the issue of the first printed editions of Euclid, | |
14117 beginning with the translation of Campano, published by | |
14118 Ratdolt, and of the <I>editio princeps</I> of the Greek text (1533), | |
14119 the study of Euclid received a great impetus, as is shown | |
14120 by the number of separate editions and commentaries which | |
14121 appeared in the sixteenth century. The first complete English | |
14122 translation by Sir Henry Billingsley (1570) was a monumental | |
14123 work of 928 pages of folio size, with a preface by John Dee, | |
14124 and notes extracted from all the most important commentaries | |
14125 from Proclus down to Dee himself, a magnificent tribute to | |
14126 the immortal Euclid. About the same time Sir Henry Savile | |
14127 began to give <I>unpaid</I> lectures on the Greek geometers; those | |
14128 on Euclid do not indeed extend beyond I. 8, but they are | |
14129 valuable because they deal with the difficulties connected with | |
14130 the preliminary matter, the definitions, &c., and the tacit | |
14131 assumptions contained in the first propositions. But it was | |
14132 in the period from about 1660 to 1730, during which Wallis | |
14133 and Halley were Professors at Oxford, and Barrow and | |
14134 Newton at Cambridge, that the study of Greek mathematics | |
14135 was at its height in England. As regards Euclid in particular | |
14136 Barrow's influence was doubtless very great. His Latin | |
14137 version (<I>Euclidis Elementorum Libri XV breviter demon- | |
14138 strati</I>) came out in 1655, and there were several more editions | |
14139 of the same published up to 1732; his first English edition | |
14140 appeared in 1660, and was followed by others in 1705, 1722, | |
14141 1732, 1751. This brings us to Simson's edition, first published | |
14142 both in Latin and English in 1756. It is presumably from | |
14143 this time onwards that Euclid acquired the unique status as | |
14144 <pb n=370><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14145 a text-book which it maintained till recently. I cannot help | |
14146 thinking that it was Barrow's influence which contributed | |
14147 most powerfully to this. We are told that Newton, when | |
14148 he first bought a Euclid in 1662 or 1663, thought it ‘a trifling | |
14149 book’, as the propositions seemed to him obvious; after- | |
14150 wards, however, on Barrow's advice, he studied the <I>Elements</I> | |
14151 carefully and derived, as he himself stated, much benefit | |
14152 therefrom. | |
14153 <C>Technical terms connected with the classical form | |
14154 of a proposition.</C> | |
14155 <p>As the classical form of a proposition in geometry is that | |
14156 which we find in Euclid, though it did not originate with | |
14157 him, it is desirable, before we proceed to an analysis of the | |
14158 <I>Elements</I>, to give some account of the technical terms used by | |
14159 the Greeks in connexion with such propositions and their | |
14160 proofs. We will take first the terms employed to describe the | |
14161 formal divisions of a proposition. | |
14162 <C>(<G>a</G>) <I>Terms for the formal divisions of a proposition.</I></C> | |
14163 <p>In its completest form a proposition contained six parts, | |
14164 (1) the <G>pro/tasis</G>, or <I>enunciation</I> in general terms, (2) the | |
14165 <G>e)/kqesis</G>, or <I>setting-out</I>, which states the particular <I>data</I>, e.g. | |
14166 a given straight line <I>AB</I>, two given triangles <I>ABC, DEF</I>, and | |
14167 the like, generally shown in a figure and constituting that | |
14168 upon which the proposition is to operate, (3) the <G>diorismo/s</G>, | |
14169 <I>definition</I> or <I>specification</I>, which means the restatement of | |
14170 what it is required to do or to prove in terms of the particular | |
14171 data, the object being to fix our ideas, (4) the <G>kataskeuh/</G>, the | |
14172 <I>construction</I> or <I>machinery</I> used, which includes any additions | |
14173 to the original figure by way of construction that are necessary | |
14174 to enable the proof to proceed, (5) the <G>a)po/deixis</G>, or the <I>proof</I> | |
14175 itself, and (6) the <G>sumpe/rasma</G>, or <I>conclusion</I>, which reverts to | |
14176 the enunciation, and states what has been proved or done; | |
14177 the conclusion can, of course, be stated in as general terms | |
14178 as the enunciation, since it does not depend on the particular | |
14179 figure drawn; that figure is only an illustration, a type of the | |
14180 <I>class</I> of figure, and it is legitimate therefore, in stating | |
14181 the conclusion, to pass from the particular to the general. | |
14182 <pb n=371><head>FORMAL DIVISIONS OF A PROPOSITION</head> | |
14183 In particular cases some of these formal divisions may be | |
14184 absent, but three are always found, the <I>enunciation, proof</I> | |
14185 and <I>conclusion.</I> Thus in many propositions no construction | |
14186 is needed, the given figure itself sufficing for the proof; | |
14187 again, in IV. 10 (to construct an isosceles triangle with each | |
14188 of the base angles double of the vertical angle) we may, in | |
14189 a sense, say with Proclus<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 203. 23 sq.</note> that there is neither <I>setting-out</I> nor | |
14190 <I>definition</I>, for there is nothing <I>given</I> in the enunciation, and | |
14191 we set out, not a given straight line, but any straight line <I>AB</I>, | |
14192 while the proposition does not state (what might be said by | |
14193 way of <I>definition</I>) that the required triangle is to have <I>AB</I> for | |
14194 one of its equal sides. | |
14195 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>The</I> <G>diorismo/s</G> <I>or statement of conditions of possibility.</I></C> | |
14196 <p>Sometimes to the statement of a problem there has to be | |
14197 added a <G>diorismo/s</G> in the more important and familiar sense of | |
14198 a criterion of the conditions of possibility or, in its most | |
14199 complete form, a criterion as to ‘whether what is sought | |
14200 is impossible or possible and how far it is practicable and in | |
14201 how many ways’.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 202. 3.</note> Both kinds of <G>diorismo/s</G> begin with the | |
14202 words <G>dei= dh/</G>, which should be translated, in the case of the | |
14203 <I>definition</I>, ‘thus it is required (to prove or do so and so)’ and, | |
14204 in the case of the criterion of possibility, ‘thus it is necessary | |
14205 that ...’ (not ‘<I>but</I> it is necessary ...’). Cf. I. 22, ‘Out of | |
14206 three straight lines which are equal to three given straight | |
14207 lines to construct a triangle: thus it is necessary that two | |
14208 of the straight lines taken together in any manner should be | |
14209 greater than the remaining straight line’. | |
14210 <C>(<G>g</G>) <I>Analysis, synthesis, reduction, reductio ad absurdum.</I></C> | |
14211 <p>The <I>Elements</I> is a synthetic treatise in that it goes directly | |
14212 forward the whole way, always proceeding from the known | |
14213 to the unknown, from the simple and particular to the more | |
14214 complex and general; hence <I>analysis</I>, which reduces the | |
14215 unknown or the more complex to the known, has no place | |
14216 in the exposition, though it would play an important part in | |
14217 the discovery of the proofs. A full account of the Greek | |
14218 <I>analysis</I> and <I>synthesis</I> will come more conveniently elsewhere. | |
14219 <pb n=372><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14220 In the meantime we may observe that, where a proposition | |
14221 is worked out by analysis followed by synthesis, the analysis | |
14222 comes between the <I>definition</I> and the <I>construction</I> of the | |
14223 proposition; and it should not be forgotten that <I>reductio ad | |
14224 absurdum</I> (called in Greek <G>h( ei)s to\ a)du/naton a)pagwgh/</G>, | |
14225 ‘reduction to the impossible’, or <G>h( dia\ to|u= a)duna/tou dei=xis</G> | |
14226 or <G>a)po/deixis</G>, ‘proof <I>per impossibile</I>’), a method of proof | |
14227 common in Euclid as elsewhere, is a variety of analysis. | |
14228 For analysis begins with <I>reduction</I> (<G>a)pagwgh/</G>) of the original | |
14229 proposition, which we hypothetically assume to be true, to | |
14230 something simpler which we can recognize as being either | |
14231 true or false; the case where it leads to a conclusion known | |
14232 to be false is the <I>reductio ad absurdum.</I> | |
14233 <C>(<G>d</G>) <I>Case, objection, porism, lemma.</I></C> | |
14234 <p>Other terms connected with propositions are the following. | |
14235 A proposition may have several <I>cases</I> according to the different | |
14236 arrangements of points, lines, &c., in the figure that may | |
14237 result from variations in the positions of the elements given; | |
14238 the word for <I>case</I> is <G>ptw=sis</G>. The practice of the great | |
14239 geometers was, as a rule, to give only one case, leaving the | |
14240 others for commentators or pupils to supply for themselves. | |
14241 But they were fully alive to the existence of such other | |
14242 cases; sometimes, if we may believe Proclus, they would even | |
14243 give a proposition solely with a view to its use for the purpose | |
14244 of proving a case of a later proposition which is actually | |
14245 omitted. Thus, according to Proclus,<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, pp. 248. 8-11; 263. 4-8.</note> the second part of I. 5 | |
14246 (about the angles beyond the base) was intended to enable | |
14247 the reader to meet an <I>objection</I> (<G>e)/nstasis</G>) that might be | |
14248 raised to I. 7 as given by Euclid on the ground that it was | |
14249 incomplete, since it took no account of what was given by | |
14250 Proclus himself, and is now generally given in our text-books, | |
14251 as the second case. | |
14252 <p>What we call a <I>corollary</I> was for the Greeks a <I>porism</I> | |
14253 (<G>po/risma</G>), i. e. something provided or ready-made, by which | |
14254 was meant some result incidentally revealed in the course | |
14255 of the demonstration of the main proposition under discussion, | |
14256 a sort of incidental gain' arising out of the demonstration, | |
14257 <pb n=373><head>TECHNICAL TERMS</head> | |
14258 as Proclus says.<note><I>Ib.</I>, p. 212. 16.</note> The name <I>porism</I> was also applied to a | |
14259 special kind of substantive proposition, as in Euclid's separate | |
14260 work in three Books entitled <I>Porisms</I> (see below, pp. 431-8). | |
14261 <p>The word <I>lemma</I> (<G>lh=mma</G>) simply means something <I>assumed.</I> | |
14262 Archimedes uses it of what is now known as the Axiom of | |
14263 Archimedes, the principle assumed by Eudoxus and others in | |
14264 the method of exhaustion; but it is more commonly used | |
14265 of a subsidiary proposition requiring proof, which, however, | |
14266 it is convenient to assume in the place where it is wanted | |
14267 in order that the argument may not be interrupted or unduly | |
14268 lengthened. Such a lemma might be proved in advance, but | |
14269 the proof was often postponed till the end, the assumption | |
14270 being marked as something to be afterwards proved by some | |
14271 such words as <G>w(s e(xh=s deixqh/setai</G>, ‘as will be proved in due | |
14272 course’. | |
14273 <C>Analysis of the <I>Elements.</I></C> | |
14274 <p>Book I of the <I>Elements</I> necessarily begins with the essential | |
14275 preliminary matter classified under the headings <I>Definitions</I> | |
14276 (<G>o(/roi</G>), <I>Postulates</I> (<G>ai)th/mata</G>) and <I>Common Notions</I> (<G>koinai\ | |
14277 e)/nnoiai</G>). In calling the axioms <I>Common Notions</I> Euclid | |
14278 followed the lead of Aristotle, who uses as alternatives for | |
14279 ‘axioms’ the terms ‘common (things)’, ‘common opinions’. | |
14280 <p>Many of the <I>Definitions</I> are open to criticism on one ground | |
14281 or another. Two of them at least seem to be original, namely, | |
14282 the definitions of a straight line (4) and of a plane surface (7); | |
14283 unsatisfactory as these are, they seem to be capable of a | |
14284 simple explanation. The definition of a straight line is | |
14285 apparently an attempt to express, without any appeal to | |
14286 sight, the sense of Plato's definition ‘that of which the middle | |
14287 covers the ends’ (<I>sc.</I> to an eye placed at one end and looking | |
14288 along it); and the definition of a plane surface is an adaptation | |
14289 of the same definition. But most of the definitions were | |
14290 probably adopted from earlier text-books; some appear to be | |
14291 inserted merely out of respect for tradition, e.g. the defini- | |
14292 tions of <I>oblong, rhombus, rhomboid</I>, which are never used | |
14293 in the <I>Elements.</I> The definitions of various figures assume | |
14294 the existence of the thing defined, e.g. the square, and the | |
14295 <pb n=374><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14296 different kinds of triangle under their twofold classification | |
14297 (<I>a</I>) with reference to their sides (equilateral, isosceles and | |
14298 scalene), and (<I>b</I>) with reference to their angles (right-angled, | |
14299 obtuse-angled and acute-angled); such definitions are pro- | |
14300 visional pending the proof of existence by means of actual con- | |
14301 struction. A <I>parallelogram</I> is not defined; its existence is | |
14302 first proved in I. 33, and in the next proposition it is called a | |
14303 ‘parallelogrammic area’, meaning an area contained by parallel | |
14304 lines, in preparation for the use of the simple word ‘parallelo- | |
14305 gram’ from I. 35 onwards. The definition of a diameter | |
14306 of a circle (17) includes a theorem; for Euclid adds that ‘such | |
14307 a straight line also bisects the circle’, which is one of the | |
14308 theorems attributed to Thales; but this addition was really | |
14309 necessary in view of the next definition (18), for, without | |
14310 this explanation, Euclid would not have been justified in | |
14311 describing a <I>semi</I>-circle as a portion of a circle cut off by | |
14312 a diameter. | |
14313 <p>More important by far are the five Postulates, for it is in | |
14314 them that Euclid lays down the real principles of Euclidean | |
14315 geometry; and nothing shows more clearly his determination | |
14316 to reduce his original assumptions to the very minimum. | |
14317 The first three Postulates are commonly regarded as the | |
14318 postulates of <I>construction</I>, since they assert the possibility | |
14319 (1) of drawing the straight line joining two points, (2) of | |
14320 producing a straight line in either direction, and (3) of describ- | |
14321 ing a circle with a given centre and ‘distance’. But they | |
14322 imply much more than this. In Postulates 1 and 3 Euclid | |
14323 postulates the existence of straight lines and. circles, and | |
14324 implicitly answers the objections of those who might say that, | |
14325 as a matter of fact, the straight lines and circles which we | |
14326 can draw are not mathematical straight lines and circles; | |
14327 Euclid may be supposed to assert that we can nevertheless | |
14328 assume our straight lines and circles to be such for the purpose | |
14329 of our proofs, since they are only illustrations enabling us to | |
14330 <I>imagine</I> the real things which they imperfectly represent. | |
14331 But, again, Postulates 1 and 2 further imply that the straight | |
14332 line drawn in the first case and the produced portion of the | |
14333 straight line in the second case are <I>unique</I>; in other words, | |
14334 Postulate 1 implies that two straight lines cannot enclose a | |
14335 space, and so renders unnecessary the ‘axiom’ to that effect | |
14336 <pb n=375><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK I</head> | |
14337 interpolated in Proposition 4, while Postulate 2 similarly im- | |
14338 plies the theorem that two straight lines cannot have a | |
14339 common segment, which Simson gave as a corollary to I. 11. | |
14340 <p>At first sight the Postulates 4 (that all right angles are | |
14341 equal) and 5 (the Parallel-Postulate) might seem to be of | |
14342 an altogether different character, since they are rather of the | |
14343 nature of theorems unproved. But Postulate 5 is easily seen | |
14344 to be connected with constructions, because so many con- | |
14345 structions depend on the existence and use of points in which | |
14346 straight lines intersect; it is therefore absolutely necessary to | |
14347 lay down some criterion by which we can judge whether two | |
14348 straight lines in a figure will or will not meet if produced. | |
14349 Postulate 5 serves this purpose as well as that of providing | |
14350 a basis for the theory of parallel lines. Strictly speaking, | |
14351 Euclid ought to have gone further and given criteria for | |
14352 judging whether other pairs of lines, e.g. a straight line and | |
14353 a circle, or two circles, in a particular figure will or will not | |
14354 intersect one another. But this would have necessitated a | |
14355 considerable series of propositions, which it would have been | |
14356 difficult to frame at so early a stage, and Euclid preferred | |
14357 to assume such intersections provisionally in certain cases, | |
14358 e.g. in I. 1. | |
14359 <p>Postulate 4 is often classed as a theorem. But it had in any | |
14360 case to be placed before Postulate 5 for the simple reason that | |
14361 Postulate 5 would be no criterion at all unless right angles | |
14362 were determinate magnitudes; Postulate 4 then declares them | |
14363 to be such. But this is not all. If Postulate 4 were to be | |
14364 proved as a theorem, it could only be proved by applying one | |
14365 pair of ‘adjacent’ right angles to another pair. This method | |
14366 would not be valid unless on the assumption of the <I>invaria- | |
14367 bility of figures</I>, which would therefore have to be asserted as | |
14368 an antecedent postulate. Euclid preferred to assert as a | |
14369 postulate, directly, the fact that all right angles are equal; | |
14370 hence his postulate may be taken as equivalent to the prin- | |
14371 ciple of the <I>invariability of figures</I>, or, what is the same thing, | |
14372 the <I>homogeneity of space.</I> | |
14373 <p>For reasons which I have given above (pp. 339, 358), I think | |
14374 that the great Postulate 5 is due to Euclid himself; and it | |
14375 seems probable that Postulate 4 is also his, if not Postulates | |
14376 1-3 as well. | |
14377 <pb n=376><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14378 <p>Of the <I>Common Notions</I> there is good reason to believe | |
14379 that only five (at the most) are genuine, the first three and | |
14380 two others, namely ‘Things which coincide when applied to | |
14381 one another are equal to one another’ (4), and ‘The whole | |
14382 is greater than the part’ (5). The objection to (4) is that | |
14383 it is incontestably geometrical, and therefore, on Aristotle's | |
14384 principles, should not be classed as an ‘axiom’; it is a more | |
14385 or less sufficient definition of geometrical equality, but not | |
14386 a real axiom. Euclid evidently disliked the method of super- | |
14387 position for proving equality, no doubt because it assumes the | |
14388 possibility of motion <I>without deformation.</I> But he could not | |
14389 dispense with it altogether. Thus in I. 4 he practically had | |
14390 to choose between using the method and assuming the whole | |
14391 proposition as a postulate. But he does not there quote | |
14392 <I>Common Notion</I> 4; he says ‘the base <I>BC</I> will coincide with | |
14393 the base <I>EF</I> and will be equal to it’. Similarly in I. 6 he | |
14394 does not quote <I>Common Notion</I> 5, but says ‘the triangle | |
14395 <I>DBC</I> will be equal to the triangle <I>ACB</I>, the less to the greater, | |
14396 which is absurd’. It seems probable, therefore, that even | |
14397 these two <I>Common Notions</I>, though apparently recognized | |
14398 by Proclus, were generalizations from particular inferences | |
14399 found in Euclid and were inserted after his time. | |
14400 <p>The propositions of Book I fall into three distinct groups. | |
14401 The first group consists of Propositions 1-26, dealing mainly | |
14402 with triangles (without the use of parallels) but also with | |
14403 perpendiculars (11, 12), two intersecting straight lines (15), | |
14404 and one straight line standing on another but not cutting it, | |
14405 and making ‘adjacent’ or supplementary angles (13, 14). | |
14406 Proposition 1 gives the construction of an equilateral triangle | |
14407 on a given straight line as base; this is placed here not so | |
14408 much on its own account as because it is at once required for | |
14409 constructions (in 2, 9, 10, 11). The construction in 2 is a | |
14410 direct continuation of the minimum constructions assumed | |
14411 in Postulates 1-3, and enables us (as the Postulates do not) to | |
14412 transfer a given length of straight line from one place to | |
14413 another; it leads in 3 to the operation so often required of | |
14414 cutting off from one given straight line a length equal to | |
14415 another. 9 and 10 are the problems of bisecting a given angle | |
14416 and a given straight line respectively, and 11 shows how | |
14417 to erect a perpendicular to a given straight line from a given | |
14418 <pb n=377><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK I</head> | |
14419 point on it. Construction as a means of proving existence is | |
14420 in evidence in the Book, not only in 1 (the equilateral triangle) | |
14421 but in 11, 12 (perpendiculars erected and let fall), and in | |
14422 22 (construction of a triangle in the general case where the | |
14423 lengths of the sides are given); 23 constructs, by means of 22, | |
14424 an angle equal to a given rectilineal angle. The propositions | |
14425 about triangles include the congruence-theorems (4, 8, 26)— | |
14426 omitting the ‘ambiguous case’ which is only taken into | |
14427 account in the analogous proposition (7) of Book VI—and the | |
14428 theorems (allied to 4) about two triangles in which two sides | |
14429 of the one are respectively equal to two sides of the other, but | |
14430 of the included angles (24) or of the bases (25) one is greater | |
14431 than the other, and it is proved that the triangle in which the | |
14432 included angle is greater has the greater base and vice versa. | |
14433 Proposition 7, used to prove Proposition 8, is also important as | |
14434 being the Book I equivalent of III. 10 (that two circles cannot | |
14435 intersect in more points than two). Then we have theorems | |
14436 about single triangles in 5, 6 (isosceles triangles have the | |
14437 angles opposite to the equal sides equal—Thales's theorem— | |
14438 and the converse), the important propositions 16 (the exterior | |
14439 angle of a triangle is greater than either of the interior and | |
14440 opposite angles) and its derivative 17 (any two angles of | |
14441 a triangle are together less than two right angles), 18, 19 | |
14442 (greater angle subtended by greater side and vice versa), | |
14443 20 (any two sides together greater than the third). This last | |
14444 furnishes the necessary <G>diorismo/s</G>, or criterion of possibility, of | |
14445 the problem in 22 of constructing a triangle out of three | |
14446 straight lines of given length, which problem had therefore | |
14447 to come after and not before 20. 21 (proving that the two | |
14448 sides of a triangle other than the base are together greater, | |
14449 but include a lesser angle, than the two sides of any other | |
14450 triangle on the same base but with vertex within the original | |
14451 triangle) is useful for the proof of the proposition (not stated | |
14452 in Euclid) that of all straight lines drawn from an external | |
14453 point to a given straight line the perpendicular is the | |
14454 shortest, and the nearer to the perpendicular is less than the | |
14455 more remote. | |
14456 <p>The second group (27-32) includes the theory of parallels | |
14457 (27-31, ending with the construction through a given point | |
14458 of a parallel to a given straight line); and then, in 32, Euclid | |
14459 <pb n=378><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14460 proves that the sum of the three angles of a triangle is equal | |
14461 to two right angles by means of a parallel to one side drawn | |
14462 from the opposite vertex (cf. the slightly different Pytha- | |
14463 gorean proof, p. 143). | |
14464 <p>The third group of propositions (33-48) deals generally | |
14465 with parallelograms, triangles and squares with reference to | |
14466 their areas. 33, 34 amount to the proof of the existence and | |
14467 the property of a parallelogram, and then we are introduced | |
14468 to a new conception, that of <I>equivalent</I> figures, or figures | |
14469 equal in area though not equal in the sense of congruent: | |
14470 parallelograms on the same base or on equal bases and between | |
14471 the same parallels are equal in area (35, 36); the same is true | |
14472 of triangles (37, 38), and a parallelogram on the same (or an | |
14473 equal) base with a triangle and between the same parallels is | |
14474 double of the triangle (41). 39 and the interpolated 40 are | |
14475 partial converses of 37 and 38. The theorem 41 enables us | |
14476 ‘to construct in a given rectilineal angle a parallelogram | |
14477 equal to a given triangle’ (42). Propositions 44, 45 are of | |
14478 the greatest importance, being the first cases of the Pytha- | |
14479 gorean method of ‘application of areas’, ‘to apply to a given | |
14480 straight line, in a given rectilineal angle, a parallelogram | |
14481 equal to a given triangle (or rectilineal figure)’. The con- | |
14482 struction in 44 is remarkably ingenious, being based on that | |
14483 of 42 combined with the proposition (43) proving that the | |
14484 ‘complements of the parallelograms about the diameter’ in any | |
14485 parallelogram are equal. We are thus enabled to transform | |
14486 a parallelogram of any shape into another with the same | |
14487 angle and of equal area but with one side of any given length, | |
14488 say a <I>unit</I> length; this is the geometrical equivalent of the | |
14489 algebraic operation of dividing the product of two quantities | |
14490 by a third. Proposition 46 constructs a square on any given | |
14491 straight line as side, and is followed by the great Pythagorean | |
14492 theorem of the square on the hypotenuse of a right-angled | |
14493 triangle (47) and its converse (48). The remarkably clever | |
14494 proof of 47 by means of the well-known ‘windmill’ figure | |
14495 and the application to it of I. 41 combined with I. 4 seems to | |
14496 be due to Euclid himself; it is really equivalent to a proof by | |
14497 the methods of Book VI (Propositions 8, 17), and Euclid's | |
14498 achievement was that of avoiding the use of proportions and | |
14499 making the proof dependent upon Book I only. | |
14500 <pb n=379><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOKS I-II</head> | |
14501 <p>I make no apology for having dealt at some length with | |
14502 Book I and, in particular, with the preliminary matter, in | |
14503 view of the unique position and authority of the <I>Elements</I> | |
14504 as an exposition of the fundamental principles of Greek | |
14505 geometry, and the necessity for the historian of mathematics | |
14506 of a clear understanding of their nature and full import. | |
14507 It will now be possible to deal more summarily with the | |
14508 other Books. | |
14509 <p>Book II is a continuation of the third section of Book I, | |
14510 relating to the transformation of areas, but is specialized in | |
14511 that it deals, not with parallelograms in general, but with | |
14512 <I>rectangles</I> and squares, and makes great use of the figure | |
14513 called the <I>gnomon.</I> The <I>rectangle</I> is introduced (Def. 1) as | |
14514 a ‘rectangular parallelogram’, which is said to be ‘contained | |
14515 by the two straight lines containing the right angle’. The | |
14516 <I>gnomon</I> is defined (Def. 2) with reference to any parallelo- | |
14517 gram, but the only gnomon actually used is naturally that | |
14518 which belongs to a square. The whole Book constitutes an | |
14519 essential part of the <I>geometrical algebra</I> which really, in | |
14520 Greek geometry, took the place of our algebra. The first ten | |
14521 propositions give the equivalent of the following algebraical | |
14522 identities. | |
14523 <p>1. <MATH><I>a</I>(<I>b</I>+<I>c</I>+<I>d</I>+...)=<I>ab</I>+<I>ac</I>+<I>ad</I>+...</MATH>, | |
14524 <p>2. <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<I>a</I>+(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<I>b</I>=(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14525 <p>3. <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<I>a</I>=<I>ab</I>+<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14526 <p>4. <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>=<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>+2<I>ab</I></MATH>, | |
14527 <p>5. <MATH><I>ab</I>+{1/2(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)-<I>b</I>}<SUP>2</SUP>={1/2(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)}<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14528 or <MATH>(<G>a</G>+<G>b</G>)(<G>a</G>-<G>b</G>)+<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP>=<G>a</G><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14529 <p>6. <MATH>(2<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<I>b</I>+<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14530 or <MATH>(<G>a</G>+<G>b</G>)(<G>b</G>-<G>a</G>)+<G>a</G><SUP>2</SUP>=<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14531 <p>7. <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>+<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>=2(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<I>a</I>+<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14532 or <MATH><G>a</G><SUP>2</SUP>+<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP>=2<G>ab</G>+(<G>a</G>-<G>b</G>)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14533 <p>8. <MATH>4(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<I>a</I>+<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>={(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)+<I>a</I>}<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14534 or <MATH>4<G>ab</G>+(<G>a</G>-<G>b</G>)<SUP>2</SUP>=(<G>a</G>+<G>b</G>)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
14535 <pb n=380><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14536 <p>9. <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>=2[{1/2(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)}<SUP>2</SUP>+{1/2(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)-<I>b</I>}<SUP>2</SUP>]</MATH>, | |
14537 or <MATH>(<G>a</G>+<G>b</G>)<SUP>2</SUP>+(<G>a</G>-<G>b</G>)<SUP>2</SUP>=2(<G>a</G><SUP>2</SUP>+<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>, | |
14538 <p>10. <MATH>(2<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>+<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>=2{<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>)<SUP>2</SUP>}</MATH>, | |
14539 or <MATH>(<G>a</G>+<G>b</G>)<SUP>2</SUP>+(<G>b</G>-<G>a</G>)<SUP>2</SUP>=2(<G>a</G><SUP>2</SUP>+<G>b</G><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>. | |
14540 As we have seen (pp. 151-3), Propositions 5 and 6 enable us | |
14541 to solve the quadratic equations | |
14542 <MATH> | |
14543 (1) <I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> or | |
14544 <BRACE><I>x</I>+<I>y</I>=<I>a</I> | |
14545 <I>xy</I>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> | |
14546 </BRACE>, | |
14547 and (2) <I>ax</I>+<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> or | |
14548 <BRACE> | |
14549 <I>y</I>-<I>x</I>=<I>a</I> | |
14550 <I>xy</I>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP> | |
14551 </BRACE>. | |
14552 </MATH> | |
14553 The procedure is <I>geometrical</I> throughout; the areas in all | |
14554 the Propositions 1-8 are actually shown in the figures. | |
14555 Propositions 9 and 10 were really intended to solve a problem | |
14556 in <I>numbers</I>, that of finding any number of successive pairs | |
14557 of integral numbers (‘side-’ and ‘diameter-’ numbers) satisfy- | |
14558 ing the equations | |
14559 <MATH>2<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>=±1</MATH> | |
14560 (see p. 93, above). | |
14561 <p>Of the remaining propositions, II. 11 and II. 14 give the | |
14562 geometrical equivalent of solving the quadratic equations | |
14563 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>ax</I>=<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> | |
14564 and <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>ab</I></MATH>, | |
14565 while the intervening propositions 12 and 13 prove, for any | |
14566 triangle with sides <I>a, b, c</I>, the equivalent of the formula | |
14567 <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>bc</I> cos <I>A.</I></MATH> | |
14568 <p>It is worth noting that, while I. 47 and its converse con- | |
14569 clude Book I as if that Book was designed to lead up to the | |
14570 great proposition of Pythagoras, the last propositions but one | |
14571 of Book II give the generalization of the same proposition | |
14572 with <I>any</I> triangle substituted for a right-angled triangle. | |
14573 <p>The subject of Book III is the geometry of the circle, | |
14574 including the relations between circles cutting or touching | |
14575 each other. It begins with some definitions, which are | |
14576 <pb n=381><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOKS II-III</head> | |
14577 generally of the same sort as those of Book I. Definition 1, | |
14578 stating that <I>equal circles</I> are those which have their diameters | |
14579 or their radii equal, might alternatively be regarded as a | |
14580 postulate or a theorem; if stated as a theorem, it could only | |
14581 be proved by superposition and the congruence-axiom. It is | |
14582 curious that the Greeks had no single word for <I>radius</I>, which | |
14583 was with them ‘the (straight line) from the centre’, <G>h( e)k tou= | |
14584 ke/ntrou</G>. A tangent to a circle is defined (Def. 2) as a straight | |
14585 line which meets the circle but, if produced, does not cut it; | |
14586 this is provisional pending the proof in III. 16 that such lines | |
14587 exist. The definitions (4, 5) of straight lines (in a circle), | |
14588 i. e. chords, equally distant or more or less distant from the | |
14589 centre (the test being the length of the perpendicular from | |
14590 the centre on the chord) might have referred, more generally, | |
14591 to the distance of any straight line from any point. The | |
14592 definition (7) of the ‘angle <I>of</I> a segment’ (the ‘mixed’ angle | |
14593 made by the circumference with the base at either end) is | |
14594 a survival from earlier text-books (cf. Props. 16, 31). The | |
14595 definitions of the ‘angle <I>in</I> a segment’ (8) and of ‘similar | |
14596 segments’ (11) assume (provisionally pending III. 21) that the | |
14597 angle in a segment is one and the same at whatever point of | |
14598 the circumference it is formed. A <I>sector</I> (<G>tomeu/s</G>, explained by | |
14599 a scholiast as <G>skutotomiko\s tomeu/s</G>, a shoemaker's knife) is | |
14600 defined (10), but there is nothing about ‘similar sectors’ and | |
14601 no statement that similar segments belong to similar sectors. | |
14602 <p>Of the propositions of Book III we may distinguish certain | |
14603 groups. Central properties account for four propositions, | |
14604 namely 1 (to find the centre of a circle), 3 (any straight line | |
14605 through the centre which bisects any chord not passing | |
14606 through the centre cuts it at right angles, and vice versa), | |
14607 4 (two chords not passing through the centre cannot bisect | |
14608 one another) and 9 (the centre is the only point from which | |
14609 more than two equal straight lines can be drawn to the | |
14610 circumference). Besides 3, which shows that any diameter | |
14611 bisects the whole series of chords at right angles to it, three | |
14612 other propositions throw light on the <I>form</I> of the circum- | |
14613 ference of a circle, 2 (showing that it is everywhere concave | |
14614 towards the centre), 7 and 8 (dealing with the varying lengths | |
14615 of straight lines drawn from any point, internal or external, | |
14616 to the concave or convex circumference, as the case may be, | |
14617 <pb n=382><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14618 and proving that they are of maximum or minimum length | |
14619 when they pass through the centre, and that they diminish or | |
14620 increase as they diverge more and more from the maximum | |
14621 or minimum straight lines on either side, while the lengths of | |
14622 any two which are equally inclined to them, one on each side, | |
14623 are equal). | |
14624 <p>Two circles which cut or touch one another are dealt with | |
14625 in 5, 6 (the two circles cannot have the same centre), 10, 13 | |
14626 (they cannot cut in more points than two, or touch at more | |
14627 points than one), 11 and the interpolated 12 (when they touch, | |
14628 the line of centres passes through the point of contact). | |
14629 <p>14, 15 deal with chords (which are equal if equally distant | |
14630 from the centre and vice versa, while chords more distant | |
14631 from the centre are less, and chords less distant greater, and | |
14632 vice versa). | |
14633 <p>16-19 are concerned with tangent properties including the | |
14634 drawing of a tangent (17); it is in 16 that we have the | |
14635 survival of the ‘angle <I>of</I> a semicircle’, which is proved greater | |
14636 than any acute rectilineal angle, while the ‘remaining’ angle | |
14637 (the ‘angle’, afterwards called <G>keratoeidh/s</G>, or ‘hornlike’, | |
14638 between the curve and the tangent at the point of contact) | |
14639 is less than any rectilineal angle. These ‘mixed’ angles, | |
14640 occurring in 16 and 31, appear no more in serious Greek | |
14641 geometry, though controversy about their nature went on | |
14642 in the works of commentators down to Clavius, Peletarius | |
14643 (Pelétier), Vieta, Galilei and Wallis. | |
14644 <p>We now come to propositions about segments. 20 proves | |
14645 that the angle at the centre is double of the angle at the | |
14646 circumference, and 21 that the angles in the same segment are | |
14647 all equal, which leads to the property of the quadrilateral | |
14648 in a circle (22). After propositions (23, 24) on ‘similar | |
14649 segments’, it is proved that in equal circles equal arcs subtend | |
14650 and are subtended by equal angles at the centre or circum- | |
14651 ference, and equal arcs subtend and are subtended by equal | |
14652 chords (26-9). 30 is the problem of bisecting a given arc, | |
14653 and 31 proves that the angle in a segment is right, acute or | |
14654 obtuse according as the segment is a semicircle, greater than | |
14655 a semicircle or less than a semicircle. 32 proves that the | |
14656 angle made by a tangent with a chord through the point | |
14657 of contact is equal to the angle in the alternate segment; | |
14658 <pb n=383><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOKS III-IV</head> | |
14659 33, 34 are problems of constructing or cutting off a segment | |
14660 containing a given angle, and 25 constructs the complete circle | |
14661 when a segment of it is given. | |
14662 <p>The Book ends with three important propositions. Given | |
14663 a circle and any point <I>O</I>, internal (35) or external (36), then, | |
14664 if any straight line through <I>O</I> meets the circle in <I>P, Q</I>, the | |
14665 rectangle <I>PO.OQ</I> is constant and, in the case where <I>O</I> is | |
14666 an external point, is equal to the square on the tangent from | |
14667 <I>O</I> to the circle. Proposition 37 is the converse of 36. | |
14668 <p>Book IV, consisting entirely of problems, again deals with | |
14669 circles, but in relation to rectilineal figures inscribed or circum- | |
14670 scribed to them. After definitions of these terms, Euclid | |
14671 shows, in the preliminary Proposition 1, how to fit into a circle | |
14672 a chord of given length, being less than the diameter. The | |
14673 remaining problems are problems of inscribing or circum- | |
14674 scribing rectilineal figures. The case of the triangle comes | |
14675 first, and we learn how to inscribe in or circumscribe about | |
14676 a circle a triangle equiangular with a given triangle (2, 3) and | |
14677 to inscribe a circle in or circumscribe a circle about a given | |
14678 triangle (4, 5). 6-9 are the same problems for a square, 11- | |
14679 14 for a regular pentagon, and 15 (with porism) for a regular | |
14680 hexagon. The porism to 15 also states that the side of the | |
14681 inscribed regular hexagon is manifestly equal to the radius | |
14682 of the circle. 16 shows how to inscribe in a circle a regular | |
14683 polygon with fifteen angles, a problem suggested by astronomy, | |
14684 since the obliquity of the ecliptic was taken to be about 24°, | |
14685 or one-fifteenth of 360°. IV. 10 is the important proposition, | |
14686 required for the construction of a regular pentagon, ‘to | |
14687 construct an isosceles triangle such that each of the base | |
14688 angles is double of the vertical angle’, which is effected by | |
14689 dividing one of the equal sides in extreme and mean ratio | |
14690 (II. 11) and fitting into the circle with this side as radius | |
14691 a chord equal to the greater segment; the proof of the con- | |
14692 struction depends on III. 32 and 37. | |
14693 <p>We are not surprised to learn from a scholiast that the | |
14694 whole Book is ‘the discovery of the Pythagoreans’.<note>Euclid, ed. Heib., vol. v, pp. 272-3.</note> The | |
14695 same scholium says that ‘it is proved in this Book that | |
14696 the perimeter of a circle is not triple of its diameter, as many | |
14697 <pb n=384><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14698 suppose, but greater than that (the reference is clearly to | |
14699 IV. 15 Por.), and likewise that neither is the circle three- | |
14700 fourths of the triangle circumscribed about it’. Were these | |
14701 fallacies perhaps exposed in the lost <I>Pseudaria</I> of Euclid? | |
14702 <p>Book V is devoted to the new theory of proportion, | |
14703 applicable to incommensurable as well as commensurable | |
14704 magnitudes, and to magnitudes of every kind (straight lines, | |
14705 areas, volumes, numbers, times, &c.), which was due to | |
14706 Eudoxus. Greek mathematics can boast no finer discovery | |
14707 than this theory, which first put on a sound footing so much | |
14708 of geometry as depended on the use of proportions. How far | |
14709 Eudoxus himself worked out his theory in detail is unknown; | |
14710 the scholiast who attributes the discovery of it to him says | |
14711 that ‘it is recognized by all’ that Book V is, as regards its | |
14712 arrangement and sequence in the <I>Elements</I>, due to Euclid | |
14713 himself.<note>Euclid, ed. Heib., vol. v, p. 282.</note> The ordering of the propositions and the develop- | |
14714 ment of the proofs are indeed masterly and worthy of Euclid; | |
14715 as Barrow said, ‘There is nothing in the whole body of the | |
14716 elements of a more subtile invention, nothing more solidly | |
14717 established, and more accurately handled, than the doctrine of | |
14718 proportionals’. It is a pity that, notwithstanding the pre- | |
14719 eminent place which Euclid has occupied in English mathe- | |
14720 matical teaching, Book V itself is little known in detail; if it | |
14721 were, there would, I think, be less tendency to seek for | |
14722 substitutes; indeed, after reading some of the substitutes, | |
14723 it is with relief that one turns to the original. For this | |
14724 reason, I shall make my account of Book V somewhat full, | |
14725 with the object of indicating not only the whole content but | |
14726 also the course of the proofs. | |
14727 <p>Of the Definitions the following are those which need | |
14728 separate mention. The definition (3) of <I>ratio</I> as ‘a sort of | |
14729 relation (<G>poia\ sxe/sis</G>) in respect of size (<G>phliko/ths</G>) between | |
14730 two magnitudes of the same kind’ is as vague and of as | |
14731 little practical use as that of a straight line; it was probably | |
14732 inserted for completeness' sake, and in order merely to aid the | |
14733 conception of a ratio. Definition 4 (‘Magnitudes are said to | |
14734 have a ratio to one another which are capable, when multi- | |
14735 plied, of exceeding one another’) is important not only because | |
14736 <pb n=385><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK V</head> | |
14737 it shows that the magnitudes must be of the same kind, | |
14738 but because, while it includes incommensurable as well as | |
14739 commensurable magnitudes, it excludes the relation of a finite | |
14740 magnitude to a magnitude of the same kind which is either | |
14741 infinitely great or infinitely small; it is also practically equiva- | |
14742 lent to the principle which underlies the method of exhaustion | |
14743 now known as the Axiom of Archimedes. Most important | |
14744 of all is the fundamental definition (5) of magnitudes which | |
14745 are in the same ratio: ‘Magnitudes are said to be in the same | |
14746 ratio, the first to the second and the third to the fourth, when, | |
14747 if any equimultiples whatever be taken of the first and third, | |
14748 and any equimultiples whatever of the second and fourth, the | |
14749 former equimultiples alike exceed, are alike equal to, or alike | |
14750 fall short of, the latter equimultiples taken in corresponding | |
14751 order.’ Perhaps the greatest tribute to this marvellous defini- | |
14752 tion is its adoption by Weierstrass as a definition of equal | |
14753 numbers. For a most attractive explanation of its exact | |
14754 significance and its absolute sufficiency the reader should turn | |
14755 to De Morgan's articles on Ratio and Proportion in the <I>Penny | |
14756 Cyclopaedia.</I><note>Vol. xix (1841). I have largely reproduced the articles in <I>The | |
14757 Thirteen Books of Euclid's Elements</I>, vol. ii, pp. 116-24.</note> The definition (7) of <I>greater ratio</I> is an adden- | |
14758 dum to Definition 5: ‘When, of the equimultiples, the multiple | |
14759 of the first exceeds the multiple of the second, but the | |
14760 multiple of the third does not exceed the multiple of the | |
14761 fourth, then the first is said to have a <I>greater ratio</I> to | |
14762 the second than the third has to the fourth’; this (possibly | |
14763 for brevity's sake) states only one criterion, the other possible | |
14764 criterion being that, while the multiple of the first is <I>equal</I> | |
14765 to that of the second, the multiple of the third is <I>tess</I> than | |
14766 that of the fourth. A proportion may consist of three or | |
14767 four terms (Defs. 8, 9, 10); ‘corresponding’ or ‘homologous’ | |
14768 terms are antecedents in relation to antecedents and conse- | |
14769 quents in relation to consequents (11). Euclid proceeds to | |
14770 define the various transformations of ratios. <I>Alternation</I> | |
14771 (<G>e)nalla/x</G>, <I>alternando</I>) means taking the alternate terms in | |
14772 the proportion <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, i.e. transforming it into <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>b</I>:<I>d</I></MATH> | |
14773 (12). <I>Inversion</I> (<G>a)na/palin</G>, inversely) means turning the ratio | |
14774 <I>a:b</I> into <I>b:a</I> (13). <I>Composition</I> of a ratio, <G>su/nqesis lo/gou</G> | |
14775 (<I>componendo</I> is in Greek <G>sunqe/nti</G>, ‘to one who has compounded | |
14776 <pb n=386><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14777 or added’, i. e. if one compounds or adds) is the turning of | |
14778 <I>a:b</I> into <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>):<I>b</I></MATH> (14). <I>Separation</I>, <G>diai/resis</G> (<G>dielo/nti</G>= | |
14779 <I>separando</I>) turns <I>a:b</I> into <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>):<I>b</I></MATH> (15). <I>Conversion</I>, <G>a)na- | |
14780 strofh/</G> (<G>a)nastre/yanti</G>=<I>convertendo</I>) turns <I>a</I>:<I>b</I> into <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>a</I>-<I>b</I></MATH> | |
14781 (16). Lastly, <I>ex aequali</I> (sc. <I>distantia</I>), <G>di) i)/sou</G>, and <I>ex aequali | |
14782 in disturbed proportion</I> (<G>e)n tetaragme/nh a)nalogi/a|</G>) are defined | |
14783 (17, 18). If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>A</I>:<I>B</I>, <I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>B</I>:<I>C</I> ... <I>k</I>:<I>l</I>=<I>K</I>:<I>L</I></MATH>, then | |
14784 the inference <I>ex aequali</I> is that <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>l</I>=<I>A</I>:<I>L</I></MATH> (proved in V. 22). | |
14785 If again <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>B</I>:<I>C</I></MATH> and <MATH><I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>A</I>:<I>B</I></MATH>, the inference <I>ex aequali | |
14786 in disturbed proportion</I> is <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>A</I>:<I>C</I></MATH> (proved in V. 23). | |
14787 <p>In reproducing the content of the Book I shall express | |
14788 magnitudes in general (which Euclid represents by straight | |
14789 lines) by the letters <I>a, b, c</I> ... and I shall use the letters | |
14790 <I>m, n, p</I> ... to express integral numbers: thus <I>ma, mb</I> are | |
14791 equimultiples of <I>a, b.</I> | |
14792 <p>The first six propositions are simple theorems in concrete | |
14793 arithmetic, and they are practically all proved by separating | |
14794 into their units the multiples used. | |
14795 <MATH> | |
14796 <BRACE> | |
14797 1. <I>ma</I>+<I>mb</I>+<I>mc</I>+...=<I>m</I>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>+<I>c</I>+...). | |
14798 5. <I>ma</I>-<I>mb</I>=<I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>). | |
14799 </BRACE> | |
14800 </MATH> | |
14801 5 is proved by means of 1. As a matter of fact, Euclid | |
14802 assumes the construction of a straight line equal to 1/<I>m</I>th of | |
14803 <MATH><I>ma</I>-<I>mb</I></MATH>. This is an anticipation of VI. 9, but can be avoided; | |
14804 for we can draw a straight line equal to <MATH><I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)</MATH>; then, | |
14805 by 1, <MATH><I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)+<I>mb</I>=<I>ma</I></MATH>, or <MATH><I>ma</I>-<I>mb</I>=<I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)</MATH>. | |
14806 <MATH> | |
14807 <BRACE> | |
14808 2. <I>ma</I>+<I>na</I>+<I>pa</I>+...=(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>+<I>p</I>+...)<I>a</I>. | |
14809 6. <I>ma</I>-<I>na</I>=(<I>m</I>-<I>n</I>)<I>a</I>. | |
14810 </BRACE> | |
14811 </MATH> | |
14812 Euclid actually expresses 2 and 6 by saying that <I>ma</I>±<I>na</I> is | |
14813 the same multiple of <I>a</I> that <I>mb</I>±<I>nb</I> is of <I>b.</I> By separation | |
14814 of <I>m, n</I> into units he in fact shows (in 2) that | |
14815 <MATH><I>ma</I>+<I>na</I>=(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)<I>a</I></MATH>, and <MATH><I>mb</I>+<I>nb</I>=(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)<I>b</I></MATH>. | |
14816 6 is proved by means of 2, as 5 by means of 1. | |
14817 <p>3. If <I>m.na, m.nb</I> are equimultiples of <I>na, nb</I>, which are | |
14818 themselves equimultiples of <I>a, b</I>, then <I>m.na, m.nb</I> are also | |
14819 equimultiples of <I>a, b.</I> | |
14820 <p>By separating <I>m, n</I> into their units Euclid practically proves | |
14821 that <MATH><I>m.na</I>=<I>mn.a</I></MATH> and <MATH><I>m.nb</I>=<I>mn.b</I></MATH>. | |
14822 <pb n=387><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK V</head> | |
14823 <p>4. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, then <MATH><I>ma</I>:<I>nb</I>=<I>mc</I>:<I>nd</I></MATH>. | |
14824 <p>Take any equimultiples <I>p.ma, p.mc</I> of <I>ma, mc</I>, and any | |
14825 equimultiples <I>q.nb, q.nd</I> of <I>nb, nd.</I> Then, by 3, these equi- | |
14826 multiples are also equimultiples of <I>a, c</I> and <I>b, d</I> respectively, | |
14827 so that by Def. 5, since <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, | |
14828 <MATH><I>p.ma</I>>=<<I>q.nb</I></MATH> according as <MATH><I>p.mc</I>>=<<I>q.nd</I></MATH>, | |
14829 whence, again by Def. 5, since <I>p, q</I> are any integers, | |
14830 <MATH><I>ma</I>:<I>nb</I>=<I>mc</I>:<I>nd</I></MATH>. | |
14831 <MATH> | |
14832 <BRACE><note>; and conversely.</note> | |
14833 7, 9. If <I>a</I>=<I>b</I>, then <I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>b</I>:<I>c</I> | |
14834 and <I>c</I>:<I>a</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>b</I> | |
14835 </BRACE> | |
14836 </MATH> | |
14837 <MATH> | |
14838 <BRACE><note>; and conversely.</note> | |
14839 8, 10. If <I>a</I>><I>b</I>, then <I>a</I>:<I>c</I>><I>b</I>:<I>c</I> | |
14840 and <I>c</I>:<I>b</I>><I>c</I>:<I>a</I> | |
14841 </BRACE> | |
14842 </MATH> | |
14843 <p>7 is proved by means of Def. 5. Take <I>ma, mb</I> equi- | |
14844 multiples of <I>a, b</I>, and <I>nc</I> a multiple of <I>c.</I> Then, since <I>a</I>=<I>b</I>, | |
14845 <MATH><I>ma</I>>=<<I>nc</I></MATH> according as <MATH><I>mb</I>>=<<I>nc</I></MATH>, | |
14846 and <MATH><I>nc</I>>=<<I>ma</I></MATH> according as <MATH><I>nc</I>>=<<I>mb</I></MATH>, | |
14847 whence the results follow. | |
14848 <p>8 is divided into two cases according to which of the two | |
14849 magnitudes <I>a</I>-<I>b</I>, <I>b</I> is the less. Take <I>m</I> such that | |
14850 <MATH><I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)><I>c</I></MATH> or <MATH><I>mb</I>><I>c</I></MATH> | |
14851 in the two cases respectively. Next let <I>nc</I> be the first | |
14852 multiple of <I>c</I> which is greater than <I>mb</I> or <MATH><I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)</MATH> respec- | |
14853 tively, so that | |
14854 <MATH><I>nc</I>><I>mb</I> or <I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)≥(<I>n</I>-1)<I>c</I></MATH>. | |
14855 Then, (i) since <MATH><I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)><I>c</I></MATH>, we have, by addition, <MATH><I>ma</I>><I>nc</I></MATH>. | |
14856 (ii) since <MATH><I>mb</I>><I>c</I></MATH>, we have similarly <MATH><I>ma</I>><I>nc</I></MATH>. | |
14857 In either case <MATH><I>mb</I><<I>nc</I></MATH>, since in case (ii) <MATH><I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)><I>mb</I></MATH>. | |
14858 Thus in either case, by the definition (7) of greater ratio, | |
14859 <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>><I>b</I>:<I>c</I></MATH>, | |
14860 and <MATH><I>c</I>:<I>b</I>><I>c</I>:<I>a</I></MATH>. | |
14861 <p>The converses 9, 10 are proved from 7, 8 by <I>reductio ad | |
14862 absurdum.</I> | |
14863 <pb n=388><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14864 <p>11. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, | |
14865 and <MATH><I>c</I>:<I>d</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, | |
14866 then <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14867 <p>Proved by taking any equimultiples of <I>a, c, e</I> and any other | |
14868 equimultiples of <I>b, d, f</I>, and using Def. 5. | |
14869 <p>12. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I>=...</MATH> | |
14870 then <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=(<I>a</I>+<I>c</I>+<I>e</I>+...):(<I>b</I>+<I>d</I>+<I>f</I>+...)</MATH>. | |
14871 <p>Proved by means of V. 1 and Def. 5, after taking equi- | |
14872 multiples of <I>a, c, e</I> ... and other equimultiples of <I>b, d, f</I> .... | |
14873 <p>13. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, | |
14874 and <MATH><I>c</I>:<I>d</I>><I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, | |
14875 then <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>><I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14876 <p>Equimultiples <I>mc, me</I> of <I>c, e</I> are taken and equimultiples | |
14877 <I>nd, nf</I> of <I>d, f</I> such that, while <MATH><I>mc</I>><I>nd</I></MATH>, <I>me</I> is not greater | |
14878 than <I>nf</I> (Def. 7). Then the same equimultiples <I>ma, mc</I> of | |
14879 <I>a, c</I> and the same equimultiples <I>nb, nd</I> of <I>b, d</I> are taken, and | |
14880 Defs. 5 and 7 are used in succession. | |
14881 <p>14. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, then, according as <MATH><I>a</I>>=<<I>c</I>, <I>b</I>>=<<I>d</I></MATH>. | |
14882 <p>The first case only is proved; the others are dismissed with | |
14883 ‘Similarly’. | |
14884 <p>If <MATH><I>a</I>><I>c</I>, <I>a</I>:<I>b</I>><I>c</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>. (8) | |
14885 <p>But <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, whence (13) <MATH><I>c</I>:<I>d</I>><I>c</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>, and therefore (10) | |
14886 <I>b</I>><I>d</I>. | |
14887 <p>15. <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>ma</I>:<I>mb</I></MATH>. | |
14888 <p>Dividing the multiples into their units, we have <I>m</I> equal | |
14889 ratios <I>a</I>:<I>b</I>; the result follows by 12. | |
14890 <p>Propositions 16-19 prove certain cases of the transformation | |
14891 of proportions in the sense of Defs. 12-16. The case of | |
14892 <I>inverting</I> the ratios is omitted, probably as being obvious. | |
14893 For, if <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, the application of Def. 5 proves simul- | |
14894 taneously that <MATH><I>b</I>:<I>a</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>c</I></MATH>. | |
14895 <p>16. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, | |
14896 then, <I>alternando</I>, <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>b</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>. | |
14897 <p>Since <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>ma</I>:<I>mb</I></MATH>, and <MATH><I>c</I>:<I>d</I>=<I>nc</I>:<I>nd</I></MATH>, (15) | |
14898 <pb n=389><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK V</head> | |
14899 we have <MATH><I>ma</I>:<I>mb</I>=<I>nc</I>:<I>nd</I></MATH>, (11) | |
14900 whence (14), according as <MATH><I>ma</I>>=<<I>nc</I>, <I>mb</I>>=<<I>nd</I></MATH>; | |
14901 therefore (Def. 5) <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>b</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>. | |
14902 <p>17. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, | |
14903 then, <I>separando</I>, <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>):<I>b</I>=(<I>c</I>-<I>d</I>):<I>d</I></MATH>. | |
14904 <p>Take <I>ma, mb, mc, md</I> equimultiples of all four magnitudes, | |
14905 and <I>nb, nd</I> other equimultiples of <I>b, d.</I> It follows (2) that | |
14906 <MATH>(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)<I>b</I>, (<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)<I>d</I></MATH> are also equimultiples of <I>b, d.</I> | |
14907 <p>Therefore, since <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, | |
14908 <MATH><I>ma</I>>=<(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)<I>b</I></MATH> according as <MATH><I>mc</I>>=<(<I>m</I>+<I>n</I>)<I>d</I></MATH>. (Def. 5) | |
14909 <p>Subtracting <I>mb</I> from both sides of the former relation and | |
14910 <I>md</I> from both sides of the latter, we have (5) | |
14911 <MATH><I>m</I>(<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>)>=<<I>nb</I></MATH> according as <MATH><I>m</I>(<I>c</I>-<I>d</I>)>=<<I>nd</I></MATH>. | |
14912 <p>Therefore (Def. 5) <MATH><I>a</I>-<I>b</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>-<I>d</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>. | |
14913 (I have here abbreviated Euclid a little, without altering the | |
14914 substance.) | |
14915 <p>18. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, | |
14916 then, <I>componendo</I>, <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>):<I>b</I>=(<I>c</I>+<I>d</I>):<I>d</I></MATH>. | |
14917 <p>Proved by <I>reductio ad absurdum.</I> Euclid assumes that | |
14918 <MATH><I>a</I>+<I>b</I>:<I>b</I>=(<I>c</I>+<I>d</I>):(<I>d</I>±<I>x</I>)</MATH>, if that is possible. (This .implies | |
14919 that to any three given magnitudes, two of which at least | |
14920 are of the same kind, there exists a fourth proportional, an | |
14921 assumption which is not strictly legitimate until the fact has | |
14922 been proved by construction.) | |
14923 <p>Therefore, <I>separando</I> (17), <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=(<I>c</I>∓<I>x</I>):(<I>d</I>±<I>x</I>)</MATH>,. | |
14924 whence (11), <MATH>(<I>c</I>∓<I>x</I>):(<I>d</I>±<I>x</I>)=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, which relations are im- | |
14925 possible, by 14. | |
14926 <p>19. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, | |
14927 then <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>):(<I>b</I>-<I>d</I>)=<I>a</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>. | |
14928 <p>Alternately (16), | |
14929 <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>b</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, whence <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>):<I>c</I>=(<I>b</I>-<I>d</I>):<I>d</I></MATH> (17). | |
14930 <p>Alternately again, <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>):(<I>b</I>-<I>d</I>)=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH> (16); | |
14931 whence (11) <MATH>(<I>a</I>-<I>c</I>):(<I>b</I>-<I>d</I>)=<I>a</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>. | |
14932 <pb n=390><head>EUCLID</head> | |
14933 <p>The transformation <I>convertendo</I> is only given in an inter- | |
14934 polated Porism to 19. But it is easily obtained by using 17 | |
14935 (<I>separando</I>) combined with <I>alternando</I> (16). Euclid himself | |
14936 proves it in X. 14 by using successively <I>separando</I> (17), <I>inver- | |
14937 sion</I> and <I>ex aequali</I> (22). | |
14938 <p>The <I>composition</I> of ratios <I>ex aequali</I> and <I>ex aequali in | |
14939 disturbed proportion</I> is dealt with in 22, 23, each of which | |
14940 depends on a preliminary proposition. | |
14941 <p>20. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>e</I></MATH>, | |
14942 and <MATH><I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, | |
14943 then, <I>ex aequali</I>, according as <MATH><I>a</I>>=<<I>c</I>, <I>d</I>>=<<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14944 <p>For, according as <MATH><I>a</I>>=<<I>c</I>, <I>a</I>:<I>b</I>>=<<I>c</I>:<I>b</I></MATH> (7, 8), | |
14945 and therefore, by means of the above relations and 13, 11, | |
14946 <MATH><I>d</I>:<I>e</I>>=<<I>f</I>:<I>e</I></MATH>, | |
14947 and therefore again (9, 10) | |
14948 <MATH><I>d</I>>=<<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14949 <p>21. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, | |
14950 and <MATH><I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>e</I></MATH>, | |
14951 then, <I>ex aequali in disturbed proportion</I>, | |
14952 according as <MATH><I>a</I>>=<<I>c</I>, <I>d</I>>=<<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14953 <p>For, according as <MATH><I>a</I>>=<<I>c</I>, <I>a</I>:<I>b</I>>=<<I>c</I>:<I>b</I></MATH> (7, 8), | |
14954 or <MATH><I>e</I>:<I>f</I>>=<<I>e</I>:<I>d</I></MATH> (13, 11), | |
14955 and therefore <MATH><I>d</I>>=<<I>f</I></MATH> (9, 10). | |
14956 <p>22. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>e</I></MATH>, | |
14957 and <MATH><I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, | |
14958 then, <I>ex aequali</I>, <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14959 <p>Take equimultiples <I>ma, md; nb, ne; pc, pf</I>, and it follows | |
14960 <MATH> | |
14961 <BRACE><note>(4)</note> | |
14962 that <I>ma</I>:<I>nb</I>=<I>md</I>:<I>ne</I>, | |
14963 and <I>nb</I>:<I>pc</I>=<I>ne</I>:<I>pf</I> | |
14964 </BRACE> | |
14965 </MATH> | |
14966 <p>Therefore (20), according as <MATH><I>ma</I>>=<<I>pc</I>, <I>md</I>>=<<I>pf</I></MATH>, | |
14967 whence (Def. 5) <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14968 <pb n=391><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK V</head> | |
14969 <p>23. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, | |
14970 and <MATH><I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>e</I></MATH>, | |
14971 then, <I>ex aequali in disturbed proportion</I>, <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14972 <p>Equimultiples <I>ma, mb, md</I> and <I>nc, ne, nf</I> are taken, and | |
14973 it is proved, by means of 11, 15, 16, that | |
14974 <MATH><I>ma</I>:<I>mb</I>=<I>ne</I>:<I>nf</I></MATH>, | |
14975 and <MATH><I>mb</I>:<I>nc</I>=<I>md</I>:<I>ne</I></MATH>, | |
14976 whence (21) <MATH><I>ma</I>>=<<I>nc</I></MATH> according as <MATH><I>md</I>>=<<I>nf</I></MATH> | |
14977 and (Def. 5) <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14978 <p>24. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, | |
14979 and also <MATH><I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, | |
14980 then <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>):<I>c</I>=(<I>d</I>+<I>e</I>):<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14981 <p>Invert the second proportion to <MATH><I>c</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>f</I>:<I>e</I></MATH>, and compound | |
14982 the first proportion with this (22); | |
14983 therefore <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>e</I></MATH>. | |
14984 <p><I>Componendo,</I> <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>):<I>b</I>=(<I>d</I>+<I>e</I>):<I>e</I></MATH>, which compounded (22) | |
14985 with the second proportion gives <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>):<I>c</I>=(<I>d</I>+<I>e</I>):<I>f</I></MATH>. | |
14986 <p>25. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, and of the four terms <I>a</I> is the greatest | |
14987 (so that <I>d</I> is also the least), <MATH><I>a</I>+<I>d</I>><I>b</I>+<I>c</I></MATH>. | |
14988 <p>Since <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, | |
14989 <MATH><I>a-c</I>:<I>b-d</I>=<I>a</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>; (19) | |
14990 and, since <MATH><I>a</I>><I>b</I>, (<I>a-c</I>)>(<I>b-d</I>)</MATH>. (16, 14) | |
14991 <p>Add <I>c</I>+<I>d</I> to each; | |
14992 therefore <MATH><I>a</I>+<I>d</I>><I>b</I>+<I>c</I></MATH>. | |
14993 <p>Such slight defects as are found in the text of this great | |
14994 Book as it has reached us, like other slight imperfections of | |
14995 form in the <I>Elements</I>, point to the probability that the work | |
14996 never received its final touches from Euclid's hand; but they | |
14997 can all be corrected without much difficulty, as Simson showed | |
14998 in his excellent edition. | |
14999 <p>Book VI contains the application to plane geometry of the | |
15000 general theory of proportion established in Book V. It begins | |
15001 with definitions of ‘similar rectilineal figures’ and of what is | |
15002 <pb n=392><head>EUCLID</head> | |
15003 meant by cutting a straight line ‘in extreme and mean ratio’. | |
15004 The first and last propositions are analogous; 1 proves that | |
15005 triangles and parallelograms of the same height are to one | |
15006 another as their bases, and 33 that in equal circles angles | |
15007 at the centre or circumference are as the arcs on which they | |
15008 stand; both use the method of equimultiples and apply | |
15009 V, Def. 5 as the test of proportion. Equally fundamental | |
15010 are 2 (that two sides of a triangle cut by any parallel to | |
15011 the third side are divided proportionally, and the converse), | |
15012 and 3 (that the internal bisector of an angle of a triangle cuts | |
15013 the opposite side into parts which have the same ratio as the | |
15014 sides containing the angle, and the converse); 2 depends | |
15015 directly on 1 and 3 on 2. Then come the alternative con- | |
15016 ditions for the similarity of two triangles: equality of all the | |
15017 angles respectively (4), proportionality of pairs of sides in | |
15018 order (5), equality of one angle in each with proportionality | |
15019 of sides containing the equal angles (6), and the ‘ambiguous | |
15020 case’ (7), in which one angle is equal to one angle and the | |
15021 sides about other angles are proportional. After the important | |
15022 proposition (8) that the perpendicular from the right angle | |
15023 in a right-angled triangle to the opposite side divides the | |
15024 triangle into two triangles similar to the original triangle and | |
15025 to one another, we pass to the proportional division of | |
15026 straight lines (9, 10) and the problems of finding a third | |
15027 proportional to two straight lines (11), a fourth proportional | |
15028 to three (12), and a mean proportional to two straight lines | |
15029 (13, the Book VI version of II. 14). In 14, 15 Euclid proves | |
15030 the reciprocal proportionality of the sides about the equal | |
15031 angles in parallelograms or triangles of equal area which have | |
15032 one angle equal to one angle and the converse; by placing the | |
15033 equal angles vertically opposite to one another so that the sides | |
15034 about them lie along two straight lines, and completing the | |
15035 figure, Euclid is able to apply VI. 1. From 14 are directly | |
15036 deduced 16, 17 (that, if four or three straight lines be propor- | |
15037 tionals, the rectangle contained by the extremes is equal to | |
15038 the rectangle contained by the two means or the square on the | |
15039 one mean, and the converse). 18-22 deal with similar recti- | |
15040 lineal figures; 19 (with Porism) and 20 are specially important, | |
15041 proving that similar triangles, and similar polygons generally, | |
15042 are to one another in the duplicate ratio of corresponding | |
15043 <pb n=393><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK VI</head> | |
15044 sides, and that, if three straight lines are proportional, then, | |
15045 as the first is to the third, so is the figure described on the first | |
15046 to the similar figure similarly described on the second. The | |
15047 fundamental case of the two similar triangles is prettily proved | |
15048 thus. The triangles being <I>ABC, DEF</I>, in which <I>B, E</I> are equal | |
15049 angles and <I>BC, EF</I> corresponding sides, find a third propor- | |
15050 tional to <I>BC, EF</I> and measure it off along <I>BC</I> as <I>BG</I>; join <I>AG.</I> | |
15051 Then the triangles <I>ABG, DEF</I> have their sides about the equal | |
15052 angles <I>B, E</I> reciprocally proportional and are therefore equal | |
15053 (VI. 15); the rest follows from VI. 1 and the definition of | |
15054 duplicate ratio (V, Def. 9). | |
15055 <p>Proposition 23 (equiangular parallelograms have to one | |
15056 another the ratio compounded of the ratios of their sides) is | |
15057 important in itself, and also because it introduces us to the | |
15058 practical use of the method of compounding, i.e. multiplying, | |
15059 ratios which is of such extraordinarily wide application in | |
15060 Greek geometry. Euclid has never defined ‘compound ratio’ | |
15061 or the ‘compounding’ of ratios; but the meaning of the terms | |
15062 <FIG> | |
15063 and the way to compound ratios are made clear in this pro- | |
15064 position. The equiangular parallelograms are placed so that | |
15065 two equal angles as <I>BCD, GCE</I> are vertically opposite at <I>C.</I> | |
15066 Complete the parallelogram <I>DCGH.</I> Take any straight line <I>K</I>, | |
15067 and (12) find another, <I>L</I>, such that | |
15068 <MATH><I>BC</I>:<I>CG</I>=<I>K</I>:<I>L</I></MATH>, | |
15069 and again another straight line <I>M</I>, such that | |
15070 <MATH><I>DC</I>:<I>CE</I>=<I>L</I>:<I>M</I></MATH>. | |
15071 Now the ratio compounded of <I>K</I>:<I>L</I> and <I>L</I>:<I>M</I> is <I>K</I>:<I>M</I>; there- | |
15072 fore <I>K</I>:<I>M</I> is the ‘ratio compounded of the ratios of the sides’. | |
15073 <p>And <MATH>(<I>ABCD</I>):(<I>DCGH</I>)=<I>BC</I>:<I>CG</I>, (1) | |
15074 =<I>K</I>:<I>L</I>; | |
15075 (<I>DCGH</I>):(<I>CEFG</I>)=<I>DC</I>:<I>CE</I> (1) | |
15076 =<I>L</I>:<I>M</I></MATH>, | |
15077 <pb n=394><head>EUCLID</head> | |
15078 <p>Therefore, <I>ex aequali</I> (V. 22), | |
15079 <MATH>(<I>ABCD</I>):(<I>CEFG</I>)=<I>K</I>:<I>M</I></MATH>. | |
15080 <p>The important Proposition 25 (to construct a rectilineal figure | |
15081 similar to one, and equal to another, given rectilineal figure) is | |
15082 one of the famous problems alternatively associated with the | |
15083 story of Pythagoras's sacrifice<note>Plutarch, <I>Non posse suaviter vivi secundum Epicurum</I>, c. 11.</note>; it is doubtless Pythagorean. | |
15084 The given figure (<I>P,</I> say) to which the required figure is to be | |
15085 similar is transformed (I. 44) into a parallelogram on the same | |
15086 base <I>BC.</I> Then the other figure (<I>Q,</I> say) to which the required | |
15087 figure is to be <I>equal</I> is (I. 45) transformed into a parallelo- | |
15088 gram on the base <I>CF</I> (in a straight line with <I>BC</I>) and of equal | |
15089 height with the other parallelogram. Then <MATH>(<I>P</I>):(<I>Q</I>)=<I>BC</I>:<I>CF</I></MATH> | |
15090 (1). It is then only necessary to take a straight line <I>GH</I> | |
15091 a mean proportional between <I>BC</I> and <I>CF</I>, and to describe on | |
15092 <I>GH</I> as base a rectilineal figure similar to <I>P</I> which has <I>BC</I> as | |
15093 base (VI. 18). The proof of the correctness of the construction | |
15094 follows from VI. 19 Por. | |
15095 <p>In 27, 28, 29 we reach the final problems in the Pythagorean | |
15096 <I>application of areas</I>, which are the geometrical equivalent of | |
15097 the algebraical solution of the most general form of quadratic | |
15098 equation where that equation has a real and positive root. | |
15099 Detailed notice of these propositions is necessary because of | |
15100 their exceptional historic importance, which arises from the | |
15101 fact that the method of these propositions was constantly used | |
15102 <FIG> | |
15103 by the Greeks in the solution of problems. They constitute, | |
15104 for example, the foundation of Book X of the <I>Elements</I> and of | |
15105 <pb n=395><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK VI</head> | |
15106 the whole treatment of conic sections by Apollonius. The | |
15107 problems themselves are enunciated in 28, 29: ‘To a given | |
15108 straight line to apply a parallelogram equal to a given recti- | |
15109 lineal figure and <I>deficient</I> (or <I>exceeding</I>) by a parallelogrammic | |
15110 figure similar to a given parallelogram’; and 27 supplies the | |
15111 <G>diorismo/s</G>, or determination of the condition of possibility, | |
15112 which is necessary in the case of <I>deficiency</I> (28): ‘The given | |
15113 rectilineal figure must (in that case) not be greater than the | |
15114 parallelogram described on the half of the straight line and | |
15115 similar to the defect.’ We will take the problem of 28 for | |
15116 examination. | |
15117 <p>We are already familiar with the notion of applying a | |
15118 parallelogram to a straight line <I>AB</I> so that it <I>falls short</I> or | |
15119 <I>exceeds</I> by a certain other parallelogram. Suppose that <I>D</I> is | |
15120 the given parallelogram to which the <I>defect</I> in this case has to | |
15121 be similar. Bisect <I>AB</I> in <I>E</I>, and on the half <I>EB</I> describe the | |
15122 parallelogram <I>GEBF</I> similar and similarly situated to <I>D.</I> | |
15123 Draw the diagonal <I>GB</I> and complete the parallelogram | |
15124 <I>HABF.</I> Now, if we draw through any point <I>T</I> on <I>HA</I> a | |
15125 straight line <I>TR</I> parallel to <I>AB</I> meeting the diagonal <I>GB</I> in | |
15126 <I>Q</I>, and then draw <I>PQS</I> parallel to <I>TA</I>, the parallelogram <I>TASQ</I> | |
15127 is a parallelogram applied to <I>AB</I> but falling short by a | |
15128 parallelogram similar and similarly situated to <I>D</I>, since the | |
15129 deficient parallelogram is <I>QSBR</I> which is similar to <I>EF</I> (24). | |
15130 (In the same way, if <I>T</I> had been on <I>HA produced</I> and <I>TR</I> had | |
15131 met <I>GB produced</I> in <I>R</I>, we should have had a parallelogram | |
15132 applied to <I>AB</I> but <I>exceeding</I> by a parallelogram similar and | |
15133 similarly situated to <I>D.</I>) | |
15134 <p>Now consider the parallelogram <I>AQ</I> falling short by <I>SR</I> | |
15135 similar and similarly situated to <I>D.</I> Since (<I>AO</I>) = (<I>ER</I>), and | |
15136 (<I>OS</I>) = (<I>QF</I>), it follows that the parallelogram <I>AQ</I> is equal to | |
15137 the gnomon <I>UWV</I>, and the problem is therefore that of | |
15138 constructing the gnomon <I>UWV</I> such that its area is equal to | |
15139 that of the given rectilineal figure <I>C.</I> The gnomon obviously | |
15140 cannot be greater than the parallelogram <I>EF</I>, and hence the | |
15141 given rectilineal figure <I>C</I> must not be greater than that | |
15142 parallelogram. This is the <G>diorismo/s</G> proved in 27. | |
15143 <p>Since the gnomon is equal to <I>C</I>, it follows that the parallelo- | |
15144 gram <I>GOQP</I> which with it makes up the parallelogram <I>EF</I> is | |
15145 equal to the difference between (<I>EF</I>) and <I>C.</I> Therefore, in | |
15146 <pb n=396><head>EUCLID</head> | |
15147 order to construct the required gnomon, we have only to draw | |
15148 in the angle <I>FGE</I> the parallelogram <I>GOQP</I> equal to (<I>EF</I>)-<I>C</I> | |
15149 and similar and similarly situated to <I>D.</I> This is what Euclid | |
15150 in fact does; he constructs the parallelogram <I>LKNM</I> equal to | |
15151 (<I>EF</I>) — <I>C</I> and similar and similarly situated to <I>D</I> (by means of | |
15152 25), and then draws <I>GOQP</I> equal to it. The problem is thus | |
15153 solved, <I>TASQ</I> being the required parallelogram. | |
15154 <p>To show the correspondence to the solution of a quadratic | |
15155 equation, let <MATH><I>AB</I>=<I>a, QS</I>=<I>x</I></MATH>, and let <I>b</I>:<I>c</I> be the ratio of the | |
15156 sides of <I>D</I>; therefore <MATH><I>SB</I>=<I>(b/c)x.</I></MATH> Then, if <I>m</I> is a certain con- | |
15157 stant (in fact the sine of an angle of one of the parallelograms), | |
15158 <MATH>(<I>AQ</I>)=<I>m</I>(<I>ax - (b/c)x</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>, so that the equation solved is | |
15159 <MATH><I>m</I>(<I>ax-(b/c)x</I><SUP>2</SUP>)=<I>C.</I></MATH> | |
15160 The algebraical solution is <MATH><I>x</I>=<I>c/b.a</I>/2±√{<I>a/b</I>(<I>c/b.a</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4-<I>C/m</I>)}</MATH>. | |
15161 Euclid gives only one solution (that corresponding to the | |
15162 <I>negative</I> sign), but he was of course aware that there are two, | |
15163 and how he could exhibit the second in the figure. | |
15164 <p>For a real solution we must have <I>C</I> not greater than | |
15165 <MATH><I>m(c/b).a</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4</MATH>, which is the area of <I>EF.</I> This corresponds to Pro- | |
15166 position 27. | |
15167 <p>We observe that what Euclid in fact does is to find the | |
15168 parallelogram <I>GOQP</I> which is of given shape (namely such | |
15169 that its area <MATH><I>m.GO.OQ</I>=<I>m.GO</I><SUP>2</SUP>(<I>b/c</I>)</MATH>) and is equal to (<I>EF</I>)-<I>C</I>; | |
15170 that is, he finds <I>GO</I> such that <MATH><I>GO</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>c/b</I>((<I>c/b</I>).(<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4)-<I>C/m</I>)</MATH>. In other | |
15171 words, he finds the straight line equal to <MATH>√{<I>c/b</I>((<I>c/b</I>).(<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4)-<I>C/m</I>)}</MATH>; | |
15172 and <I>x</I> is thus known, since <MATH><I>x</I>=<I>GE - GO</I>=(<I>c/b</I>).(<I>a</I>/2)-<I>GO</I></MATH>. | |
15173 Euclid's procedure, therefore, corresponds closely to the alge- | |
15174 braic solution. | |
15175 <p>The solution of 29 is exactly similar, <I>mutatis mutandis.</I> | |
15176 A solution is always possible, so that no <G>diorismo/s</G> is required. | |
15177 <pb n=397><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOKS VI-VII</head> | |
15178 <p>VI. 31 gives the extension of the Pythagorean proposition | |
15179 I. 47 showing that for squares in the latter proposition we | |
15180 may substitute similar plane figures of any shape whatever. | |
15181 30 uses 29 to divide a straight line in extreme and mean | |
15182 ratio (the same problem as II. 11). | |
15183 <p>Except in the respect that it is based on the new theory of | |
15184 proportion, Book VI does not appear to contain any matter | |
15185 that was not known before Euclid's time. Nor is the generali- | |
15186 zation of I. 47 in VI. 31, for which Proclus professes such | |
15187 admiration, original on Euclid's part, for, as we have already | |
15188 seen (p. 191), Hippocrates of Chios assumes its truth for semi- | |
15189 circles described on the three sides of a right-angled triangle. | |
15190 <p>We pass to the arithmetical Books, VII, VIII, IX. Book VII | |
15191 begins with a set of definitions applicable in all the three | |
15192 Books. They include definitions of a <I>unit</I>, a <I>number</I>, and the | |
15193 following varieties of numbers, <I>even, odd, even-times-even, even- | |
15194 times-odd, odd-times-odd, prime, prime to one another, com- | |
15195 posite, composite to one another, plane, solid, square, cube, | |
15196 similar plane</I> and <I>solid</I> numbers, and a <I>perfect</I> number, | |
15197 definitions of terms applicable in the numerical theory of pro- | |
15198 portion, namely <I>a part</I> (= a submultiple or aliquot part), | |
15199 <I>parts</I> (=a proper fraction), <I>multiply</I>, and finally the defini- | |
15200 tion of (four) proportional numbers, which states that ‘num- | |
15201 bers are proportional when the first is the same multiple, the | |
15202 same part, or the same parts, of the second that the third is of | |
15203 the fourth’, i.e. numbers <I>a, b, c, d</I> are proportional if, when | |
15204 <MATH><I>a</I>=<I>(m/n)b</I>, <I>c</I>=<I>(m/n)d</I></MATH>, where <I>m, n</I> are any integers (although the | |
15205 definition does not in terms cover the case where <I>m>n</I>). | |
15206 <p>The propositions of Book VII fall into four main groups. | |
15207 1-3 give the method of finding the greatest common mea- | |
15208 sure of two or three unequal numbers in essentially the same | |
15209 form in which it appears in our text-books, Proposition 1 | |
15210 giving the test for two numbers being prime to one another, | |
15211 namely that no remainder measures the preceding quotient | |
15212 till 1 is reached. The second group, 4-19, sets out the | |
15213 numerical theory of proportion. 4-10 are preliminary, deal- | |
15214 ing with numbers which are ‘a part’ or ‘parts’ of other num- | |
15215 bers, and numbers which are the same ‘part’ or ‘parts’ of | |
15216 other numbers, just as the preliminary propositions of Book V | |
15217 <pb n=398><head>EUCLID</head> | |
15218 deal with multiples and equimultiples. 11-14 are transforma- | |
15219 tions of proportions corresponding to similar transformations | |
15220 (<I>separando</I>, alternately, &c.) in Book V. The following are | |
15221 the results, expressed with the aid of letters which here repre- | |
15222 sent integral numbers exclusively. | |
15223 <p>If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I> (<I>a</I>><I>c, b</I>><I>d</I>)</MATH>, then | |
15224 <MATH>(<I>a-c</I>):(<I>b-d</I>)=<I>a</I>:<I>b</I></MATH>. (11) | |
15225 <p>If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>a</I>′=<I>b</I>:<I>b</I>′=<I>c</I>:<I>c</I>′...</MATH>, then each of the ratios is equal to | |
15226 <MATH>(<I>a</I>+<I>b</I>+<I>c</I>+...):(<I>a</I>′+<I>b</I>′+<I>c</I>′+...)</MATH>. (12) | |
15227 <p>If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, then <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>b</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>. (13) | |
15228 <p>If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>e</I></MATH> and <MATH><I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, then, <I>ex aequali,</I> | |
15229 <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>d</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>. (14) | |
15230 <p>If 1:<I>m</I>=<I>a</I>:<I>ma</I> (expressed by saying that the third | |
15231 number measures the fourth the same number of times that | |
15232 the unit measures the second), then alternately | |
15233 <MATH>1:<I>a</I>=<I>m</I>:<I>ma.</I></MATH> (15) | |
15234 <p>The last result is used to prove that <I>ab</I>=<I>ba</I>; in other | |
15235 words, that the order of multiplication is indifferent (16), and | |
15236 this is followed by the propositions that <I>b</I>:<I>c</I>=<I>ab</I>:<I>ac</I> (17) | |
15237 and that <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>ac</I>:<I>bc</I></MATH> (18), which are again used to prove | |
15238 the important proposition (19) that, if <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, then | |
15239 <MATH><I>ad</I>=<I>bc</I></MATH>, a theorem which corresponds to VI. 16 for straight | |
15240 lines. | |
15241 <p>Zeuthen observes that, while it was necessary to use the | |
15242 numerical definition of proportion to carry the numerical | |
15243 theory up to this point, Proposition 19 establishes the necessary | |
15244 point of contact between the two theories, since it is now | |
15245 shown that the definition of proportion in V, Def. 5, has, | |
15246 when applied to numbers, the same import as that in VII, | |
15247 Def. 20, and we can henceforth without hesitation borrow any | |
15248 of the propositions established in Book V.<note>Zeuthen, ‘Sur la constitution des livres arithmétiques des Éléments | |
15249 d'Euclide’ (<I>Oversigt over det kgl. Danske Videnskabernes Selskabs Forhand- | |
15250 linger</I>, 1910, pp. 412, 413).</note> | |
15251 <p>Propositions 20, 21 about ‘the least numbers of those which | |
15252 have the same ratio with them’ prove that, if <I>m, n</I> are such | |
15253 numbers and <I>a, b</I> any other numbers in the same ratio, <I>m</I> | |
15254 <pb n=399><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOKS VII-VIII</head> | |
15255 measures <I>a</I> the same number of times that <I>n</I> measures <I>b</I>, and | |
15256 that numbers prime to one another are the least of those which | |
15257 have the same ratio with them. These propositions lead up to | |
15258 Propositions 22-32 about numbers prime to one another, prime | |
15259 numbers, and composite numbers. This group includes funda- | |
15260 mental theorems such as the following. If two numbers be | |
15261 prime to any number, their product will be prime to the same | |
15262 (24). If two numbers be prime to one another, so will their | |
15263 squares, their cubes, and so on generally (27). If two numbers | |
15264 be prime to one another, their sum will be prime to each | |
15265 of them; and, if the sum be prime to either, the original | |
15266 numbers will be prime to one another (28). Any prime number | |
15267 is prime to any number which it does not measure (29). If two | |
15268 numbers are multiplied, and any prime number measures the | |
15269 product, it will measure one of the original numbers (30). | |
15270 Any composite number is measured by some prime number | |
15271 (31). Any number either is prime or is measured by some | |
15272 prime number (32). | |
15273 <p>Propositions 33 to the end (39) are directed to the problem | |
15274 of finding the least common multiple of two or three numbers; | |
15275 33 is preliminary, using the G. C. M. for the purpose of solving | |
15276 the problem, ‘Given as many numbers as we please, to find the | |
15277 least of those which have the same ratio with them.’ | |
15278 <p>It seems clear that in Book VII Euclid was following | |
15279 earlier models, while no doubt making improvements in the | |
15280 exposition. This is, as we have seen (pp. 215-16), partly con- | |
15281 firmed by the fact that in the proof by Archytas of the | |
15282 proposition that ‘no number can be a mean between two | |
15283 consecutive numbers’ propositions are presupposed correspond- | |
15284 ing to VII. 20, 22, 33. | |
15285 <p>Book VIII deals largely with series of numbers ‘in con- | |
15286 tinued proportion’, i.e. in geometrical progression (Propositions | |
15287 1-3, 6-7, 13). If the series in G.P. be | |
15288 <MATH><I>a<SUP>n</SUP>, a<SUP>n-1</SUP>b, a<SUP>n-2</SUP>b<SUP>2</SUP>,... a<SUP>2</SUP>b<SUP>n-2</SUP>, ab<SUP>n-1</SUP>, b<SUP>n</SUP></I></MATH>, | |
15289 Propositions 1-3 deal with the case where the terms are the | |
15290 smallest that are in the ratio <I>a</I>:<I>b</I>, in which case <I>a</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP>, <I>b<SUP>n</SUP></I> are | |
15291 prime to one another. 6-7 prove that, if <I>a<SUP>n</SUP></I> does not measure | |
15292 <I>a</I><SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP><I>b</I>, no term measures any other, but if <I>a<SUP>n</SUP></I> measures <I>b<SUP>n</SUP></I>, | |
15293 it measures <I>a</I><SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP><I>b.</I> Connected with these are Propositions 14-17 | |
15294 <pb n=400><head>EUCLID</head> | |
15295 proving that, according as <I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP> does or does not measure <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>, | |
15296 <I>a</I> does or does not measure <I>b</I> and vice versa; and similarly, | |
15297 according as <I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP> does or does not measure <I>b</I><SUP>3</SUP>, <I>a</I> does or does not | |
15298 measure <I>b</I> and vice versa. 13 proves that, if <I>a, b, c</I> ... are in | |
15299 G. P., so are <I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>, <I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>, <I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP> ... and <I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP>, <I>b</I><SUP>3</SUP>, <I>c</I><SUP>3</SUP> ... respectively. | |
15300 <p>Proposition 4 is the problem, Given as many ratios as we | |
15301 please, <I>a</I>:<I>b, c</I>:<I>d</I> ... to find a series <I>p, q, r,</I> ... in the least | |
15302 possible terms such that <MATH><I>p</I>:<I>q</I>=<I>a</I>:<I>b, q</I>:<I>r</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d,</I></MATH> .... This is | |
15303 done by finding the L. C. M., first of <I>b, c</I>, and then of other | |
15304 pairs of numbers as required. The proposition gives the | |
15305 means of compounding two or more ratios between numbers | |
15306 in the same way that ratios between pairs of straight lines | |
15307 are compounded in VI. 23; the corresponding proposition to | |
15308 VI. 23 then follows (5), namely, that plane numbers have | |
15309 to one another the ratio compounded of the ratios of their | |
15310 sides. | |
15311 <p>Propositions 8-10 deal with the interpolation of geometric | |
15312 means between numbers. If <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>e</I>:<I>f</I></MATH>, and there are <I>n</I> | |
15313 geometric means between <I>a</I> and <I>b</I>, there are <I>n</I> geometric | |
15314 means between <I>e</I> and <I>f</I> also (8). If <I>a</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP>, <I>a</I><SUP><I>n</I>-1</SUP><I>b</I> ... <I>ab<SUP>n</I>-1</SUP>, <I>b<SUP>n</SUP></I> is a | |
15315 G. P. of <I>n</I>+1 terms, so that there are (<I>n</I>-1) means between | |
15316 <I>a<SUP>n</SUP>, b<SUP>n</SUP></I>, there are the same number of geometric means between | |
15317 1 and <I>a<SUP>n</SUP></I> and between 1 and <I>b</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP> respectively (9); and con- | |
15318 versely, if 1, <I>a, a</I><SUP>2</SUP> ... <I>a<SUP>n</SUP></I> and 1, <I>b, b</I><SUP>2</SUP> ... <I>b<SUP>n</SUP></I> are terms in G. P., | |
15319 there are the same number (<I>n</I>-1) of means between <I>a<SUP>n</SUP>, b<SUP>n</SUP></I> (10). | |
15320 In particular, there is one mean proportional number between | |
15321 square numbers (11) and between similar plane numbers (18), | |
15322 and conversely, if there is one mean between two numbers, the | |
15323 numbers are similar plane numbers (20); there are two means | |
15324 between cube numbers (12) and between similar solid numbers | |
15325 (19), and conversely, if there are two means between two num- | |
15326 bers, the numbers are similar solid numbers (21). So far as | |
15327 squares and cubes are concerned, these propositions are stated by | |
15328 Plato in the <I>Timaeus,</I> and Nicomachus, doubtless for this reason, | |
15329 calls them ‘Platonic’. Connected with them are the proposi- | |
15330 tions that similar plane numbers have the same ratio as a square | |
15331 has to a square (26), and similar solid numbers have the same | |
15332 ratio as a cube has to a cube (27). A few other subsidiary | |
15333 propositions need no particular mention. | |
15334 <p>Book IX begins with seven simple propositions such as that | |
15335 <pb n=401><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK IX</head> | |
15336 the product of two similar plane numbers is a square (1) and, | |
15337 if the product of two numbers is a square number, the num- | |
15338 bers are similar plane numbers (2); if a cube multiplies itself | |
15339 or another cube, the product is a cube (3, 4); if <I>a</I><SUP>3</SUP><I>B</I> is a | |
15340 cube, <I>B</I> is a cube (5); if <I>A</I><SUP>2</SUP> is a cube, <I>A</I> is a cube (6). Then | |
15341 follow six propositions (8-13) about a series of terms in geo- | |
15342 metrical progression beginning with 1. If 1, <I>a, b, c ... k</I> are | |
15343 <I>n</I> terms in geometrical progression, then (9), if <I>a</I> is a square | |
15344 (or a cube), all the other terms <I>b, c, ... k</I> are squares (or | |
15345 cubes); if <I>a</I> is not a square, then the only squares in the series | |
15346 are the term after <I>a,</I> i.e. <I>b,</I> and all alternate terms after <I>b;</I> if | |
15347 <I>a</I> is not a cube, the only cubes in the series are the fourth | |
15348 term (<I>c</I>), the seventh, tenth, &c., terms, being terms separated | |
15349 by two throughout; the seventh, thirteenth, &c., terms (leaving | |
15350 out five in each case) will be both square and cube (8, 10). | |
15351 These propositions are followed by the interesting theorem | |
15352 that, if 1, <I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB> ... <I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I> ... are terms in geometrical progression, | |
15353 and if <I>a<SUB>r</SUB>, a<SUB>n</SUB></I> are any two terms where <I>r<n, a<SUB>r</SUB></I> measures <I>a<SUB>n</SUB>,</I> | |
15354 and <MATH><I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>=<I>a</I><SUB><I>r</I></SUB>.<I>a</I><SUB><I>n-r</I></SUB></MATH> (11 and Por.); this is, of course, equivalent | |
15355 to the formula <MATH><I>a</I><SUP><I>m</I>+<I>n</I></SUP>=<I>a</I><SUP><I>m</I></SUP>.<I>a</I><SUP><I>n</I></SUP></MATH>. Next it is proved that, if the | |
15356 last term <I>k</I> in a series 1, <I>a, b, c ... k</I> in geometrical progression | |
15357 is measured by any primes, <I>a</I> is measured by the same (12); | |
15358 and, if <I>a</I> is prime, <I>k</I> will not be measured by any numbers | |
15359 except those which have a place in the series (13). Proposi- | |
15360 tion 14 is the equivalent of the important theorem that <I>a | |
15361 number can only be resolved into prime factors in one way.</I> | |
15362 Propositions follow to the effect that, if <I>a, b</I> be prime to one | |
15363 another, there can be no integral third proportional to them | |
15364 (16) and, if <I>a, b, c ... k</I> be in G.P. and <I>a, k</I> are prime to one | |
15365 another, then there is no integral fourth proportional to <I>a, b, k</I> | |
15366 (17). The conditions for the possibility of an integral third | |
15367 proportional to two numbers and of an integral fourth propor- | |
15368 tional to three are then investigated (18, 19). Proposition 20 | |
15369 is the important proposition that <I>the number of prime numbers | |
15370 is infinite</I>, and the proof is the same as that usually given in | |
15371 our algebraical text-books. After a number of easy proposi- | |
15372 tions about odd, even, ‘even-times-odd’, ‘even-times-even’ | |
15373 numbers respectively (Propositions 21-34), we have two im- | |
15374 portant propositions which conclude the Book. Proposition 35 | |
15375 gives the summation of a G.P. of <I>n</I> terms, and a very elegant | |
15376 <pb n=402><head>EUCLID</head> | |
15377 solution it is. Suppose that <I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>, <I>a</I><SUB>3</SUB>, ... <I>a<SUB>n</I>+1</SUB> are <I>n</I>+1 terms | |
15378 in G. P.; Euclid proceeds thus: | |
15379 <p>We have <MATH><I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>+1</SUB>/<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I>=<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I>/<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>=...=<I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>/<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB></MATH>, | |
15380 and, <I>separando</I>, <MATH><I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>+1</SUB>-<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I>/<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I>=<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I>-<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>/<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>=...=<I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>-<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>/<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB></MATH> | |
15381 <p>Adding antecedents and consequents, we have (VII. 12) | |
15382 <MATH><I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>+1</SUB>-<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>/<I>a<SUB>n</SUB></I>+<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>+...+<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>=<I>a</I><SUB>2</SUB>-<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB>/<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB></MATH>, | |
15383 which gives <MATH><I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>+<I>a</I><SUB><I>n</I>-1</SUB>+... +<I>a</I><SUB>1</SUB></MATH> or <I>S</I><SUB><I>n</I></SUB>. | |
15384 <p>The last proposition (36) gives the criterion for <I>perfect | |
15385 numbers</I>, namely that, if, the sum of any number of terms of | |
15386 the series 1, 2, 2<SUP>2</SUP> ... 2<SUP><I>n</I></SUP> is prime, the product of the said sum | |
15387 and of the last term, viz. (1+2+2<SUP>2</SUP>+...+2<SUP><I>n</I></SUP>) 2<SUP><I>n</I></SUP>, is a perfect | |
15388 number, i.e. is equal to the sum of all its factors. | |
15389 <p>It should be added, as regards all the arithmetical Books, | |
15390 that all numbers are represented in the diagrams as simple | |
15391 straight lines, whether they are linear, plane, solid, or any | |
15392 other kinds of numbers; thus a product of two or more factors | |
15393 is represented as a new straight line, not as a rectangle or a | |
15394 solid. | |
15395 <p>Book X is perhaps the most remarkable, as it is the most | |
15396 perfect in form, of all the Books of the <I>Elements.</I> It deals | |
15397 with irrationals, that is to say, irrational straight lines in rela- | |
15398 tion to any particular straight line assumed as rational, and | |
15399 it investigates every possible variety of straight lines which | |
15400 can be represented by √(√<I>a</I>±√<I>b</I>), where <I>a, b</I> are two com- | |
15401 mensurable lines. The theory was, of course, not invented by | |
15402 Euclid himself. On the contrary, we know that not only the | |
15403 fundamental proposition X. 9 (in which it is proved that | |
15404 squares which have not to one another the ratio of a square | |
15405 number to a square number have their sides incommen- | |
15406 surable in length, and conversely), but also a large part of | |
15407 the further development of the subject, was due to Theae- | |
15408 tetus. Our authorities for this are a scholium to X. 9 and a | |
15409 passage from Pappus's commentary on Book X preserved | |
15410 in the Arabic (see pp. 154-5, 209-10, above). The passage | |
15411 <pb n=403><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOKS IX-X</head> | |
15412 of Pappus goes on to speak of the share of Euclid in the | |
15413 investigation: | |
15414 <p>‘As for Euclid, he set himself to give rigorous rules, which he | |
15415 established, relative to commensurability and incommensura- | |
15416 bility in general; he made precise the definitions and the | |
15417 distinctions between rational and irrational magnitudes, he set | |
15418 out a great number of orders of irrational magnitudes, and | |
15419 finally he made clear their whole extent.’ | |
15420 <p>As usual, Euclid begins with definitions. ‘Commensurable’ | |
15421 magnitudes can be measured by one and the same measure; | |
15422 ‘incommensurable’ magnitudes cannot have any common | |
15423 measure (1). Straight lines are ‘commensurable in square’ | |
15424 when the squares on them can be measured by the same area, | |
15425 but ‘incommensurable in square’ when the squares on them | |
15426 have no common measure (2). Given an assigned straight | |
15427 line, which we agree to call ‘rational’, any straight line which | |
15428 is commensurable with it either in length or in square only is | |
15429 also called rational; but any straight line which is incommen- | |
15430 surable with it (i.e. not commensurable with it either in length | |
15431 or in square) is ‘irrational’ (3). The square on the assigned | |
15432 straight line is ‘rational’, and any area commensurable with | |
15433 it is ‘rational’, but any area incommensurable with it is | |
15434 ‘irrational’, as also is the side of the square equal to that | |
15435 area (4). As regards straight lines, then, Euclid here takes | |
15436 a wider view of ‘rational’ than we have met before. If a | |
15437 straight line <G>r</G> is assumed as rational, not only is (<I>m/n</I>)<G>r</G> also | |
15438 ‘rational’ where <I>m, n</I> are integers and <I>m/n</I> in its lowest terms | |
15439 is not square, but any straight line is rational which is either | |
15440 commensurable in length or commensurable <I>in square only</I> | |
15441 with <G>r</G>; that is, <MATH>√(<I>m/n</I>).<G>r</G></MATH> is rational according to Euclid. In | |
15442 the case of squares, <G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP> is of course rational, and so is <MATH>(<I>m/n</I>)<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>; but | |
15443 <MATH>√(<I>m/n</I>).<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> is not rational, and of course the side of the latter | |
15444 square <MATH>√<SUP>4</SUP>(<I>m/n</I>).<G>r</G></MATH> is irrational, as are all straight lines commen- | |
15445 surable neither in length nor in square with <G>r</G>, e. g. <MATH>√<I>a</I>±√<I>b</I></MATH> | |
15446 or (<MATH>√<I>k</I>±√<G>l</G>).<G>r</G></MATH>. | |
15447 <pb n=404> | |
15448 <head>EUCLID</head> | |
15449 <p>The Book begins with the famous proposition, on which the | |
15450 ‘method of exhaustion’ as used in Book XII depends, to the | |
15451 effect that, if from any magnitude there be subtracted more | |
15452 than its half (or its half simply), from the remainder more than | |
15453 its half (or its half), and so on continually, there will at length | |
15454 remain a magnitude less than any assigned magnitude of the | |
15455 same kind. Proposition 2 uses the process for finding the | |
15456 G. C. M. of two magnitudes as a test of their commensurability | |
15457 or incommensurability: they are incommensurable if the process | |
15458 never comes to an end, i.e. if no remainder ever measures the | |
15459 preceding divisor; and Propositions 3, 4 apply to commen- | |
15460 surable magnitudes the method of finding the G. C. M. of two | |
15461 or three <I>numbers</I> as employed in VII. 2, 3. Propositions 5 | |
15462 to 8 show that two magnitudes are commensurable or incom- | |
15463 mensurable according as they have or have not to one another | |
15464 the ratio of one number to another, and lead up to the funda- | |
15465 mental proposition (9) of Theaetetus already quoted, namely | |
15466 that the sides of squares are commensurable or incommen- | |
15467 surable in length according as the squares have or have not to | |
15468 one another the ratio of a square number to a square number, | |
15469 and conversely. Propositions 11-16 are easy inferences as to | |
15470 the commensurability or incommensurability of magnitudes | |
15471 from the known relations of others connected with them; | |
15472 e.g. Proposition 14 proves that, if <MATH><I>a</I>:<I>b</I>=<I>c</I>:<I>d</I></MATH>, then, according | |
15473 as <MATH>√(<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> is commensurable or incommensurable with <I>a</I>, | |
15474 <MATH>√(<I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> is commensurable or incommensurable with <I>c.</I> | |
15475 Following on this, Propositions 17, 18 prove that the roots of | |
15476 the quadratic equation <MATH><I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>/4</MATH> are commensurable or | |
15477 incommensurable with <I>a</I> according as <MATH>√(<I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> is commen- | |
15478 surable or incommensurable with <I>a.</I> Propositions 19-21 deal | |
15479 with rational and irrational <I>rectangles</I>, the former being | |
15480 contained by straight lines commensurable in length, whereas | |
15481 rectangles contained by straight lines commensurable in square | |
15482 only are irrational. The side of a square equal to a rectangle | |
15483 of the latter kind is called <I>medial</I>; this is the first in Euclid's | |
15484 classification of irrationals. As the sides of the rectangle may | |
15485 be expressed as <G>r</G>, <G>r</G>√<I>k</I>, where <G>r</G> is a rational straight line, | |
15486 the <I>medial</I> is <I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r</G>. Propositions 23-8 relate to medial straight | |
15487 lines and rectangles; two medial straight lines may be either | |
15488 commensurable in length or commensurable in square only: | |
15489 <pb n=405> | |
15490 <head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK X</head> | |
15491 thus <I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r</G> and <G>l</G><I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r</G> are commensurable in length, while <I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r</G> | |
15492 and √<G>l</G>.<I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r</G> are commensurable in square only: the rectangles | |
15493 formed by such pairs are in general <I>medial</I>, as <G>l</G><I>k</I><SUP>1/2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP> and | |
15494 √<G>l</G>.<I>k</I><SUP>1/2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>; but if <MATH>√<G>l</G>=<I>k</I>′√<I>k</I></MATH> in the second case, the rectangle | |
15495 (<I>k′k</I><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>) is rational (Propositions 24, 25). Proposition 26 proves | |
15496 that the difference between two medial areas cannot be | |
15497 rational; as any two medial areas can be expressed in the | |
15498 form √<I>k</I>.<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>, √<G>l</G>.<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>, this is equivalent to proving, as we do in | |
15499 algebra, that (√<I>k</I>-√<G>l</G>) cannot be equal to <I>k</I>′. Finally, | |
15500 Propositions 27, 28 find medial straight lines commensurable | |
15501 in square only (1) which contain a rational rectangle, viz. <I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r</G>, | |
15502 <I>k</I><SUP>3/4</SUP><G>r</G>, and (2) which contain a medial rectangle, viz.<I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r,l</G><SUP>1/2</SUP><G>r</G>/<I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP>. It | |
15503 should be observed that, as <G>r</G> may take either of the forms <I>a</I> | |
15504 or √<I>A</I>, a medial straight line may take the alternative forms | |
15505 √(<I>a</I>√<I>B</I>) or √<SUP>4</SUP>(<I>AB</I>), and the pairs of medial straight lines just | |
15506 mentioned may take respectively the forms | |
15507 (1) <MATH>√(<I>a</I>√<I>B</I>), √(<I>B</I>√<I>B</I>/<I>a</I>)</MATH> or <MATH>√<SUP>4</SUP>(<I>AB</I>), √(<I>B</I>(√<I>B</I>/√<I>A</I>))</MATH> | |
15508 and (2) <MATH>√(<I>a</I>√<I>B</I>), √(<I>aC</I>/√<I>B</I>)</MATH> or <MATH>√<SUP>4</SUP>(<I>AB</I>), √(<I>C</I>√<I>A</I>/√<I>B</I>)</MATH> | |
15509 I shall henceforth omit reference to these obvious alternative | |
15510 forms. Next follow two lemmas the object of which is to find | |
15511 (1) two square numbers the sum of which is a square, Euclid's | |
15512 solution being | |
15513 <MATH><I>mnp</I><SUP>2</SUP>.<I>mnq</I><SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>mnp</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>mnq</I><SUP>2</SUP>/2)<SUP>2</SUP>=(<I>mnp</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>mnq</I><SUP>2</SUP>/2)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
15514 where <I>mnp</I><SUP>2</SUP>, <I>mnq</I><SUP>2</SUP> are either both odd or both even, and | |
15515 (2) two square numbers the sum of which is not square, | |
15516 Euclid's solution being | |
15517 <MATH><I>mp</I><SUP>2</SUP>.<I>mq</I><SUP>2</SUP>, ((<I>mp</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>mq</I><SUP>2</SUP>/2)-1)<SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
15518 Propositions 29-35 are problems the object of which is to find | |
15519 (<I>a</I>) two rational straight lines commensurable in square only, | |
15520 (<I>b</I>) two medial straight lines commensurable in square only, | |
15521 (<I>c</I>) two straight lines incommensurable in square, such that | |
15522 the difference or sum of their squares and the rectangle | |
15523 <pb n=406> | |
15524 <head>EUCLID</head> | |
15525 contained by them respectively have certain characteristics. | |
15526 The solutions are | |
15527 <p>(<I>a</I>) <I>x, y</I> rational and commensurable in square only. | |
15528 <p>Prop. 29: <MATH><G>r, r</G>√(1-<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>) [√(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> commensurable with <I>x</I>]. | |
15529 ” 30: <MATH><G>r, r</G>/√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>) [√(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> incommensurable with <I>x</I>]. | |
15530 <p>(<I>b</I>) <I>x, y</I> medial and commensurable in square only. | |
15531 <p>Prop. 31: <MATH><G>r</G>(1-<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)<SUP>1/4</SUP>, <G>r</G>(1-<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)<SUP>3/4</SUP> [<I>xy</I> rational, √(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> commen- | |
15532 surable with <I>x</I>]; | |
15533 <MATH><G>r</G>/(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)<SUP>1/4</SUP>, <G>r</G>/(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)<SUP>3/4</SUP> [<I>xy</I> rational, √(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> incom- | |
15534 mensurable with <I>x</I>]. | |
15535 ” 32: <MATH><G>rl</G><SUP>1/4</SUP>, <G>rl</G><SUP>1/4</SUP>√(1-<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>) [<I>xy</I> medial, √(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> commensur- | |
15536 able with <I>x</I>]; | |
15537 <MATH><G>rl</G><SUP>1/4</SUP>, <G>rl</G><SUP>1/4</SUP>/√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>) [<I>xy</I> medial, √(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> incommen- | |
15538 surable with <I>x</I>]. | |
15539 <p>(<I>c</I>) <I>x, y</I> incommensurable in square. | |
15540 <p>Prop. 33: <MATH><G>r</G>/√2√(1+<I>k</I>/√1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>), <G>r</G>/√2√(1 - <I>k</I>/√1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>) | |
15541 [(<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> rational, <I>xy</I> medial]. | |
15542 ” 34: <MATH><G>r</G>/√{2(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)}.√{√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)+<I>k</I>}, | |
15543 <G>r</G>/√{2(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)}.√{√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)-<I>k</I>} | |
15544 [<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> medial, <I>xy</I> rational]. | |
15545 ” 35: <MATH><G>rl</G><SUP>1/4</SUP>/√2√{1 + <I>k</I>/√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)}, <G>rl</G><SUP>1/4</SUP>/√2√{1 - <I>k</I>/√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)} | |
15546 [<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>y</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> and <I>xy</I> both medial and | |
15547 incommensurable with one another]. | |
15548 With Proposition 36 begins Euclid's exposition of the several | |
15549 compound irrationals, twelve in number Those which only | |
15550 differ in the sign separating the two component parts can be | |
15551 <pb n=407> | |
15552 <head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK X</head> | |
15553 taken together. The twelve compound irrationals, with their | |
15554 names, are as follows: | |
15555 <MATH> | |
15556 <BRACE> | |
15557 <note>(<I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB>) (<I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15558 Binomial, <G>r</G> + √<I>k</I>.<G>r</G> (Prop. 36) | |
15559 Apotome, <G>r</G> - √<I>k</I>.<G>r</G> (Prop. 73) | |
15560 </BRACE> | |
15561 <BRACE> | |
15562 <note>(<I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB>) (<I>B</I><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15563 <note><I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r</G> ± <I>k</I><SUP>3/4</SUP><G>r</G> (Props. 37, 74)</note> | |
15564 First bimedial | |
15565 First apotome of a medial | |
15566 </BRACE> | |
15567 <BRACE> | |
15568 <note>(<I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB>) (<I>C</I><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15569 <note><I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r</G> ± <G>l</G><SUP>1/2</SUP><G>r</G>/<I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP> (Props. 38, 75)</note> | |
15570 Second bimedial | |
15571 Second apotome of a medial | |
15572 </BRACE> | |
15573 <BRACE> | |
15574 <note>(<I>D</I><SUB>1</SUB>) (<I>D</I><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15575 <note><G>r</G>/√2√(1 + <I>k</I>/√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)) ± <G>r</G>/√2√(1 - <I>k</I>/√(1 + <I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)) (Props. 39, 76)</note> | |
15576 Major | |
15577 Minor | |
15578 </BRACE> | |
15579 <BRACE> | |
15580 <note>(<I>E</I><SUB>1</SUB>) (<I>E</I><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15581 <note><G>r</G>/√2(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)√(√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>) + <I>k</I>) ± <G>r</G>/√2(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)√(√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)-<I>k</I>) (Props. 40, 77)</note> | |
15582 Side of a rational plus a medial area | |
15583 That which ‘produces’ with a rational area a medial whole | |
15584 </BRACE> | |
15585 <BRACE> | |
15586 <note>(<I>F</I><SUB>1</SUB>) (<I>F</I><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15587 <note><G>rl</G><SUP>1/4</SUP>/√2√(1 + <I>k</I>/√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)) ± <G>rl</G><SUP>1/4</SUP>/√2√(1 - <I>k</I>/√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)) (Props. 41, 78).</note> | |
15588 Side of the sum of two medial areas | |
15589 That which ‘produces’ with a medial area a medial whole | |
15590 </BRACE> | |
15591 </MATH> | |
15592 <p>As regards the above twelve compound irrationals, it is | |
15593 to be noted that | |
15594 <p><I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB> are the positive roots of the equation | |
15595 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>4</SUP>-2(1+<I>k</I>)<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>.<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+(1-<I>k</I>)<SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>4</SUP>=0</MATH>; | |
15596 <p><I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>B</I><SUB>2</SUB> are the positive roots of the equation | |
15597 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>4</SUP>-2√<I>k</I>(1+<I>k</I>)<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>.<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>k</I>(1-<I>k</I>)<SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>4</SUP>=0</MATH>; | |
15598 <p><I>C</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>C</I><SUB>2</SUB> are the positive roots of the equation | |
15599 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>4</SUP>-2<I>k</I>+<G>l</G>/√<I>k</I><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>.<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+(<I>k</I>-<G>l</G>)<SUP>2</SUP>/<I>k</I><G>r</G><SUP>4</SUP>=0</MATH>; | |
15600 <pb n=408> | |
15601 <head>EUCLID</head> | |
15602 <p><I>D</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>D</I><SUB>2</SUB> are the positive roots of the equation | |
15603 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>4</SUP>-2<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>.<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>/1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>4</SUP>=0</MATH>; | |
15604 <p><I>E</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>E</I><SUB>2</SUB> are the positive roots of the equation | |
15605 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>4</SUP>-2/√(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>.<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>/(1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>)<SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>4</SUP>=0</MATH>; | |
15606 <p><I>F</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>F</I><SUB>2</SUB> are the positive roots of the equation | |
15607 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>4</SUP>-2√<G>l</G>.<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>+<G>l</G><I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP>/1+<I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>4</SUP>=0</MATH>. | |
15608 <p>Propositions 42-7 prove that each of the above straight lines, | |
15609 made up of the <I>sum</I> of two terms, is divisible into its terms | |
15610 in only one way. In particular, Proposition 42 proves the | |
15611 equivalent of the well-known theorem in algebra that, | |
15612 if <MATH><I>a</I>+√<I>b</I>=<I>x</I>+√<I>y</I></MATH>, then <MATH><I>a</I>=<I>x</I>, <I>b</I>=<I>y</I></MATH>; | |
15613 and if <MATH>√<I>a</I>+√<I>b</I>=√<I>x</I>+√<I>y</I></MATH>, | |
15614 then <MATH><I>a</I>=<I>x</I>, <I>b</I>=<I>y</I> (or <I>a</I>=<I>y</I>, <I>b</I>=<I>x</I>)</MATH>. | |
15615 <p>Propositions 79-84 prove corresponding facts in regard to | |
15616 the corresponding irrationals with the negative sign between | |
15617 the terms: in particular Proposition 79 shows that, | |
15618 if <MATH><I>a</I>-√<I>b</I>=<I>x</I>-√<I>y</I></MATH>, then <MATH><I>a</I>=<I>x</I>, <I>b</I>=<I>y</I></MATH>; | |
15619 and if <MATH>√<I>a</I>-√<I>b</I>=√<I>x</I>-√<I>y</I></MATH>, then <MATH><I>a</I>=<I>x</I>, <I>b</I>=<I>y</I></MATH>. | |
15620 <p>The next sections of the Book deal with binomials and | |
15621 apotomes classified according to the relation of their terms to | |
15622 another given rational straight line. There are six kinds, | |
15623 which are first defined and then constructed, as follows: | |
15624 <MATH> | |
15625 <BRACE> | |
15626 <note>(<G>a</G><SUB>1</SUB>) (<G>a</G><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15627 <note><I>k</I><G>r</G>±<I>k</I><G>r</G>√(1-<G>l</G><SUP>2</SUP>); (Props. 48, 85)</note> | |
15628 First binomial | |
15629 First apotome | |
15630 </BRACE> | |
15631 <BRACE> | |
15632 <note>(<G>b</G><SUB>1</SUB>) (<G>b</G><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15633 <note><I>k</I><G>r</G>/√(1-<G>l</G><SUP>2</SUP>) ± <I>k</I><G>r</G>; (Props. 49, 86)</note> | |
15634 Second binomial | |
15635 Second apotome | |
15636 </BRACE> | |
15637 <BRACE> | |
15638 <note>(<G>g</G><SUB>1</SUB>) (<G>g</G><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15639 <note><I>m</I>√<I>k</I>.<G>r</G> ± <I>m</I>√<I>k</I>.<G>r</G>√(1-<G>l</G><SUP>2</SUP>); (Props. 50, 87)</note> | |
15640 Third binomial | |
15641 Third apotome | |
15642 </BRACE> | |
15643 </MATH> | |
15644 <pb n=409> | |
15645 <head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK X</head> | |
15646 <MATH> | |
15647 <BRACE> | |
15648 <note>(<G>d</G><SUB>1</SUB>) (<G>d</G><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15649 <note><I>k</I><G>r</G> ± <I>k</I><G>r</G>/√(1+<G>l</G>); (Props. 51, 88)</note> | |
15650 Fourth binomial | |
15651 Fourth apotome | |
15652 </BRACE> | |
15653 <BRACE> | |
15654 <note>(<G>e</G><SUB>1</SUB>) (<G>e</G><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15655 <note><I>k</I><G>r</G>√(1+<G>l</G>) ± <I>k</I><G>r</G>; (Props. 52, 89)</note> | |
15656 Fifth binomial | |
15657 Fifth apotome | |
15658 </BRACE> | |
15659 <BRACE> | |
15660 <note>(<G>z</G><SUB>1</SUB>) (<G>z</G><SUB>2</SUB>)</note> | |
15661 <note>√<I>k</I>.<G>r</G> ± √<G>l.r</G> (Prop. 53, 90)</note> | |
15662 Sixth binomial | |
15663 Sixth apotome | |
15664 </BRACE> | |
15665 </MATH> | |
15666 <p>Here again it is to be observed that these binomials and | |
15667 apotomes are the greater and lesser roots respectively of | |
15668 certain quadratic equations, | |
15669 <p><G>a</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>a</G><SUB>2</SUB> being the roots of <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>k</I><G>r</G>.<I>x</I>+<G>l</G><SUP>2</SUP><I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>=0</MATH>, | |
15670 <p><G>b</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>b</G><SUB>2</SUB> ” ” <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>- 2<I>k</I><G>r</G>/√(1-<G>l</G><SUP>2</SUP>).<I>x</I> + <G>l</G><SUP>2</SUP>/1-<G>l</G><SUP>2</SUP><I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>=0</MATH>, | |
15671 <p><G>g</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>g</G><SUB>2</SUB> ” ” <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>m</I>√<I>k</I>.<G>r</G><I>x</I>+<G>l</G><SUP>2</SUP><I>m</I><SUP>2</SUP><I>k</I><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>=0</MATH>, | |
15672 <p><G>d</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>d</G><SUB>2</SUB> ” ” <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>k</I><G>r</G>.<I>x</I> + <G>l</G>/1+<G>l</G><I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>=0</MATH>, | |
15673 <p><G>e</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>e</G><SUB>2</SUB> ” ” <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-2<I>k</I><G>r</G>√(1+<G>l</G>).<I>x</I>+<G>l</G><I>k</I><SUP>2</SUP><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>=0</MATH>, | |
15674 <p><G>z</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>z</G><SUB>2</SUB> ” ” <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>-2√<I>k</I>.<G>r</G><I>x</I>+(<I>k</I>-<G>l</G>)<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>=0</MATH>. | |
15675 <p>The next sets of propositions (54-65 and 91-102) prove the | |
15676 connexion between the first set of irrationals (<I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB> ... <I>F</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>F</I><SUB>2</SUB>) | |
15677 and the second set (<G>a</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>a</G><SUB>2</SUB> ... <G>z</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>z</G><SUB>2</SUB>) respectively. It is shown | |
15678 e.g., in Proposition 54, that the side of a square equal to the | |
15679 rectangle contained by <G>r</G> and the first binomial <G>a</G><SUB>1</SUB> is a binomial | |
15680 of the type <I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB>, and the same thing is proved in Proposition 91 | |
15681 for the first apotome. In fact | |
15682 <MATH>√{<G>r</G>(<I>k</I><G>r</G> ± <I>k</I><G>r</G>√1-<G>l</G><SUP>2</SUP>)}=<G>r</G>√{1/2<I>k</I>(1+<G>l</G>)} ± <G>r</G>√{1/2<I>k</I>(1-<G>l</G>)}</MATH>. | |
15683 Similarly √(<G>rb</G><SUB>1</SUB>), √(<G>rb</G><SUB>2</SUB>) are irrationals of the type <I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>B</I><SUB>2</SUB> | |
15684 respectively, and so on. | |
15685 <p>Conversely, the square on <I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB> or <I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB>, if applied as a rectangle | |
15686 to a rational straight line (<G>s</G>, say), has for its breadth a binomial | |
15687 or apotome of the types <G>a</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>a</G><SUB>2</SUB> respectively (60, 97). | |
15688 <p>In fact <MATH>(<G>r</G>±√<I>k</I>.<G>r</G>)<SUP>2</SUP>/<G>s</G>=<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>/<G>s</G> {(1+<I>k</I>) ± 2√<I>k</I>}</MATH>, | |
15689 and <I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB><SUP>2</SUP>, <I>B</I><SUB>2</SUB><SUP>2</SUP> are similarly related to irrationals of the type | |
15690 <G>b</G><SUB>1</SUB>, <G>b</G><SUB>2</SUB>, and so on. | |
15691 <pb n=410> | |
15692 <head>EUCLID</head> | |
15693 <p>Propositions 66-70 and Propositions 103-7 prove that | |
15694 straight lines commensurable in length with <I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB> ... <I>F</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>F</I><SUB>2</SUB> | |
15695 respectively are irrationals of the same type and order. | |
15696 <p>Propositions 71, 72, 108-10 show that the irrationals | |
15697 <I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB> ... <I>F</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>F</I><SUB>2</SUB> arise severally as the sides of squares equal | |
15698 to the sum or difference of a rational and a medial area, or the | |
15699 sum or difference of two medial areas incommensurable with | |
15700 one another. Thus <I>k</I><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP> ± √<G>l.r</G><SUP>2</SUP> is the sum or difference of a | |
15701 rational and a medial area, √<I>k</I>.<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP> ± √<G>l</G>.<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP> is the sum or | |
15702 difference of two medial areas incommensurable with one | |
15703 another provided that √<I>k</I> and √<G>l</G> are incommensurable, and | |
15704 the propositions prove that | |
15705 <MATH>√(<I>k</I><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP> ± √<G>l</G>.<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>) and √(√<I>k</I>.<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP> ± √<G>l</G>.<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH> | |
15706 take one or other of the forms <I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB> ... <I>F</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>F</I><SUB>2</SUB> according to | |
15707 the different possible relations between <I>k</I>, <G>l</G> and the sign | |
15708 separating the two terms, but no other forms. | |
15709 <p>Finally, it is proved at the end of Proposition 72, in Proposi- | |
15710 tion 111 and the explanation following it that the thirteen | |
15711 irrational straight lines, the medial and the twelve other | |
15712 irrationals <I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB> ... <I>F</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>F</I><SUB>2</SUB>, are all different from one another. | |
15713 E.g. (Proposition 111) a binomial straight line cannot also be | |
15714 an apotome; in other words, √<I>x</I>+√<I>y</I> cannot be equal to | |
15715 √<I>x</I>′ - √.<I>y</I>′, and <I>x</I>+√<I>y</I> cannot be equal to <I>x</I>′ - √<I>y</I>′. We | |
15716 prove the latter proposition by squaring, and Euclid's proce- | |
15717 dure corresponds exactly to this. Propositions 112-14 prove | |
15718 that, if a rectangle equal to the square on a rational straight | |
15719 line be applied to a binomial, the other side containing it is an | |
15720 apotome of the same order, with terms commensurable with | |
15721 those of the binomial and in the same ratio, and vice versa; | |
15722 also that a binomial and apotome of the same order and with | |
15723 terms commensurable respectively contain a rational rectangle. | |
15724 Here we have the equivalent of rationalizing the denominators | |
15725 of the fractions <MATH><I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>/√<I>A</I> ± √<I>B</I></MATH> or <MATH><I>c</I><SUP>2</SUP>/<I>a</I> ± √<I>B</I></MATH> by multiplying the | |
15726 numerator and denominator by <MATH>√<I>A</I> ∓ √<I>B</I></MATH> or <MATH><I>a</I> ∓ √<I>B</I></MATH> respec- | |
15727 tively. Euclid in fact proves that | |
15728 <MATH><G>s</G><SUP>2</SUP>/(<G>r</G>+√<I>k</I>.<G>r</G>)=<G>lr</G> - √<I>k</I>.<G>lr</G> (<I>k</I>∠1)</MATH>, | |
15729 and his method enables us to see that <MATH><G>l</G>=<G>s</G><SUP>2</SUP>/(<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>-<I>k</I><G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>. | |
15730 Proposition 115 proves that from a medial straight line an | |
15731 <pb n=411> | |
15732 <head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK X</head> | |
15733 infinite number of other irrational straight lines arise each | |
15734 of which is different from the preceding. <I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>r</G> being medial, | |
15735 we take another rational straight line <G>s</G> and find the mean | |
15736 proportional √(<I>k</I><SUP>1/4</SUP><G>rs</G>); this is a new irrational. Take the | |
15737 mean between this and <G>s</G>′, and so on. | |
15738 <p>I have described the contents of Book X at length because | |
15739 it is probably not well known to mathematicians, while it is | |
15740 geometrically very remarkable and very finished. As regards | |
15741 its object Zeuthen has a remark which, I think, must come | |
15742 very near the truth. ‘Since such roots of equations of the | |
15743 second degree as are incommensurable with the given magni- | |
15744 tudes cannot be expressed by means of the latter and of num- | |
15745 bers, it is conceivable that the Greeks, in exact investigations, | |
15746 introduced no approximate values, but worked on with the | |
15747 magnitudes they had found, which were represented by | |
15748 straight lines obtained by the construction corresponding to | |
15749 the solution of the equation. That is exactly the same thing | |
15750 which happens when we do not evaluate roots but content | |
15751 ourselves with expressing them by radical signs and other | |
15752 algebraical symbols. But, inasmuch as one straight line looks | |
15753 like another, the Greeks did not get the same clear view of | |
15754 what they denoted (i.e. by simple inspection) as our system | |
15755 of symbols assures to us. For this reason then it was neces- | |
15756 sary to undertake a classification of the irrational magnitudes | |
15757 which had been arrived at by successive solutions of equations | |
15758 of the second degree.’ That is, Book X formed a repository | |
15759 of results to which could be referred problems depending on | |
15760 the solution of certain types of equations, quadratic and | |
15761 biquadratic but reducible to quadratics, namely the equations | |
15762 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP> ± 2<G>m</G><I>x</I>.<G>r</G> ± <G>n.r</G><SUP>2</SUP>=0</MATH>, | |
15763 and <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>4</SUP> ± 2<G>m</G><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>.<G>r</G><SUP>2</SUP> ± <G>n</G>.<G>r</G><SUP>4</SUP>=0</MATH>, | |
15764 where <G>r</G> is a rational straight line and <G>m, n</G> are coefficients. | |
15765 According to the values of <G>m, n</G> in relation to one another and | |
15766 their character (<G>m</G>, but not <G>n</G>, may contain a surd such as | |
15767 √<I>m</I> or √(<I>m</I>/<I>n</I>)) the two positive roots of the first equations are | |
15768 the binomial and apotome respectively of some one of the | |
15769 orders ‘first’, ‘second’, . . . ‘sixth’, while the two positive | |
15770 roots of the latter equation are of some one of the other forms | |
15771 of irrationals (<I>A</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>A</I><SUB>2</SUB>), (<I>B</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>B</I><SUB>2</SUB>) ... (<I>F</I><SUB>1</SUB>, <I>F</I><SUB>2</SUB>). | |
15772 <pb n=412> | |
15773 <head>EUCLID</head> | |
15774 <p>Euclid himself, in Book XIII, makes considerable use of the | |
15775 second part of Book X dealing with <I>apotomes</I>; he regards a | |
15776 straight line as sufficiently defined in character if he can say | |
15777 that it is, e.g., an <I>apotome</I> (XIII. 17), a <I>first apotome</I> (XIII. 6), | |
15778 a <I>minor</I> straight line (XIII. 11). So does Pappus.<note>Cf. Pappus, iv, pp. 178, 182.</note> | |
15779 <p>Our description of Books XI-XIII can be shorter. They | |
15780 deal with geometry in three dimensions. The definitions, | |
15781 belonging to all three Books, come at the beginning of Book XI. | |
15782 They include those of a straight line, or a plane, at right angles | |
15783 to a plane, the inclination of a plane to a plane (dihedral angle), | |
15784 parallel planes, equal and similar solid figures, solid angle, | |
15785 pyramid, prism, sphere, cone, cylinder and parts of them, cube, | |
15786 octahedron, icosahedron and dodecahedron. Only the defini- | |
15787 tion of the sphere needs special mention. Whereas it had | |
15788 previously been defined as the figure which has all points of | |
15789 its surface equidistant from its centre, Euclid, with an eye to | |
15790 his use of it in Book XIII to ‘comprehend’ the regular solids | |
15791 in a sphere, defines it as the figure comprehended by the revo- | |
15792 lution of a semicircle about its diameter. | |
15793 <p>The propositions of Book XI are in their order fairly | |
15794 parallel to those of Books I and VI on plane geometry. First | |
15795 we have propositions that a straight line is wholly in a plane | |
15796 if a portion of it is in the plane (1), and that two intersecting | |
15797 straight lines, and a triangle, are in one plane (2). Two | |
15798 intersecting planes cut in a straight line (3). Straight lines | |
15799 perpendicular to planes are next dealt with (4-6, 8, 11-14), | |
15800 then parallel straight lines not all in the same plane (9, 10, 15), | |
15801 parallel planes (14, 16), planes at right angles to one another | |
15802 (18, 19), solid angles contained by three angles (20, 22, 23, 26) | |
15803 or by more angles (21). The rest of the Book deals mainly | |
15804 with parallelepipedal solids. It is only necessary to mention | |
15805 the more important propositions. Parallelepipedal solids on the | |
15806 same base or equal bases and between the same parallel planes | |
15807 (i.e. having the same height) are equal (29-31). Parallele- | |
15808 pipedal solids of the same height are to one another as their | |
15809 bases (32). Similar parallelepipedal solids are in the tripli- | |
15810 cate ratio of corresponding sides (33). In equal parallele- | |
15811 pipedal solids the bases are reciprocally proportional to their | |
15812 heights and conversely (34). If four straight lines be propor- | |
15813 <pb n=413> | |
15814 <head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOKS XI-XII</head> | |
15815 tional, so are parallelepipedal solids similar and similarly | |
15816 described upon them, and conversely (37). A few other | |
15817 propositions are only inserted because they are required as | |
15818 lemmas in later books, e.g. that, if a cube is bisected by two | |
15819 planes each of which is parallel to a pair of opposite faces, the | |
15820 common section of the two planes and the diameter of the | |
15821 cube bisect one another (38). | |
15822 <p>The main feature of Book XII is the application of the | |
15823 <I>method of exhaustion</I>, which is used to prove successively that | |
15824 circles are to one another as the squares on their diameters | |
15825 (Propositions 1, 2), that pyramids of the same height and with | |
15826 triangular bases are to one another as the bases (3-5), that | |
15827 any cone is, in content, one third part of the cylinder which | |
15828 has the same base with it and equal height (10), that cones | |
15829 and cylinders of the same height are to one another as their | |
15830 bases (11), that similar cones and cylinders are to one another | |
15831 in the triplicate ratio of the diameters of their bases (12), and | |
15832 finally that spheres are to one another in the triplicate ratio | |
15833 of their respective diameters (16-18). Propositions 1, 3-4 and | |
15834 16-17 are of course preliminary to the main propositions 2, 5 | |
15835 and 18 respectively. Proposition 5 is extended to pyramids | |
15836 with polygonal bases in Proposition 6. Proposition 7 proves | |
15837 that any prism with triangular bases is divided into three | |
15838 pyramids with triangular bases and equal in content, whence | |
15839 any pyramid with triangular base (and therefore also any | |
15840 pyramid with polygonal base) is equal to one third part of | |
15841 the prism having the same base and equal height. The rest | |
15842 of the Book consists of propositions about pyramids, cones, | |
15843 and cylinders similar to those in Book XI about parallele- | |
15844 pipeds and in Book VI about parallelograms: similar pyra- | |
15845 mids with triangular bases, and therefore also similar pyramids | |
15846 with polygonal bases, are in the triplicate ratio of correspond- | |
15847 ing sides (8); in equal pyramids, cones and cylinders the bases | |
15848 are reciprocally proportional to the heights, and conversely | |
15849 (9, 15). | |
15850 <p>The method of exhaustion, as applied in Euclid, rests upon | |
15851 X. 1 as lemma, and no doubt it will be desirable to insert here | |
15852 an example of its use. An interesting case is that relating to | |
15853 the pyramid. Pyramids with triangular bases and of the same | |
15854 height, says Euclid, are to one another as their bases (Prop. 5). | |
15855 <pb n=414> | |
15856 <head>EUCLID</head> | |
15857 It is first proved (Proposition 3) that, given any pyramid, as | |
15858 <I>ABCD</I>, on the base <I>BCD</I>, if we bisect the six edges at the | |
15859 <FIG> | |
15860 points <I>E, F, G, H, K, L</I>, and draw the straight lines shown in | |
15861 the figure, we divide the pyramid <I>ABCD</I> into two equal | |
15862 prisms and two equal pyramids <I>AFGE, FBHK</I> similar to the | |
15863 original pyramid (the equality of the prisms is proved in | |
15864 XI. 39), and that the sum of the two prisms is greater than | |
15865 half the original pyramid. Proposition 4 proves that, if each | |
15866 of two given pyramids of the same height be so divided, and | |
15867 if the small pyramids in each are similarly divided, then the | |
15868 smaller pyramids left over from that division are similarly | |
15869 divided, and so on to any extent, the sums of all the pairs of | |
15870 prisms in the two given pyramids respectively will be to one | |
15871 another as the respective bases. Let the two pyramids and | |
15872 their volumes be denoted by <I>P</I>, <I>P</I>′ respectively, and their bases | |
15873 by <I>B</I>, <I>B</I>′ respectively. Then, if <I>B</I>:<I>B</I>′ is not equal to <I>P</I>:<I>P</I>′, it | |
15874 must be equal to <I>P</I>:<I>W</I>, where <I>W</I> is some volume either less or | |
15875 greater than <I>P</I>′. | |
15876 <p>I. Suppose <I>W</I> < <I>P</I>′. | |
15877 <p>By X. 1 we can divide <I>P</I>′ and the successive pyramids in | |
15878 it into prisms and pyramids until the sum of the small | |
15879 pyramids left over in it is less that <I>P</I>′ - <I>W</I>, so that | |
15880 <MATH><I>P</I>′ > (prisms in <I>P</I>′) > <I>W</I></MATH>. | |
15881 <p>Suppose this done, and <I>P</I> divided similarly. | |
15882 <p>Then (XII. 4) | |
15883 <MATH>(sum of prisms in <I>P</I>):(sum of prisms in <I>P</I>′)=<I>B</I>:<I>B</I>′ | |
15884 =<I>P</I>:<I>W</I></MATH>, by hypothesis. | |
15885 <p>But <MATH><I>P</I> > (sum of prisms in <I>P</I>)</MATH>: | |
15886 therefore <MATH><I>W</I> > (sum of prisms in <I>P</I>′)</MATH>. | |
15887 <pb n=415> | |
15888 <head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOKS XII-XIII</head> | |
15889 <p>But <I>W</I> is also less than the sum of the prisms in <I>P</I>′: which | |
15890 is impossible. | |
15891 <p>Therefore <I>W</I> is <I>not</I> less than <I>P</I>′. | |
15892 <p>II. Suppose <I>W</I> > <I>P</I>′. | |
15893 <p>We have, inversely, | |
15894 <MATH><I>B</I>′:<I>B</I>=<I>W</I>:<I>P</I> | |
15895 = <I>P</I>′:<I>V</I></MATH>, where <I>V</I> is some solid less than <I>P.</I> | |
15896 <p>But this can be proved impossible, exactly as in Part I. | |
15897 Therefore <I>W</I> is neither greater nor less than <I>P</I>′, so that | |
15898 <MATH><I>B</I>:<I>B</I>′=<I>P</I>:<I>P</I>′</MATH>. | |
15899 <p>We shall see, when we come to Archimedes, that he extended | |
15900 this method of exhaustion. Instead of merely taking the one | |
15901 approximation, from underneath as it were, by constructing | |
15902 successive figures <I>within</I> the figure to be measured and so | |
15903 exhausting it, he combines with this an approximation from | |
15904 <I>outside.</I> He takes sets both of inscribed and circumscribed | |
15905 figures, approaching from both sides the figure to be measured, | |
15906 and, as it were, <I>compresses</I> them into one, so that they coincide | |
15907 as nearly as we please with one another and with the curvi- | |
15908 linear figure itself. The two parts of the proof are accordingly | |
15909 separate in Archimedes, and the second is not merely a reduction | |
15910 to the first. | |
15911 <p>The object of Book XIII is to construct, and to ‘comprehend | |
15912 in a sphere’, each of the five regular solids, the pyramid | |
15913 (Prop. 13), the octahedron (Prop. 14), the cube (Prop. 15), | |
15914 the icosahedron (Prop. 16) and the dodecahedron (Prop. 17); | |
15915 ‘comprehending in a sphere’ means the construction of the | |
15916 circumscribing sphere, which involves the determination of | |
15917 the relation of a ‘side’ (i.e. edge) of the solid to the radius | |
15918 of the sphere; in the case of the first three solids the relation | |
15919 is actually determined, while in the case of the icosahedron | |
15920 the side of the figure is shown to be the irrational straight | |
15921 line called ‘minor’, and in the case of the dodecahedron an | |
15922 ‘apotome’. The propositions at the beginning of the Book | |
15923 are preliminary. Propositions 1-6 are theorems about straight | |
15924 lines cut in extreme and mean ratio, Propositions 7, 8 relate | |
15925 to pentagons, and Proposition 8 proves that, if, in a regular | |
15926 pentagon, two diagonals (straight lines joining angular points | |
15927 <pb n=416> | |
15928 <head>EUCLID</head> | |
15929 next but one to each other) are drawn intersecting at a point, | |
15930 each of them is divided at the point in extreme and mean | |
15931 ratio, the greater segment being equal to the side of the pen- | |
15932 tagon. Propositions 9 and 10 relate to the sides of a pentagon, | |
15933 a decagon and a hexagon all inscribed in the same circle, | |
15934 and are preliminary to proving (in Prop. 11) that the side of | |
15935 the inscribed pentagon is, in relation to the diameter of the | |
15936 circle, regarded as rational, the irrational straight line called | |
15937 ‘minor’. If <I>p, d, h</I> be the sides of the regular pentagon, | |
15938 decagon, and hexagon inscribed in the same circle, Proposition 9 | |
15939 proves that <I>h</I> + <I>d</I> is cut in extreme and mean ratio, <I>h</I> being the | |
15940 greater segment; this is equivalent to saying that <MATH>(<I>r</I> + <I>d</I>)<I>d</I>=<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
15941 where <I>r</I> is the radius of the circle, or, in other words, that | |
15942 <MATH><I>d</I>=1/2<I>r</I>(√5-1)</MATH>. Proposition 10 proves that <MATH><I>p</I><SUP>2</SUP> = <I>h</I><SUP>2</SUP> + <I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> or | |
15943 <I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP> + <I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP>, whence we obtain <MATH><I>p</I>=1/2<I>r</I>√(10-2√5)</MATH>. Expressed as | |
15944 a ‘minor’ irrational straight line, which Proposition 11 shows | |
15945 it to be, <MATH><I>p</I>=1/2<I>r</I>√(5+2√5)-1/2<I>r</I>√(5-2√5)</MATH>. | |
15946 <p>The constructions for the several solids, which have to be | |
15947 inscribed in a given sphere, may be briefly indicated, thus: | |
15948 <p>1. The regular pyramid or <I>tetrahedron</I>. | |
15949 <p>Given <I>D</I>, the diameter of the sphere which is to circum- | |
15950 scribe the tetrahedron, Euclid draws a circle with radius <I>r</I> | |
15951 such that <MATH><I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>=1/3<I>D</I>.2/3<I>D</I></MATH>, or <MATH><I>r</I>=1/3√2.<I>D</I></MATH>, inscribes an equi- | |
15952 lateral triangle in the circle, and then erects from the centre | |
15953 of it a straight line perpendicular to its plane and of length | |
15954 2/3<I>D</I>. The lines joining the extremity of the perpendicular to | |
15955 the angular points of the equilateral triangle determine the | |
15956 tetrahedron. Each of the upstanding edges (<I>x</I>, say) is such | |
15957 that <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>+4/9<I>D</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, and it has been proved (in XIII. 12) | |
15958 that the square on the side of the triangle inscribed in the | |
15959 circle is also 3<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>. Therefore the edge <I>a</I> of the tetrahedron | |
15960 =√3.<I>r</I> = 1/3√6.<I>D.</I> | |
15961 <p>2. The <I>octahedron.</I> | |
15962 <p>If <I>D</I> be the diameter of the circumscribing sphere, a square | |
15963 is inscribed in a circle of diameter <I>D</I>, and from its centre | |
15964 straight lines are drawn in both directions perpendicular to | |
15965 its plane and of length equal to the radius of the circle or half | |
15966 the diagonal of the square. Each of the edges which stand up | |
15967 from the square=√2.1/2<I>D</I>, which is equal to the side of the | |
15968 <pb n=417> | |
15969 <head>THE <I>ELEMENTS</I>. BOOK XIII</head> | |
15970 square. Each of the edges <I>a</I> of the octahedron is therefore | |
15971 equal to √2.1/2<I>D.</I> | |
15972 <p>3. The <I>cube.</I> | |
15973 <p><I>D</I> being the diameter of the circumscribing sphere, draw | |
15974 a square with side <I>a</I> such that <MATH><I>a</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>D</I>.1/3<I>D</I></MATH>, and describe a cube | |
15975 on this square as base. The edge <MATH><I>a</I>=1/3√3.<I>D</I></MATH>. | |
15976 <p>4. The <I>icosahedron.</I> | |
15977 <p>Given <I>D</I>, the diameter of the sphere, construct a circle with | |
15978 radius <I>r</I> such that <MATH><I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>D</I>.1/5<I>D</I></MATH>. Inscribe in it a regular | |
15979 decagon. Draw from its angular points straight lines perpen- | |
15980 dicular to the plane of the circle and equal in length to its | |
15981 radius <I>r</I>; this determines the angular points of a regular | |
15982 decagon inscribed in an equal parallel circle. By joining | |
15983 alternate angular points of one of the decagons, describe a | |
15984 regular pentagon in the circle circumscribing it, and then do | |
15985 the same in the other circle but so that the angular points are | |
15986 not opposite those of the other pentagon. Join the angular | |
15987 points of one pentagon to the nearest angular points of the | |
15988 other; this gives ten triangles. Then, if <I>p</I> be the side of each | |
15989 pentagon, <I>d</I> the side of each decagon, the upstanding sides | |
15990 of the triangles (=<I>x</I>, say) are given by <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>p</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> | |
15991 (Prop. 10); therefore the ten triangles are equilateral. We | |
15992 have lastly to find the common vertices of the five equilateral | |
15993 triangles standing on the pentagons and completing the icosa- | |
15994 hedron. If <I>C</I>, <I>C</I>′ be the centres of the parallel circles, <I>CC</I>′ is | |
15995 produced in both directions to <I>X, Z</I> respectively so that | |
15996 <I>CX</I>=<I>C′Z</I>=<I>d</I> (the side of the decagon). Then again the | |
15997 upstanding edges connecting to <I>X, Z</I> the angular points of the | |
15998 two pentagons respectively (=<I>x</I>, say) are given by | |
15999 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>r</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>d</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>p</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
16000 <p>Hence each of the edges | |
16001 <MATH><I>a</I>=<I>p</I>=1/2<I>r</I>√(10-2√5)=<I>D</I>/2√5√(10-2√5) | |
16002 =(1/10)<I>D</I>√{10(5-√5)}</MATH>. | |
16003 It is finally shown that the sphere described on <I>XZ</I> as | |
16004 diameter circumscribes the icosahedron, and | |
16005 <MATH><I>XZ</I>=<I>r</I>+2<I>d</I>=<I>r</I>+<I>r</I>(√5-1)=<I>r</I>.√5=<I>D</I></MATH>. | |
16006 <pb n=418> | |
16007 <head>EUCLID</head> | |
16008 <p>5. The <I>dodecahedron</I>. | |
16009 <p>We start with the cube inscribed in the given sphere with | |
16010 diameter <I>D</I>. We then draw pentagons which have the edges | |
16011 of the cube as diagonals in the manner shown in the figure. | |
16012 If <I>H, N, M, O</I> be the middle points of the sides of the face | |
16013 <I>BF</I>, and <I>H, G, L, K</I> the middle points of the sides of the | |
16014 face <I>BD</I>, join <I>NO, GK</I> which are then parallel to <I>BC</I>, and | |
16015 draw <I>MH, HL</I> bisecting them at right angles at <I>P, Q</I>. | |
16016 <p>Divide <I>PN, PO, QH</I> in extreme and mean ratio at <I>R, S, T</I>, | |
16017 and let <I>PR, PS, QT</I> be the greater segments. Draw <I>RU, PX, | |
16018 SV</I> at right angles to the plane <I>BF</I>, and <I>TW</I> at right angles to | |
16019 <FIG> | |
16020 the plane <I>BD</I>, such that each of these perpendiculars =<I>PR</I> | |
16021 or <I>PS</I>. Join <I>UV, VC, CW, WB, BU</I>. These determine one | |
16022 of the pentagonal faces, and the others are drawn similarly. | |
16023 <p>It is then proved that each of the pentagons, as <I>UVCWB</I>, | |
16024 is (1) equilateral, (2) in the same plane, (3) equiangular. | |
16025 <p>As regards the sides we see, e. g., that | |
16026 <MATH><I>BU</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BR</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>RU</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>BN</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>NR</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>RP</I><SUP>2</SUP> | |
16027 =<I>PN</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>NR</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>RP</I><SUP>2</SUP>=4<I>RP</I><SUP>2</SUP> (by means of XIII. 4) = <I>UV</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, | |
16028 and so on. | |
16029 <pb n=419><head>THE <I>ELEMENTS.</I> BOOK XIII</head> | |
16030 <p>Lastly, it is proved that the same sphere of diameter <I>D</I> | |
16031 which circumscribes the cube also circumscribes the dodeca- | |
16032 hedron. For example, if <I>Z</I> is the centre of the sphere, | |
16033 <MATH><I>ZU</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>ZX</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>XU</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>NS</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>PS</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3<I>PN</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>, (XIII. 4) | |
16034 while <MATH><I>ZB</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3<I>ZP</I><SUP>2</SUP>=3<I>PN</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
16035 <p>If <I>a</I> be the edge of the dodecahedron, <I>c</I> the edge of the cube, | |
16036 <MATH><I>a</I>=2<I>RP</I>=2.(√5-1)/4 <I>c</I> | |
16037 =(2√3)/3.(√5-1)/4 <I>D</I> | |
16038 =1/6 <I>D</I> (√15-√3)</MATH>. | |
16039 <p>Book XIII ends with Proposition 18, which arranges the | |
16040 edges of the five regular solids inscribed in one and the same | |
16041 sphere in order of magnitude, while an addendum proves that | |
16042 no other regular solid figures except the five exist. | |
16043 <C>The so-called Books XIV, XV.</C> | |
16044 <p>This is no doubt the place to speak of the continuations | |
16045 of Book XIII which used to be known as Books XIV, XV of | |
16046 the <I>Elements</I>, though they are not by Euclid. The former | |
16047 is the work of Hypsicles, who probably lived in the second | |
16048 half of the second century B.C., and who is otherwise known | |
16049 as the reputed author of an astronomical tract <G>)*anaforiko/s</G> | |
16050 (<I>De ascensionibus</I>) still extant (the earliest extant Greek book | |
16051 in which the division of the circle into 360 degrees appears), | |
16052 besides other works, which have not survived, on the harmony | |
16053 of the spheres and on polygonal numbers. The preface to | |
16054 ‘Book XIV’ is interesting historically. It appears from | |
16055 it that Apollonius wrote a tract on the comparison of the | |
16056 dodecahedron and icosahedron inscribed in one and the same | |
16057 sphere, i.e. on the ratio between them, and that there were two | |
16058 editions of this work, the first of which was in some way | |
16059 incorrect, while the second gave a correct proof of the pro- | |
16060 position that, as the surface of the dodecahedron is to | |
16061 the surface of the icosahedron, so is the solid content of the | |
16062 <pb n=420><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16063 dodecahedron to that of the icosahedron, ‘because the per- | |
16064 pendicular from the centre of the sphere to the pentagon of | |
16065 the dodecahedron and to the triangle of the icosahedron is the | |
16066 same’. Hypsicles says also that Aristaeus, in a work entitled | |
16067 <I>Comparison of the five figures</I>, proved that ‘the same circle | |
16068 circumscribes both the pentagon of the dodecahedron and the | |
16069 triangle of the icosahedron inscribed in the same sphere’; | |
16070 whether this Aristaeus is the same as the Aristaeus of the | |
16071 <I>Solid Loci</I>, the elder contemporary of Euclid, we do not | |
16072 know. The proposition of Aristaeus is proved by Hypsicles | |
16073 as Proposition 2 of his book. The following is a summary | |
16074 of the results obtained by Hypsicles. In a lemma at the end | |
16075 he proves that, if two straight lines be cut in extreme and | |
16076 mean ratio, the segments of both are in one and the same | |
16077 ratio; the ratio is in fact <MATH>2:(√5-1)</MATH>. If then <I>any</I> straight | |
16078 line <I>AB</I> be divided at <I>C</I> in extreme and mean ratio, <I>AC</I> being | |
16079 the greater segment, Hypsicles proves that, if we have a cube, | |
16080 a dodecahedron and an icosahedron all inscribed in the same | |
16081 sphere, then: | |
16082 <MATH>(Prop. 7) (side of cube):(side of icosahedron) | |
16083 =√(<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>):√(<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>BC</I><SUP>2</SUP>); | |
16084 (Prop. 6) (surface of dodecahedron):(surface of icosahedron) | |
16085 =(side of cube):(side of icosahedron); | |
16086 (Prop. 8) (content of dodecahedron):(content of icosahedron) | |
16087 =(surface of dodecahedron):(surface of icosahedron); | |
16088 and consequently | |
16089 (content of dodecahedron):(content of icosahedron) | |
16090 =√(<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>AC</I><SUP>2</SUP>):√(<I>AB</I><SUP>2</SUP>+<I>BC</I><SUP>2</SUP>)</MATH>. | |
16091 <p>The second of the two supplementary Books (‘Book XV’) is | |
16092 also concerned with the regular solids, but is much inferior to | |
16093 the first. The exposition leaves much to be desired, being | |
16094 in some places obscure, in others actually inaccurate. The | |
16095 Book is in three parts unequal in length. The first<note>Heiberg's Euclid, vol. v, pp. 40-8.</note> shows | |
16096 how to inscribe certain of the regular solids in certain others, | |
16097 <pb n=421><head>THE SO-CALLED BOOKS XIV, XV</head> | |
16098 (<I>a</I>) a tetrahedron in a cube, (<I>b</I>) an octahedron in a tetrahedron, | |
16099 (<I>c</I>) an octahedron in a cube, (<I>d</I>) a cube in an octahedron, | |
16100 (<I>e</I>) a dodecahedron in an icosahedron. The second portion<note>Heiberg's Euclid, vol. v. pp. 48-50.</note> | |
16101 explains how to calculate the number of edges and the number | |
16102 of solid angles in the five solids respectively. The third | |
16103 portion<note><I>Ib.</I>, pp. 50-66.</note> shows how to determine the dihedral angles between | |
16104 the faces meeting in any edge of any one of the solids. The | |
16105 method is to construct an isosceles triangle with vertical angle | |
16106 equal to the said angle; from the middle point of any edge | |
16107 two perpendiculars are drawn to it, one in each of the two | |
16108 faces intersecting in that edge; these perpendiculars (forming | |
16109 the dihedral angle) are used to determine the two equal sides | |
16110 of an isosceles triangle, and the base of the triangle is easily | |
16111 found from the known properties of the particular solid. The | |
16112 rules for drawing the respective isosceles triangles are first | |
16113 given all together in general terms; and the special interest | |
16114 of the passage consists in the fact that the rules are attributed | |
16115 to ‘Isidorus our great teacher’. This Isidorus is doubtless | |
16116 Isidorus of Miletus, the architect of the church of Saint Sophia | |
16117 at Constantinople (about A.D. 532). Hence the third portion | |
16118 of the Book at all events was written by a pupil of Isidorus | |
16119 in the sixth century. | |
16120 <C>The <I>Data.</I></C> | |
16121 <p>Coming now to the other works of Euclid, we will begin | |
16122 with those which have actually survived. Most closely con- | |
16123 nected with the <I>Elements</I> as dealing with plane geometry, the | |
16124 subject-matter of Books I-VI, is the <I>Data</I>, which is accessible | |
16125 in the Heiberg-Menge edition of the Greek text, and also | |
16126 in the translation annexed by Simson to his edition of the | |
16127 <I>Elements</I> (although this translation is based on an inferior | |
16128 text). The book was regarded as important enough to be | |
16129 included in the <I>Treasury of Analysis</I> (<G>to/pos a)naluo/menos</G>) as | |
16130 known to Pappus, and Pappus gives a description of it; the | |
16131 description shows that there were differences between Pappus's | |
16132 text and ours, for, though Propositions 1-62 correspond to the | |
16133 description, as also do Propositions 87-94 relating to circles | |
16134 at the end of the book, the intervening propositions do not | |
16135 <pb n=422><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16136 exactly agree, the differences, however, affecting the distribu- | |
16137 tion and numbering of the propositions rather than their | |
16138 substance. The book begins with definitions of the senses | |
16139 in which things are said to be <I>given.</I> Things such as areas, | |
16140 straight lines, angles and ratios are said to be ‘given in | |
16141 <I>magnitude</I> when we can make others equal to them’ (Defs. | |
16142 1-2). Rectilineal figures are ‘given <I>in species</I>’ when their | |
16143 angles are severally given as well as the ratios of the sides to | |
16144 one another (Def. 3). Points, lines and angles are ‘given | |
16145 <I>in position</I>’ ‘when they always occupy the same place’: a not | |
16146 very illuminating definition (4). A circle is given <I>in position | |
16147 and in magnitude</I> when the centre is given <I>in position</I> and | |
16148 the radius <I>in magnitude</I> (6); and so on. The object of the | |
16149 proposition called a Datum is to prove that, if in a given figure | |
16150 certain parts or relations are given, other parts or relations are | |
16151 also given, in one or other of these senses. | |
16152 <p>It is clear that a systematic collection of <I>Data</I> such as | |
16153 Euclid's would very much facilitate and shorten the procedure | |
16154 in <I>analysis</I>; this no doubt accounts for its inclusion in the | |
16155 <I>Treasury of Analysis.</I> It is to be observed that this form of | |
16156 proposition does not actually determine the thing or relation | |
16157 which is shown to be given, but merely proves that it can be | |
16158 determined when once the facts stated in the hypothesis | |
16159 are known; if the proposition stated that a certain thing <I>is</I> | |
16160 so and so, e.g. that a certain straight line in the figure is of | |
16161 a certain length, it would be a theorem; if it directed us to | |
16162 <I>find</I> the thing instead of proving that it is ‘given’, it would | |
16163 be a problem; hence many propositions of the form of the | |
16164 <I>Data</I> could alternatively be stated in the form of theorems or | |
16165 problems. | |
16166 <p>We should naturally expect much of the subject-matter of | |
16167 the <I>Elements</I> to appear again in the <I>Data</I> under the different | |
16168 aspect proper to that book; and this proves to be the case. | |
16169 We have already mentioned the connexion of Eucl. II. 5, 6 | |
16170 with the solution of the mixed quadratic equations <MATH><I>ax</I>±<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH>. | |
16171 The solution of these equations is equivalent to the solution of | |
16172 the simultaneous equations | |
16173 <MATH> | |
16174 <BRACE><I>y</I>±<I>x</I>=<I>a</I> | |
16175 <I>xy</I>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></BRACE> | |
16176 </MATH> | |
16177 and Euclid shows how to solve these equations in Propositions | |
16178 <pb n=423><head>THE <I>DATA</I></head> | |
16179 84, 85 of the <I>Data</I>, which state that ‘If two straight lines | |
16180 contain a given area in a given angle, and if the difference | |
16181 (sum) of them be given, then shall each of them be given.’ | |
16182 The proofs depend directly upon those of Propositions 58, 59, | |
16183 ‘If a given area be applied to a given straight line, falling | |
16184 short (exceeding) by a figure given in species, the breadths | |
16185 of the deficiency (excess) are given.’ All the ‘areas’ are | |
16186 parallelograms. | |
16187 <p>We will give the proof of Proposition 59 (the case of | |
16188 ‘excess’). Let the given area <I>AB</I> | |
16189 <FIG> | |
16190 be applied to <I>AC</I>, exceeding by the | |
16191 figure <I>CB</I> given in species. I say | |
16192 that each of the sides <I>HC, CE</I> is | |
16193 given. | |
16194 <p>Bisect <I>DE</I> in <I>F</I>, and construct | |
16195 on <I>EF</I> the figure <I>FG</I> similar and | |
16196 similarly situated to <I>CB</I> (VI. 18). | |
16197 Therefore <I>FG, CB</I> are about the same diagonal (VI. 26). | |
16198 Complete the figure. | |
16199 <p>Then <I>FG</I>, being similar to <I>CB</I>, is given in species, and, | |
16200 since <I>FE</I> is given, <I>FG</I> is given in magnitude (Prop. 52). | |
16201 <p>But <I>AB</I> is given; therefore <MATH><I>AB</I>+<I>FG</I></MATH>, that is to say, <I>KL</I>, is | |
16202 given in magnitude. But it is also given in species, being | |
16203 similar to <I>CB</I>; therefore the sides of <I>KL</I> are given (Prop. 55). | |
16204 <p>Therefore <I>KH</I> is given, and, since <MATH><I>KC</I>=<I>EF</I></MATH> is also given, | |
16205 the difference <I>CH</I> is given. And <I>CH</I> has a given ratio to <I>HB</I>; | |
16206 therefore <I>HB</I> is also given (Prop. 2). | |
16207 <p>Eucl. III. 35, 36 about the ‘power’ of a point with reference | |
16208 to a circle have their equivalent in <I>Data</I> 91, 92 to the effect | |
16209 that, given a circle and a point in the same plane, the rectangle | |
16210 contained by the intercepts between this point and the points | |
16211 in which respectively the circumference is cut by any straight | |
16212 line passing through the point and meeting the circle is | |
16213 also given. | |
16214 <p>A few more enunciations may be quoted. Proposition 8 | |
16215 (compound ratio): Magnitudes which have given ratios to the | |
16216 same magnitude have a given ratio to one another also. | |
16217 Propositions 45, 46 (similar triangles): If a triangle have one | |
16218 angle given, and the ratio of the sum of the sides containing | |
16219 that angle, or another angle, to the third side (in each case) be | |
16220 <pb n=424><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16221 given, the triangle is given in species. Proposition 52: If a | |
16222 (rectilineal) figure given in species be described on a straight | |
16223 line given in magnitude, the figure is given in magnitude. | |
16224 Proposition 66: If a triangle have one angle given, the rect- | |
16225 angle contained by the sides including the angle has to the | |
16226 (area of the) triangle a given ratio. Proposition 80: If a | |
16227 triangle have one angle given, and if the rectangle contained | |
16228 by the sides including the given angle have to the square on | |
16229 the third side a given ratio, the triangle is given in species. | |
16230 <p>Proposition 93 is interesting: If in a circle given in magni- | |
16231 tude a straight line be drawn cutting off a segment containing | |
16232 a given angle, and if this angle be bisected (by a straight line | |
16233 cutting the base of the segment and the circumference beyond | |
16234 it), the sum of the sides including the given angle will have a | |
16235 given ratio to the chord bisecting the angle, and the rectangle | |
16236 contained by the sum of the said sides and the portion of the | |
16237 bisector cut off (outside the segment) towards the circum- | |
16238 ference will also be given. | |
16239 <p>Euclid's proof is as follows. In the circle <I>ABC</I> let the | |
16240 chord <I>BC</I> cut off a segment containing a given angle <I>BAC</I>, | |
16241 and let the angle be bisected by <I>AE</I> meeting <I>BC</I> in <I>D.</I> | |
16242 <p>Join <I>BE.</I> Then, since the circle is given in magnitude, and | |
16243 <FIG> | |
16244 <I>BC</I> cuts off a segment containing a given | |
16245 angle, <I>BC</I> is given (Prop. 87). | |
16246 <p>Similarly <I>BE</I> is given; therefore the | |
16247 ratio <I>BC</I>:<I>BE</I> is given. (It is easy to | |
16248 see that the ratio <I>BC</I>:<I>BE</I> is equal to | |
16249 2 cos 1/2 <I>A.</I>) | |
16250 <p>Now, since the angle <I>BAC</I> is bisected, | |
16251 <MATH><I>BA</I>:<I>AC</I>=<I>BD</I>:<I>DC</I></MATH>. | |
16252 <p>It follows that <MATH>(<I>BA</I>+<I>AC</I>):(<I>BD</I>+<I>DC</I>)=<I>AC</I>:<I>DC</I></MATH>. | |
16253 <p>But the triangles <I>ABE, ADC</I> are similar; | |
16254 therefore <MATH><I>AE</I>:<I>BE</I>=<I>AC</I>:<I>DC</I> | |
16255 =(<I>BA</I>+<I>AC</I>):<I>BC</I></MATH>, from above. | |
16256 <p>Therefore <MATH>(<I>BA</I>+<I>AC</I>):<I>AE</I>=<I>BC</I>:<I>BE</I></MATH>, which is a given | |
16257 ratio. | |
16258 <pb n=425><head>THE <I>DATA</I></head> | |
16259 <p>Again, since the triangles <I>ADC, BDE</I> are similar, | |
16260 <MATH><I>BE</I>:<I>ED</I>=<I>AC</I>:<I>CD</I>=(<I>BA</I>+<I>AC</I>):<I>BC</I></MATH>. | |
16261 <p>Therefore <MATH>(<I>BA</I>+<I>AC</I>).<I>ED</I>=<I>BC.BE</I></MATH>, which is given. | |
16262 <C>On divisions (of figures).</C> | |
16263 <p>The only other work of Euclid in pure geometry which has | |
16264 survived (but not in Greek) is the book <I>On divisions</I> (<I>of | |
16265 figures</I>), <G>peri\ diaire/sewn bibli/on</G>. It is mentioned by Proclus, | |
16266 who gives some hints as to its content<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 144. 22-6.</note>; he speaks of the | |
16267 business of the author being divisions of figures, circles or | |
16268 rectilineal figures, and remarks that the parts may be like | |
16269 in definition or notion, or unlike; thus to divide a triangle | |
16270 into triangles is to divide it into like figures, whereas to | |
16271 divide it into a triangle and a quadrilateral is to divide it into | |
16272 unlike figures. These hints enable us to check to some extent | |
16273 the genuineness of the books dealing with divisions of figures | |
16274 which have come down through the Arabic. It was John Dee | |
16275 who first brought to light a treatise <I>De divisionibus</I> by one | |
16276 Muhammad Bagdadinus (died 1141) and handed over a copy | |
16277 of it (in Latin) to Commandinus in 1563; it was published by | |
16278 the latter in Dee's name and his own in 1570. Dee appears | |
16279 not to have translated the book from the Arabic himself, but | |
16280 to have made a copy for Commandinus from a manuscript of | |
16281 a Latin translation which he himself possessed at one time but | |
16282 which was apparently stolen and probably destroyed some | |
16283 twenty years after the copy was made. The copy does not | |
16284 seem to have been made from the Cotton MS. which passed to | |
16285 the British Museum after it had been almost destroyed by | |
16286 a fire in 1731.<note>The question is fully discussed by R. C. Archibald, <I>Euclid's Book on | |
16287 Divisions of Figures with a restoration based on Woepcke's text and on the | |
16288 Practica Geometriae of Leonardo Pisano</I> (Cambridge 1915).</note> The Latin translation may have been that | |
16289 made by Gherard of Cremona (1114-87), since in the list of | |
16290 his numerous translations a ‘liber divisionum’ occurs. But | |
16291 the Arabic original cannot have been a direct translation from | |
16292 Euclid, and probably was not even a direct adaptation of it, | |
16293 since it contains mistakes and unmathematical expressions; | |
16294 moreover, as it does not contain the propositions about the | |
16295 <pb n=426><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16296 division of a circle alluded to by Proclus, it can scarcely have | |
16297 contained more than a fragment of Euclid's original work. | |
16298 But Woepcke found in a manuscript at Paris a treatise in | |
16299 Arabic on the division of figures, which he translated and | |
16300 published in 1851. It is expressly attributed to Euclid in the | |
16301 manuscript and corresponds to the indications of the content | |
16302 given by Proclus. Here we find divisions of different recti- | |
16303 linear figures into figures of the same kind, e.g. of triangles | |
16304 into triangles or trapezia into trapezia, and also divisions into | |
16305 ‘unlike’ figures, e.g. that of a triangle by a straight line parallel | |
16306 to the base. The missing propositions about the division of | |
16307 a circle are also here: ‘to divide into two equal parts a given | |
16308 figure bounded by an arc of a circle and two straight lines | |
16309 including a given angle’ (28), and ‘to draw in a given circle | |
16310 two parallel straight lines cutting off a certain fraction from | |
16311 the circle’ (29). Unfortunately the proofs are given of only | |
16312 four propositions out of 36, namely Propositions 19, 20, 28, 29, | |
16313 the Arabic translator having found the rest too easy and | |
16314 omitted them. But the genuineness of the treatise edited by | |
16315 Woepcke is attested by the facts that the four proofs which | |
16316 remain are elegant and depend on propositions in the | |
16317 <I>Elements</I>, and that there is a lemma with a true Greek ring, | |
16318 ‘to apply to a straight line a rectangle equal to the rectangle | |
16319 contained by <I>AB, AC</I> and deficient by a square’ (18). Moreover, | |
16320 the treatise is no fragment, but ends with the words, ‘end of | |
16321 the treatise’, and is (but for the missing proofs) a well-ordered | |
16322 and compact whole. Hence we may safely conclude that | |
16323 Woepcke's tract represents not only Euclid's work but the | |
16324 whole of it. The portion of the <I>Practica geometriae</I> of | |
16325 Leonardo of Pisa which deals with the division of figures | |
16326 seems to be a restoration and extension of Euclid's work; | |
16327 Leonardo must presumably have come across a version of it | |
16328 from the Arabic. | |
16329 <p>The type of problem which Euclid's treatise was designed | |
16330 to solve may be stated in general terms as that of dividing a | |
16331 given figure by one or more straight lines into parts having | |
16332 prescribed ratios to one another or to other given areas. The | |
16333 figures divided are the triangle, the parallelogram, the trape- | |
16334 zium, the quadrilateral, a figure bounded by an arc of a circle | |
16335 and two straight lines, and the circle. The figures are divided | |
16336 <pb n=427><head>ON DIVISIONS OF FIGURES</head> | |
16337 into two equal parts, or two parts in a given ratio; or again, | |
16338 a given fraction of the figure is to be cut off, or the figure is | |
16339 to be divided into several parts in given ratios. The dividing | |
16340 straight lines may be transversals drawn through a point | |
16341 situated at a vertex of the figure, or a point on any side, on one | |
16342 of two parallel sides, in the interior of the figure, outside the | |
16343 figure, and so on; or again, they may be merely parallel lines, | |
16344 or lines parallel to a base. The treatise also includes auxiliary | |
16345 propositions, (1) ‘to apply to a given straight line a rectangle | |
16346 equal to a given area and deficient by a square’, the proposi- | |
16347 tion already mentioned, which is equivalent to the algebraical | |
16348 solution of the equation <MATH><I>ax</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>b</I><SUP>2</SUP></MATH> and depends on Eucl. II. 5 | |
16349 (cf. p. 152 above); (2) propositions in proportion involving | |
16350 unequal instead of equal ratios: | |
16351 <MATH>If <I>a.d</I>>or<<I>b.c</I>, then <I>a</I>:<I>b</I>>or<<I>c</I>:<I>d</I> respectively. | |
16352 If <I>a</I>:<I>b</I>><I>c</I>:<I>d</I>, then (<I>a</I>∓<I>b</I>:<I>b</I>>(<I>c</I>∓<I>d</I>):<I>d</I>. | |
16353 If <I>a</I>:<I>b</I><<I>c</I>:<I>d</I>, then (<I>a</I>-<I>b</I>):<I>b</I><(<I>c</I>-<I>d</I>):<I>d</I></MATH>. | |
16354 <p>By way of illustration I will set out shortly three proposi- | |
16355 tions from the Woepcke text. | |
16356 <p>(1) Propositions 19, 20 (slightly generalized): To cut off | |
16357 a certain fraction (<I>m</I>/<I>n</I>) from a given triangle by a straight | |
16358 <FIG> | |
16359 line drawn through a given point within the triangle (Euclid | |
16360 gives two cases corresponding to <MATH><I>m</I>/<I>n</I>=1/2</MATH> and <MATH><I>m</I>/<I>n</I>=1/3</MATH>). | |
16361 <p>The construction will be best understood if we work out | |
16362 the analysis of the problem (not given by Euclid). | |
16363 <p>Suppose that <I>ABC</I> is the given triangle, <I>D</I> the given | |
16364 <pb n=428><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16365 internal point; and suppose the problem solved, i.e. <I>GH</I> | |
16366 drawn through <I>D</I> in such a way that <MATH>▵<I>GBH</I>=<I>m</I>/<I>n</I>.▵<I>ABC</I></MATH>. | |
16367 <p>Therefore <MATH><I>GB.BH</I>=<I>m</I>/<I>n.AB.BC</I></MATH>. (This is assumed by | |
16368 Euclid.) | |
16369 <p>Now suppose that the unknown quantity is <MATH><I>GB</I>=<I>x</I></MATH>, say. | |
16370 <p>Draw <I>DE</I> parallel to <I>BC</I>; then <I>DE, EB</I> are given. | |
16371 <p>Now <MATH><I>BH</I>:<I>DE</I>=<I>GB</I>:<I>GE</I>=<I>x</I>:(<I>x</I>-<I>BE</I>)</MATH>, | |
16372 or <MATH><I>BH</I>=(<I>x.DE</I>)/(<I>x</I>-<I>BE</I>)</MATH>; | |
16373 therefore <MATH><I>GB.BH</I>=<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>.<I>DE</I>/(<I>x</I>-<I>BE</I>)</MATH>. | |
16374 <p>And, by hypothesis, <MATH><I>GB.BH</I>=<I>m</I>/<I>n.AB.BC</I></MATH>; | |
16375 therefore <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>m/n.(AB.BC)/DE</I> (<I>x</I>-<I>BE</I>)</MATH>, | |
16376 or, if <MATH><I>k</I>=<I>m</I>/<I>n.(AB.BC)/DE</I></MATH>, we have to solve the equation | |
16377 <MATH><I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>k</I>(<I>x</I>-<I>BE</I>)</MATH>, | |
16378 or <MATH><I>kx</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>k.BE</I></MATH>. | |
16379 <p>This is exactly what Euclid does; he first finds <I>F</I> on <I>BA</I> | |
16380 such that <MATH><I>BF.DE</I>=<I>m</I>/<I>n.AB.BC</I></MATH> (the length of <I>BF</I> is deter- | |
16381 mined by applying to <I>DE</I> a rectangle equal to <MATH><I>m</I>/<I>n.AB.BC</I></MATH>, | |
16382 Eucl. I. 45), that is, he finds <I>BF</I> equal to <I>k.</I> Then he gives | |
16383 the geometrical solution of the equation <MATH><I>kx</I>-<I>x</I><SUP>2</SUP>=<I>k.BE</I></MATH> in the | |
16384 form ‘apply to the straight line <I>BF</I> a rectangle equal to | |
16385 <I>BF.BE</I> and deficient by a square’; that is to say, he deter- | |
16386 mines <I>G</I> so that <MATH><I>BG.GF</I>=<I>BF.BE</I></MATH>. We have then only | |
16387 to join <I>GD</I> and produce it to <I>H</I>; and <I>GH</I> cuts off the required | |
16388 triangle. | |
16389 <p>(The problem is subject to a <G>diorismo/s</G> which Euclid does | |
16390 not give, but which is easily supplied.) | |
16391 <p>(2) Proposition 28: To divide into two equal parts a given | |
16392 <pb n=429><head>ON DIVISIONS OF FIGURES</head> | |
16393 figure bounded by an arc of a circle and by two straight lines | |
16394 which form a given angle. | |
16395 <p>Let <I>ABEC</I> be the given figure, <I>D</I> the middle point of <I>BC</I>, | |
16396 and <I>DE</I> perpendicular to <I>BC.</I> Join <I>AD.</I> | |
16397 <p>Then the broken line <I>ADE</I> clearly divides the figure into | |
16398 two equal parts. Join <I>AE</I>, and draw | |
16399 <FIG> | |
16400 <I>DF</I> parallel to it meeting <I>BA</I> in <I>F.</I> | |
16401 Join <I>FE.</I> | |
16402 <p>The triangles <I>AFE, ADE</I> are then | |
16403 equal, being in the same parallels. | |
16404 Add to each the area <I>AEC.</I> | |
16405 <p>Therefore the area <I>AFEC</I> is equal to the area <I>ADEC</I>, and | |
16406 therefore to half the area of the given figure. | |
16407 <p>(3) Proposition 29: To draw in a given circle two parallel | |
16408 chords cutting off a certain fraction (<I>m</I>/<I>n</I>) of the circle. | |
16409 <p>(The fraction <I>m</I>/<I>n</I> must be | |
16410 <FIG> | |
16411 such that we can, by plane | |
16412 methods, draw a chord cutting off | |
16413 <I>m</I>/<I>n</I> of the circumference of | |
16414 the circle; Euclid takes the case | |
16415 where <MATH><I>m</I>/<I>n</I>=1/3</MATH>.) | |
16416 <p>Suppose that the arc <I>ADB</I> is | |
16417 <I>m</I>/<I>n</I> of the circumference of the | |
16418 circle. Join <I>A, B</I> to the centre <I>O.</I> | |
16419 Draw <I>OC</I> parallel to <I>AB</I> and join | |
16420 <I>AC, BC.</I> From <I>D</I>, the middle point | |
16421 of the arc <I>AB</I>, draw the chord <I>DE</I> parallel to <I>BC.</I> Then shall | |
16422 <I>BC, DE</I> cut off <I>m</I>/<I>n</I> of the area of the circle. | |
16423 <p>Since <I>AB, OC</I> are parallel, | |
16424 <MATH>▵<I>AOB</I>=▵<I>ACB</I></MATH>. | |
16425 <p>Add to each the segment <I>ADB</I>; | |
16426 therefore | |
16427 <MATH>(sector <I>ADBO</I>)=figure bounded by <I>AC, CB</I> and arc <I>ADB</I> | |
16428 =(segmt. <I>ABC</I>)-(segmt. <I>BFC</I>)</MATH>. | |
16429 <p>Since <I>BC, DE</I> are parallel, <MATH>(arc <I>DB</I>)=(arc <I>CE</I>)</MATH>; | |
16430 <pb n=430><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16431 therefore | |
16432 <MATH>(arc <I>ABC</I>)=(arc <I>DCE</I>), and (segmt. <I>ABC</I>)=(segmt. <I>DCE</I>); | |
16433 therefore (sector <I>ADBO</I>), or <I>m</I>/<I>n</I> (circle <I>ABC</I>) | |
16434 =(segmt. <I>DCE</I>)-(segmt. <I>BFC</I>)</MATH>. | |
16435 <p>That is <I>BC, DE</I> cut off an area equal to <MATH><I>m</I>/<I>n</I> (circle <I>ABC</I>)</MATH>. | |
16436 <C>Lost geometrical works.</C> | |
16437 <C>(<I>a</I>) The <I>Pseudaria.</I></C> | |
16438 <p>The other purely geometrical works of Euclid are lost so far | |
16439 as is known at present. One of these again belongs to the | |
16440 domain of elementary geometry. This is the <I>Pseudaria</I>, or | |
16441 ‘Book of Fallacies’, as it is called by Proclus, which is clearly | |
16442 the same work as the ‘Pseudographemata’ of Euclid men- | |
16443 tioned by a commentator on Aristotle in terms which agree | |
16444 with Proclus's description.<note>Michael Ephesius, <I>Comm. on Arist. Soph. El.</I>, fol. 25<SUP>v</SUP>, p. 76. 23 Wallies.</note> Proclus says of Euclid that, | |
16445 <p>‘Inasmuch as many things, while appearing to rest on truth | |
16446 and to follow from scientific principles, really tend to lead one | |
16447 astray from the principles and deceive the more superficial | |
16448 minds, he has handed down methods for the discriminative | |
16449 understanding of these things as well, by the use of which | |
16450 methods we shall be able to give beginners in this study | |
16451 practice in the discovery of paralogisms, and to avoid being | |
16452 ourselves misled. The treatise by which he puts this machinery | |
16453 in our hands he entitled (the book) of Pseudaria, enumerating | |
16454 in order their various kinds, exercising our intelligence in each | |
16455 case by theorems of all sorts, setting the true side by side | |
16456 with the false, and combining the refutation of error with | |
16457 practical illustration. This book then is by way of cathartic | |
16458 and exercise, while the Elements contain the irrefragable and | |
16459 complete guide to the actual scientific investigation of the | |
16460 subjects of geometry.’<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 70. 1-18. Cf. a scholium to Plato's <I>Theaetetus</I> | |
16461 191 B, which says that the fallacies did not arise through any importation | |
16462 of sense-perception into the domain of non-sensibles.</note> | |
16463 <p>The connexion of the book with the <I>Elements</I> and the refer- | |
16464 ence to its usefulness for beginners show that it did not go | |
16465 beyond the limits of elementary geometry. | |
16466 <pb n=431><head>LOST GEOMETRICAL WORKS</head> | |
16467 <p>We now come to the lost works belonging to higher | |
16468 geometry. The most important was evidently | |
16469 <C>(<G>b</G>) The <I>Porisms.</I></C> | |
16470 <p>Our only source of information about the nature and con- | |
16471 tents of the <I>Porisms</I> is Pappus. In his general preface about | |
16472 the books composing the <I>Treasury of Analysis</I> Pappus writes | |
16473 as follows<note>Pappus, vii, pp. 648-60.</note> (I put in square brackets the words bracketed by | |
16474 Hultsch). | |
16475 <p>‘After the Tangencies (of Apollonius) come, in three Books, | |
16476 the Porisms of Euclid, a collection [in the view of many] most | |
16477 ingeniously devised for the analysis of the more weighty | |
16478 problems, [and] although nature presents an unlimited num- | |
16479 ber of such porisms, [they have added nothing to what was | |
16480 originally written by Euclid, except that some before my time | |
16481 have shown their want of taste by adding to a few (of the | |
16482 propositions) second proofs, each (proposition) admitting of | |
16483 a definite number of demonstrations, as we have shown, and | |
16484 Euclid having given one for each, namely that which is the | |
16485 most lucid. These porisms embody a theory subtle, natural, | |
16486 necessary, and of considerable generality, which is fascinating | |
16487 to those who can see and produce results]. | |
16488 <p>‘Now all the varieties of porisms belong, neither to theorems | |
16489 nor problems, but to a species occupying a sort of intermediate | |
16490 position [so that their enunciations can be formed like those of | |
16491 either theorems or problems], the result being that, of the great | |
16492 number of geometers, some regarded them as of the class of | |
16493 theorems, and others of problems, looking only to the form of | |
16494 the proposition. But that the ancients knew better the differ- | |
16495 ence between these three things is clear from the definitions. | |
16496 For they said that a theorem is that which is proposed with a | |
16497 view to the demonstration of the very thing proposed, a pro- | |
16498 blem that which is thrown out with a view to the construction | |
16499 of the very thing proposed, and a porism that which is pro- | |
16500 posed with a view to the producing of the very thing proposed. | |
16501 [But this definition of the porism was changed by the more | |
16502 recent writers who could not produce everything, but used | |
16503 these elements and proved only the fact that that which is | |
16504 sought really exists, but did not produce it, and were accord- | |
16505 ingly confuted by the definition and the whole doctrine. They | |
16506 based their definition on an incidental characteristic, thus: | |
16507 A porism is that which falls short of a locus-theorem in | |
16508 <pb n=432><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16509 respect of its hypothesis. Of this kind of porisms loci are | |
16510 a species, and they abound in the Treasury of Analysis; but | |
16511 this species has been collected, named, and handed down | |
16512 separately from the porisms, because it is more widely diffused | |
16513 than the other species] . . . But it has further become charac- | |
16514 teristic of porisms that, owing to their complication, the enun- | |
16515 ciations are put in a contracted form, much being by usage | |
16516 left to be understood; so that many geometers understand | |
16517 them only in a partial way and are ignorant of the more | |
16518 essential features of their content. | |
16519 <p>‘[Now to comprehend a number of propositions in one | |
16520 enunciation is by no means easy in these porisms, because | |
16521 Euclid himself has not in fact given many of each species, but | |
16522 chosen, for examples, one or a few out of a great multitude. | |
16523 But at the beginning of the first book he has given some pro- | |
16524 positions, to the number of ten, of one species, namely that | |
16525 more fruitful species consisting of loci.] Consequently, finding | |
16526 that these admitted of being comprehended in our enunciation, | |
16527 we have set it out thus: | |
16528 <p>If, in a system of four straight lines which cut one | |
16529 another two and two, three points on one straight line | |
16530 be given, while the rest except one lie on different straight | |
16531 lines given in position, the remaining point also will lie | |
16532 on a straight line given in position. | |
16533 <p>‘This has only been enunciated of four straight lines, of | |
16534 which not more than two pass through the same point, but it | |
16535 is not known (to most people) that it is true of any assigned | |
16536 number of straight lines if enunciated thus: | |
16537 <p>If any number of straight lines cut one another, not | |
16538 more than two (passing) through the same point, and all | |
16539 the points (of intersection situated) on one of them be | |
16540 given, and if each of those which are on another (of | |
16541 them) lie on a straight line given in position— | |
16542 <p>or still more generally thus: | |
16543 <p>if any number of straight lines cut one another, not more | |
16544 than two (passing) through the same point, and all the | |
16545 points (of intersection situated) on one of them be given, | |
16546 while of the other points of intersection in multitude | |
16547 equal to a triangular number a number corresponding | |
16548 to the side of this triangular number lie respectively on | |
16549 straight lines given in position, provided that of these | |
16550 latter points no three are at the angular points of a | |
16551 triangle (sc. having for sides three of the given straight | |
16552 <pb n=433><head>THE <I>PORISMS</I></head> | |
16553 lines)—each of the remaining points will lie on a straight | |
16554 line given in position.<note>Loria (<I>Le scienze esatte nell'antica Grecia,</I> pp. 256-7) gives the mean- | |
16555 ing of this as follows, pointing out that Simson first discovered it: ‘If | |
16556 a complete <I>n</I>-lateral be deformed so that its sides respectively turn about | |
16557 <I>n</I> points on a straight line, and (<I>n</I> - 1) of its 1/2 <I>n</I> (<I>n</I> - 1) vertices move on | |
16558 as many straight lines, the other 1/2 (<I>n</I> - 1) (<I>n</I> - 2) of its vertices likewise | |
16559 move on as many straight lines: but it is necessary that it should be | |
16560 impossible to form with the (<I>n</I> - 1) vertices any triangle having for sides | |
16561 the sides of the polygon.’</note> | |
16562 <p>‘It is probable that the writer of the Elements was not | |
16563 unaware of this, but that he only set out the principle; and | |
16564 he seems, in the case of all the porisms, to have laid down the | |
16565 principles and the seed only [of many important things], | |
16566 the kinds of which should be distinguished according to the | |
16567 differences, not of their hypotheses, but of the results and | |
16568 the things sought. [All the hypotheses are different from one | |
16569 another because they are entirely special, but each of the | |
16570 results and things sought, being one and the same, follow from | |
16571 many different hypotheses.] | |
16572 <p>‘We must then in the first book distinguish the following | |
16573 kinds of things sought: | |
16574 <p>‘At the beginning of the book is this proposition: | |
16575 <p>I. <I>If from two given points straight lines be drawn | |
16576 meeting on a straight line given in position, and one cut | |
16577 off from a straight line given in position</I> (<I>a segment | |
16578 measured</I>) <I>to a given point on it, the other will also cut | |
16579 off from another</I> (<I>straight line a segment</I>) <I>having to the | |
16580 first a given ratio.</I> | |
16581 <p>‘Following on this (we have to prove) | |
16582 <p>II. that such and such a point lies on a straight line | |
16583 given in position; | |
16584 <p>III. that the ratio of such and such a pair of straight | |
16585 lines is given’; | |
16586 <p>&c. &c. (up to XXIX). | |
16587 <p>‘The three books of the porisms contain 38 lemmas; of the | |
16588 theorems themselves there are 171.’ | |
16589 <p>Pappus further gives lemmas to the <I>Porisms.</I><note>Pappus, vii, pp. 866-918; Euclid, ed. Heiberg-Menge, vol. viii, | |
16590 pp. 243-74.</note> | |
16591 <p>With Pappus's account of Porisms must be compared the | |
16592 passages of Proclus on the same subject. Proclus distinguishes | |
16593 <pb n=434><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16594 the two senses of the word <G>po/risma</G>. The first is that of | |
16595 a <I>corollary,</I> where something appears as an incidental result | |
16596 of a proposition, obtained without trouble or special seeking, | |
16597 a sort of bonus which the investigation has presented us | |
16598 with.<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, pp. 212. 14; 301. 22.</note> The other sense is that of Euclid's <I>Porisms.</I> In | |
16599 this sense | |
16600 <p>‘<I>porism</I> is the name given to things which are sought, but | |
16601 need some finding and are neither pure bringing into existence | |
16602 nor simple theoretic argument. For (to prove) that the angles | |
16603 at the base of isosceles triangles are equal is matter of theoretic | |
16604 argument, and it is with reference to things existing that such | |
16605 knowledge is (obtained). But to bisect an angle, to construct | |
16606 a triangle, to cut off, or to place—all these things demand the | |
16607 making of something; and to find the centre of a given circle, | |
16608 or to find the greatest common measure of two given commen- | |
16609 surable magnitudes, or the like, is in some sort intermediate | |
16610 between theorems and problems. For in these cases there is | |
16611 no bringing into existence of the things sought, but finding | |
16612 of them; nor is the procedure purely theoretic. For it is | |
16613 necessary to bring what is sought into view and exhibit it | |
16614 to the eye. Such are the porisms which Euclid wrote and | |
16615 arranged in three books of Porisms.’<note><I>Ib.,</I> p. 301. 25 sq.</note> | |
16616 <p>Proclus's definition thus agrees well enough with the first, | |
16617 the ‘older’, definition of Pappus. A porism occupies a place | |
16618 between a theorem and a problem; it deals with something | |
16619 already existing, as a theorem does, but has to <I>find</I> it (e.g. the | |
16620 centre of a circle), and, as a certain operation is therefore | |
16621 necessary, it partakes to that extent of the nature of a problem, | |
16622 which requires us to construct or produce something not | |
16623 previously existing. Thus, besides III. 1 and X. 3, 4 of the | |
16624 <I>Elements</I> mentioned by Proclus, the following propositions are | |
16625 real porisms: III. 25, VI. 11-13, VII. 33, 34, 36, 39, VIII. 2, 4, | |
16626 X. 10, XIII. 18. Similarly, in Archimedes's <I>On the Sphere and | |
16627 Cylinder,</I> I. 2-6 might be called porisms. | |
16628 <p>The enunciation given by Pappus as comprehending ten of | |
16629 Euclid's propositions may not reproduce the <I>form</I> of Euclid's | |
16630 enunciations; but, comparing the result to be proved, that | |
16631 certain points lie on straight lines given in position, with the | |
16632 <I>class</I> indicated by II above, where the question is of such and | |
16633 such a point lying on a straight line given in position, and | |
16634 <pb n=435><head>THE <I>PORISMS</I></head> | |
16635 with other classes, e.g. (V) that such and such a line is given | |
16636 in position, (VI) that such and such a line verges to a given point, | |
16637 (XXVII) that there exists a given point such that straight | |
16638 lines drawn from it to such and such (circles) will contain | |
16639 a triangle given in species, we may conclude that a usual form | |
16640 of a porism was ‘to prove that it is possible to find a point | |
16641 with such and such a property’ or ‘a straight line on which | |
16642 lie all the points satisfying given conditions’, and so on. | |
16643 <p>The above exhausts all the positive information which we | |
16644 have about the nature of a porism and the contents of Euclid's | |
16645 <I>Porisms.</I> It is obscure and leaves great scope for speculation | |
16646 and controversy; naturally, therefore, the problem of restoring | |
16647 the <I>Porisms</I> has had a great fascination for distinguished | |
16648 mathematicians ever since the revival of learning. But it has | |
16649 proved beyond them all. Some contributions to a solution have, | |
16650 it is true, been made, mainly by Simson and Chasles. The first | |
16651 claim to have restored the <I>Porisms</I> seems to be that of Albert | |
16652 Girard (about 1590-1633), who spoke (1626) of an early pub- | |
16653 lication of his results, which, however, never saw the light. | |
16654 The great Fermat (1601-65) gave his idea of a ‘porism’, | |
16655 illustrating it by five examples which are very interesting in | |
16656 themselves<note><I>Œuvres de Fermat,</I> ed. Tannery and Henry, I, p. 76-84.</note>; but he did not succeed in connecting them with | |
16657 the description of Euclid's <I>Porisms</I> by Pappus, and, though he | |
16658 expressed a hope of being able to produce a complete restoration | |
16659 of the latter, his hope was not realized. It was left for Robert | |
16660 Simson (1687-1768) to make the first decisive step towards the | |
16661 solution of the problem.<note>Roberti Simson <I>Opera quaedam reliqua,</I> 1776, pp. 315-594.</note> He succeeded in explaining the mean- | |
16662 ing of the actual porisms enunciated in such general terms by | |
16663 Pappus. In his tract on Porisms he proves the first porism | |
16664 given by Pappus in its ten different cases, which, according to | |
16665 Pappus, Euclid distinguished (these propositions are of the | |
16666 class connected with <I>loci</I>); after this he gives a number of | |
16667 other propositions from Pappus, some auxiliary proposi- | |
16668 tions, and some 29 ‘porisms’, some of which are meant to | |
16669 illustrate the classes I, VI, XV, XXVII-XXIX distin- | |
16670 guished by Pappus. Simson was able to evolve a definition | |
16671 of a porism which is perhaps more easily understood in | |
16672 Chasles's translation: ‘Le porisme est une proposition dans | |
16673 <pb n=436><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16674 laquelle on demande de démontrer qu'une chose ou plusieurs | |
16675 choses sont <I>données,</I> qui, ainsi que l'une quelconque d'une | |
16676 infinité d'autres choses non données, mais dont chacune est | |
16677 avec des choses données dans une même relation, ont une | |
16678 propriété commune, décrite dans la proposition.’ We need | |
16679 not follow Simson's English or Scottish successors, Lawson | |
16680 (1777), Playfair (1794), W. Wallace (1798), Lord Brougham | |
16681 (1798), in their further speculations, nor the controversies | |
16682 between the Frenchmen, A. J. H. Vincent and P. Breton (de | |
16683 Champ), nor the latter's claim to priority as against Chasles; | |
16684 the work of Chasles himself (<I>Les trois livres des Porismes | |
16685 d'Euclide rétablis . . .</I> Paris, 1860) alone needs to be men- | |
16686 tioned. Chasles adopted the definition of a porism given by | |
16687 Simson, but showed how it could be expressed in a different | |
16688 form. ‘Porisms are incomplete theorems which express | |
16689 certain relations existing between things variable in accord- | |
16690 ance with a common law, relations which are indicated in | |
16691 the enunciation of the porism, but which need to be completed | |
16692 by determining the magnitude or position of certain things | |
16693 which are the consequences of the hypotheses and which | |
16694 would be determined in the enunciation of a theorem properly | |
16695 so called or a complete theorem.’ Chasles succeeded in eluci- | |
16696 dating the connexion between a porism and a locus as de- | |
16697 scribed by Pappus, though he gave an inexact translation of | |
16698 the actual words of Pappus: ‘<I>Ce qui constitue le porisme est | |
16699 ce qui manque à l'hypothèse d'un théorème local</I> (en d'autres | |
16700 termes, le porisme est inférieur, par l'hypothèse, au théorème | |
16701 local; c'est à dire que quand quelques parties d'une proposi- | |
16702 tion locale n'ont pas dans l'énoncé la détermination qui leur | |
16703 est propre, cette proposition cesse d'être regardée comme un | |
16704 théorème et devient un porisme)’; here the words italicized | |
16705 are not quite what Pappus said, viz. that ‘a porism is that | |
16706 which falls short of a locus-theorem in respect of its hypo- | |
16707 thesis’, but the explanation in brackets is correct enough if | |
16708 we substitute ‘in respect of’ for ‘par’ (‘by’). The work of | |
16709 Chasles is historically important because it was in the course | |
16710 of his researches on this subject that he was led to the idea of | |
16711 anharmonic ratios; and he was probably right in thinking | |
16712 that the <I>Porisms</I> were propositions belonging to the modern | |
16713 theory of transversals and to projective geometry. But, as a | |
16714 <pb n=437><head>THE <I>PORISMS</I></head> | |
16715 restoration of Euclid's work, Chasles's Porisms cannot be re- | |
16716 garded as satisfactory. One consideration alone is, to my | |
16717 mind, conclusive on this point. Chasles made ‘porisms’ out | |
16718 of Pappus's various <I>lemmas</I> to Euclid's porisms and com- | |
16719 paratively easy deductions from those lemmas. Now we | |
16720 have experience of Pappus's lemmas to books which still | |
16721 survive, e.g. the <I>Conics</I> of Apollonius; and, to judge by these | |
16722 instances, his lemmas stood in a most ancillary relation to | |
16723 the propositions to which they relate, and do not in the | |
16724 least compare with them in difficulty and importance. Hence | |
16725 it is all but impossible to believe that the lemmas to the | |
16726 porisms were themselves porisms such as were Euclid's own | |
16727 porisms; on the contrary, the analogy of Pappus's other sets | |
16728 of lemmas makes it all but necessary to regard the lemmas in | |
16729 question as merely supplying proofs of simple propositions | |
16730 assumed by Euclid without proof in the course of the demon- | |
16731 stration of the actual porisms. This being so, it appears that | |
16732 the problem of the complete restoration of Euclid's three | |
16733 Books still awaits a solution, or rather that it will never be | |
16734 solved unless in the event of discovery of fresh documents. | |
16735 <p>At the same time the lemmas of Pappus to the <I>Porisms</I> | |
16736 are by no means insignificant propositions in themselves, | |
16737 and, if the usual relation of lemmas to substantive proposi- | |
16738 tions holds, it follows that the <I>Porisms</I> was a distinctly | |
16739 advanced work, perhaps the most important that Euclid ever | |
16740 wrote; its loss is therefore much to be deplored. Zeuthen | |
16741 has an interesting remark à propos of the proposition which | |
16742 Pappus quotes as the first proposition of Book I, ‘If from two | |
16743 given points straight lines be drawn meeting on a straight | |
16744 line given in position, and one of them cut off from a straight | |
16745 line given in position (a segment measured) towards a given | |
16746 point on it, the other will also cut off from another (straight | |
16747 line a segment) bearing to the first a given ratio.’ This pro- | |
16748 position is also true if there be substituted for the first given | |
16749 straight line a conic regarded as the ‘locus with respect to | |
16750 four lines’, and the proposition so extended can be used for | |
16751 completing Apollonius's exposition of that locus. Zeuthen | |
16752 suggests, on this ground, that the <I>Porisms</I> were in part by- | |
16753 products of the theory of conics and in part auxiliary means | |
16754 for the study of conics, and that Euclid called them by the | |
16755 <pb n=438><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16756 same name as that applied to corollaries because they were | |
16757 corollaries with respect to conics.<note>Zeuthen, <I>Die Lehre von den Kegelschnitten im Altertum,</I> 1886, pp. 168, | |
16758 173-4.</note> This, however, is a pure | |
16759 conjecture. | |
16760 <C>(<G>g</G>) The <I>Conics.</I></C> | |
16761 <p>Pappus says of this lost work: ‘The four books of Euclid's | |
16762 Conics were completed by Apollonius, who added four more | |
16763 and gave us eight books of Conics.’<note>Pappus, vii, p. 672. 18.</note> It is probable that | |
16764 Euclid's work was already lost by Pappus's time, for he goes | |
16765 on to speak of ‘Aristaeus who wrote the <I>still extant</I> five books | |
16766 of Solid Loci <G>sunexh= toi=s kwnikoi=s</G>, connected with, or supple- | |
16767 mentary to, the conics’.<note>Cf. Pappus, vii, p. 636. 23.</note> This latter work seems to have | |
16768 been a treatise on conics regarded as loci; for ‘solid loci’ was | |
16769 a term appropriated to conics, as distinct from ‘plane loci’, | |
16770 which were straight lines and circles. In another passage | |
16771 Pappus (or an interpolator) speaks of the ‘conics’ of Aristaeus | |
16772 the ‘elder’,<note><I>Ib.</I> vii, p. 672. 12.</note> evidently referring to the same book. Euclid no | |
16773 doubt wrote on the general theory of conics, as Apollonius did, | |
16774 but only covered the ground of Apollonius's first three books, | |
16775 since Apollonius says that no one before him had touched the | |
16776 subject of Book IV (which, however, is not important). As in | |
16777 the case of the <I>Elements,</I> Euclid would naturally collect and | |
16778 rearrange, in a systematic exposition, all that had been dis- | |
16779 covered up to date in the theory of conics. That Euclid's | |
16780 treatise covered most of the essentials up to the last part of | |
16781 Apollonius's Book III seems clear from the fact that Apol- | |
16782 lonius only claims originality for some propositions connected | |
16783 with the ‘three- and four-line locus’, observing that Euclid | |
16784 had not completely worked out the synthesis of the said locus, | |
16785 which, indeed, was not possible without the propositions | |
16786 referred to. Pappus (or an interpolator)<note><I>Ib.</I> vii, pp. 676. 25-678. 6.</note> excuses Euclid on | |
16787 the ground that he made no claim to go beyond the discoveries | |
16788 of Aristaeus, but only wrote so much about the locus as was | |
16789 possible with the aid of Aristaeus's conics. We may conclude | |
16790 that Aristaeus's book preceded Euclid's, and that it was, at | |
16791 least in point of originality, more important. When Archi- | |
16792 medes refers to propositions in conics as having been proved | |
16793 <pb n=439><head>THE <I>CONICS</I> AND <I>SURFACE-LOCI</I></head> | |
16794 in the ‘elements of conics’, he clearly refers to these two | |
16795 treatises, and the other propositions to which he refers as well | |
16796 known and not needing proof were doubtless taken from the | |
16797 same sources. Euclid still used the old names for the conic | |
16798 sections (sections of a right-angled, acute-angled, and obtuse- | |
16799 angled cone respectively), but he was aware that an ellipse | |
16800 could be obtained by cutting (through) a cone in any manner | |
16801 by a plane not parallel to the base, and also by cutting a | |
16802 cylinder; this is clear from a sentence in his <I>Phaenomena</I> to | |
16803 the effect that, ‘If a cone or a cylinder be cut by a plane not | |
16804 parallel to the base, this section is a section of an acute-angled | |
16805 cone, which is like a shield (<G>qureo/s</G>).’ | |
16806 <C>(<G>d</G>) The <I>Surface-Loci</I> (<G>to/poi pro\s e)pifanei/a|</G>).</C> | |
16807 <p>Like the <I>Data</I> and the <I>Porisms,</I> this treatise in two Books | |
16808 is mentioned by Pappus as belonging to the <I>Treasury of | |
16809 Analysis.</I> What is meant by surface-loci, literally ‘loci on a | |
16810 surface’ is not entirely clear, but we are able to form a con- | |
16811 jecture on the subject by means of remarks in Proclus and | |
16812 Pappus. The former says (1) that a locus is ‘a position of a | |
16813 line or of a surface which has (throughout it) one and the | |
16814 same property’,<note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 394. 17.</note> and (2) that ‘of locus-theorems some are | |
16815 constructed on lines and others on surfaces’<note><I>Ib.,</I> p. 394. 19.</note>; the effect of | |
16816 these statements together seems to be that ‘loci on lines’ are | |
16817 loci which <I>are</I> lines, and ‘loci on surfaces’ loci which <I>are</I> | |
16818 surfaces. On the other hand, the possibility does not seem to | |
16819 be excluded that loci on surfaces may be loci <I>traced</I> on sur- | |
16820 faces; for Pappus says in one place that the equivalent of the | |
16821 <I>quadratrix</I> can be got geometrically ‘by means of loci on | |
16822 surfaces as follows’<note>Pappus, iv, p. 258. 20-25.</note> and then proceeds to use a spiral de- | |
16823 scribed on a cylinder (the cylindrical helix), and it is consis- | |
16824 tent with this that in another passage<note><I>Ib.</I> vii. 662. 9.</note> (bracketed, however, by | |
16825 Hultsch) ‘linear’ loci are said to be exhibited (<G>dei/knuntai</G>) or | |
16826 realized from loci on surfaces, for the quadratrix is a ‘linear’ | |
16827 locus, i.e. a locus of an order higher than a plane locus | |
16828 (a straight line or circle) and a ‘solid’ locus (a conic). How- | |
16829 ever this may be, Euclid's <I>Surface-Loci</I> probably included | |
16830 <pb n=440><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16831 such loci as were cones, cylinders and spheres. The two | |
16832 lemmas given by Pappus lend some colour to this view. The | |
16833 first of these<note>Pappus, vii, p. 1004. 17; Euclid, ed. Heiberg-Menge, vol. viii, p. 274.</note> and the figure attached to it are unsatisfactory | |
16834 as they stand, but Tannery indicated a possible restoration.<note>Tannery in <I>Bulletin des sciences mathématiques,</I> 2° série, VI, p. 149.</note> | |
16835 If this is right, it suggests that one of the loci contained all | |
16836 the points on the elliptical parallel sections of a cylinder, and | |
16837 was therefore an oblique circular cylinder. Other assump- | |
16838 tions with regard to the conditions to which the lines in the | |
16839 figure may be subject would suggest that other loci dealt with | |
16840 were cones regarded as containing all points on particular | |
16841 parallel elliptical sections of the cones. In the second lemma | |
16842 Pappus states and gives a complete proof of the focus-and- | |
16843 directrix property of a conic, viz. that <I>the locus of a point | |
16844 the distance of which from a given point is in a given ratio | |
16845 to its distance from a fixed straight line is a conic section, | |
16846 which is an ellipse, a parabola or a hyperbola according as the | |
16847 given ratio is less than, equal to, or greater than unity.</I><note>Pappus, vii, pp. 1004. 23-1014; Euclid, vol. viii, pp. 275-81.</note> Two | |
16848 conjectures are possible as to the application of this theorem in | |
16849 Euclid's <I>Surface-Loci.</I> (<I>a</I>) It may have been used to prove that | |
16850 the locus of a point the distance of which from a given straight | |
16851 line is in a given ratio to its distance from a given plane | |
16852 is a certain cone. Or (<I>b</I>) it may have been used to prove | |
16853 that the locus of a point the distance of which from a given | |
16854 point is in a given ratio to its distance from a given plane is | |
16855 the surface formed by the revolution of a conic about its major | |
16856 or conjugate axis.<note>For further details, see <I>The Works of Archimedes,</I> pp. lxii-lxv.</note> | |
16857 <p>We come now to Euclid's works under the head of | |
16858 <C>Applied mathematics.</C> | |
16859 <C>(<G>a</G>) The <I>Phaenomena.</I></C> | |
16860 <p>The book on <I>sphaeric</I> intended for use in astronomy and | |
16861 entitled <I>Phaenomena</I> has already been noticed (pp. 349, 351-2). | |
16862 It is extant in Greek and was included in Gregory's edition of | |
16863 Euclid. The text of Gregory, however, represents the later | |
16864 of two recensions which differ considerably (especially in | |
16865 Propositions 9 to 16). The best manuscript of this later | |
16866 recension (b) is the famous Vat. gr. 204 of the tenth century, | |
16867 <pb n=441><head>THE <I>PHAENOMENA</I> AND <I>OPTICS</I></head> | |
16868 while the best manuscript of the older and better version (a) | |
16869 is the Viennese MS.Vind. gr. XXXI. 13 of the twelfth century. | |
16870 A new text edited by Menge and taking account of both | |
16871 recensions is now available in the last volume of the Heiberg- | |
16872 Menge edition of Euclid.<note><I>Euclidis Phaenomena et scripta Musica</I> edidit Henricus Menge. | |
16873 <I>Fragmenta</I> collegit et disposuit J. L. Heiberg, Teubner, 1916.</note> | |
16874 <C>(<G>b</G>) <I>Optics</I> and <I>Catoptrica.</I></C> | |
16875 <p>The <I>Optics,</I> a treatise included by Pappus in the collection of | |
16876 works known as the Little Astronomy, survives in two forms. | |
16877 One is the recension of Theon translated by Zambertus in | |
16878 1505; the Greek text was first edited by Johannes Pena | |
16879 (de la Pène) in 1557, and this form of the treatise was alone | |
16880 included in the editions up to Gregory's. But Heiberg dis- | |
16881 covered the earlier form in two manuscripts, one at Vienna | |
16882 (Vind. gr. XXXI. 13) and one at Florence (Laurent. XXVIII. 3), | |
16883 and both recensions are contained in vol. vii of the Heiberg- | |
16884 Menge text of Euclid (Teubner, 1895). There is no reason to | |
16885 doubt that the earlier recension is Euclid's own work; the | |
16886 style is much more like that of the <I>Elements,</I> and the proofs of | |
16887 the propositions are more complete and clear. The later recen- | |
16888 sion is further differentiated by a preface of some length, which | |
16889 is said by a scholiast to be taken from the commentary or | |
16890 elucidation by Theon. It would appear that the text of this | |
16891 recension is Theon's, and that the preface was a reproduction | |
16892 by a pupil of what was explained by Theon in lectures. It | |
16893 cannot have been written much, if anything, later than Theon's | |
16894 time, for it is quoted by Nemesius about A.D. 400. Only the | |
16895 earlier and genuine version need concern us here. It is | |
16896 a kind of elementary treatise on perspective, and it may have | |
16897 been intended to forearm students of astronomy against | |
16898 paradoxical theories such as those of the Epicureans, who | |
16899 maintained that the heavenly bodies <I>are</I> of the size that they | |
16900 <I>look.</I> It begins in the orthodox fashion with Definitions, the | |
16901 first of which embodies the same idea of the process of vision | |
16902 as we find in Plato, namely that it is due to rays proceeding | |
16903 from our eyes and impinging upon the object, instead of | |
16904 the other way about: ‘the straight lines (rays) which issue | |
16905 from the eye traverse the distances (or dimensions) of great | |
16906 <pb n=442><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16907 magnitudes’; Def. 2: ‘The figure contained by the visual rays | |
16908 is a cone which has its vertex in the eye, and its base at the | |
16909 extremities of the objects seen’; Def. 3: ‘And those things | |
16910 are seen on which the visual rays impinge, while those are | |
16911 not seen on which they do not’; Def. 4: ‘Things seen under | |
16912 a greater angle appear greater, and those under a lesser angle | |
16913 less, while things seen under equal angles appear equal’; | |
16914 Def. 7: ‘Things seen under more angles appear more distinctly.’ | |
16915 Euclid assumed that the visual rays are not ‘continuous’, | |
16916 i.e. not absolutely close together, but are separated by a | |
16917 certain distance, and hence he concluded, in Proposition 1, | |
16918 that we can never really see the whole of any object, though | |
16919 we seem to do so. Apart, however, from such inferences as | |
16920 these from false hypotheses, there is much in the treatise that | |
16921 is sound. Euclid has the essential truth that the rays are | |
16922 straight; and it makes no difference geometrically whether | |
16923 they proceed from the eye or the object. Then, after pro- | |
16924 positions explaining the differences in the apparent size of an | |
16925 object according to its position relatively to the eye, he proves | |
16926 that the apparent sizes of two equal and parallel objects are | |
16927 not proportional to their distances from the eye (Prop. 8); in | |
16928 this proposition he proves the equivalent of the fact that, if <G>a</G>, | |
16929 <G>b</G> are two angles and <MATH><G>a</G> < <G>b</G> < (1/2)<G>p</G></MATH>, then | |
16930 <MATH>(tan <G>a</G>)/(tan <G>b</G>) < <G>a</G>/<G>b</G></MATH>, | |
16931 the equivalent of which, as well as of the corresponding | |
16932 formula with sines, is assumed without proof by Aristarchus | |
16933 a little later. From Proposition 6 can easily be deduced the | |
16934 fundamental proposition in perspective that parallel lines | |
16935 (regarded as equidistant throughout) appear to meet. There | |
16936 are four simple propositions in heights and distances, e.g. to | |
16937 find the height of an object (1) when the sun is shining | |
16938 (Prop. 18), (2) when it is not (Prop. 19): similar triangles are, | |
16939 of course, used and the horizontal mirror appears in the second | |
16940 case in the orthodox manner, with the assumption that the | |
16941 angles of incidence and reflection of a ray are equal, ‘as | |
16942 is explained in the Catoptrica (or theory of mirrors)’. Pro- | |
16943 positions 23-7 prove that, if an eye sees a sphere, it sees | |
16944 less than half of the sphere, and the contour of what is seen | |
16945 <pb n=443><head><I>OPTICS</I></head> | |
16946 appears to be a circle; if the eye approaches nearer to | |
16947 the sphere the portion seen becomes less, though it appears | |
16948 greater; if we see the sphere with two eyes, we see a hemi- | |
16949 sphere, or more than a hemisphere, or less than a hemisphere | |
16950 according as the distance between the eyes is equal to, greater | |
16951 than, or less than the diameter of the sphere; these pro- | |
16952 positions are comparable with Aristarchus's Proposition 2 | |
16953 stating that, if a sphere be illuminated by a larger sphere, | |
16954 the illuminated portion of the former will be greater | |
16955 than a hemisphere. Similar propositions with regard to the | |
16956 cylinder and cone follow (Props. 28-33). Next Euclid con- | |
16957 siders the conditions for the apparent equality of different | |
16958 diameters of a circle as seen from an eye occupying various | |
16959 positions outside the plane of the circle (Props. 34-7); he | |
16960 shows that all diameters will appear equal, or the circle will | |
16961 really look like a circle, if the line joining the eye to the | |
16962 centre is perpendicular to the plane of the circle, <I>or,</I> not being | |
16963 perpendicular to that plane, is equal to the length of the | |
16964 radius, but this will not otherwise be the case (35), so that (36) | |
16965 a chariot wheel will sometimes appear circular, sometimes | |
16966 awry, according to the position of the eye. Propositions | |
16967 37 and 38 prove, the one that there is a locus such that, if the | |
16968 eye remains at one point of it, while a straight line moves so | |
16969 that its extremities always lie on it, the line will always | |
16970 <I>appear</I> of the same length in whatever position it is placed | |
16971 (not being one in which either of the extremities coincides | |
16972 with, or the extremities are on opposite sides of, the point | |
16973 at which the eye is placed), the locus being, of course, a circle | |
16974 in which the straight line is placed as a chord, when it | |
16975 necessarily subtends the same angle at the circumference or at | |
16976 the centre, and therefore at the eye, if placed at a point of the | |
16977 circumference or at the centre; the other proves the same thing | |
16978 for the case where the line is fixed with its extremities on the | |
16979 locus, while the eye moves upon it. The same idea underlies | |
16980 several other propositions, e.g. Proposition 45, which proves | |
16981 that a common point can be found from which unequal | |
16982 magnitudes will appear equal. The unequal magnitudes are | |
16983 straight lines <I>BC, CD</I> so placed that <I>BCD</I> is a straight line. | |
16984 A segment greater than a semicircle is described on <I>BC,</I> and | |
16985 a similar segment on <I>CD.</I> The segments will then intersect | |
16986 <pb n=444><head>EUCLID</head> | |
16987 at <I>F,</I> and the angles subtended by <I>BC</I> and <I>CD</I> at <I>F</I> are | |
16988 equal. The rest of the treatise is of the same character, and | |
16989 it need not be further described. | |
16990 <p>The <I>Catoptrica</I> published by Heiberg in the same volume is | |
16991 not by Euclid, but is a compilation made at a much later date, | |
16992 possibly by Theon of Alexandria, from ancient works on the | |
16993 subject and mainly no doubt from those of Archimedes and | |
16994 Heron. Theon<note>Theon, <I>Comm. on Ptolemy's Syntaxis,</I> i, p. 10.</note> himself quotes a <I>Catoptrica</I> by Archimedes, | |
16995 and Olympiodorus<note><I>Comment. on Arist. Meteorolog.</I> ii, p. 94, Ideler, p. 211. 18 Busse.</note> quotes Archimedes as having proved the | |
16996 fact which appears as an axiom in the <I>Catoptrica</I> now in | |
16997 question, namely that, if an object be placed just out of sight | |
16998 at the bottom of a vessel, it will become visible over the edge | |
16999 when water is poured in. It is not even certain that Euclid | |
17000 wrote <I>Catoptrica</I> at all, since, if the treatise was Theon's, | |
17001 Proclus may have assigned it to Euclid through inadvertence. | |
17002 <C>(<G>g</G> <I>Music.</I></C> | |
17003 <p>Proclus attributes to Euclid a work on the <I>Elements of | |
17004 Music</I> (<G>ai( kata\ mousikh\n stoixeiw/seis</G><note>Proclus on Eucl. I, p. 69. 3.</note>; so does Marinus.<note>Marinus, <I>Comm. on the Data</I> (Euclid, vol. vi, p. 254. 19).</note> | |
17005 As a matter of fact, two musical treatises attributed to Euclid | |
17006 are still extant, the <I>Sectio Canonis</I> (<G>*katatomh\ kano/nos</G>) and the | |
17007 <I>Introductio harmonica</I> (<G>*ei)sagwgh\ a(rmonikh/</G>). The latter, | |
17008 however, is certainly not by Euclid, but by Cleonides, a pupil | |
17009 of Aristoxenus. The question remains, in what relation does | |
17010 the <I>Sectio Canonis</I> stand to the ‘Elements’ mentioned by | |
17011 Proclus and Marinus? The <I>Sectio</I> gives the Pythagorean | |
17012 theory of music, but is altogether too partial and slight to | |
17013 deserve the title ‘Elements of Music’. Jan, the editor of the | |
17014 <I>Musici Graeci,</I> thought that the <I>Sectio</I> was a sort of summary | |
17015 account extracted from the ‘Elements’ by Euclid himself, | |
17016 which hardly seems likely; he maintained that it is the | |
17017 genuine work of Euclid on the grounds (1) that the style and | |
17018 diction and the form of the propositions agree well with what | |
17019 we find in Euclid's <I>Elements,</I> and (2) that Porphyry in his | |
17020 commentary on Ptolemy's <I>Harmonica</I> thrice quotes Euclid as | |
17021 the author of a <I>Sectio Canonis.</I><note>See Wallis, <I>Opera mathematica,</I> vol. iii, 1699, pp. 267, 269, 272.</note> The latest editor, Menge, | |
17022 <pb n=445><head>ON MUSIC</head> | |
17023 points out that the extract given by Porphyry shows some | |
17024 differences from our text and contains some things quite | |
17025 unworthy of Euclid; hence he is inclined to think that the | |
17026 work as we have it is not actually by Euclid, but was ex- | |
17027 tracted by some other author of less ability from the genuine | |
17028 ‘Elements of Music’ by Euclid. | |
17029 <C>(<G>d</G>) Works on mechanics attributed to Euclid.</C> | |
17030 <p>The Arabian list of Euclid's works further includes among | |
17031 those held to be genuine ‘the book of the Heavy and Light’. | |
17032 This is apparently the tract <I>De levi et ponderoso</I> included by. | |
17033 Hervagius in the Basel Latin translation of 1537 and by | |
17034 Gregory in his edition. That it comes from the Greek is | |
17035 made clear by the lettering of the figures; and this is con- | |
17036 firmed by the fact that another, very slightly different, version | |
17037 exists at Dresden (Cod. Dresdensis Db. 86), which is evidently | |
17038 a version of an Arabic translation from the Greek, since the | |
17039 lettering of the figures follows the order characteristic of such | |
17040 Arabic translations, <I>a, b, g, d, e, z, h, t.</I> The tract consists of | |
17041 nine definitions or axioms and five propositions. Among the | |
17042 definitions are these: Bodies are equal, different, or greater in | |
17043 size according as they occupy equal, different, or greater spaces | |
17044 (1-3). Bodies are equal in <I>power</I> or in <I>virtue</I> which move | |
17045 over equal distances in the same medium of air or water in | |
17046 equal times (4), while the <I>power</I> or <I>virtue</I> is greater if the | |
17047 motion takes less time, and less if it takes more (6). Bodies | |
17048 are <I>of the same kind</I> if, being equal in size, they are also equal | |
17049 in <I>power</I> when the medium is the same; they are different in | |
17050 kind when, being equal in size, they are not equal in <I>power</I> or | |
17051 <I>virtue</I> (7, 8). Of bodies different in kind, that has more <I>power</I> | |
17052 which is more dense (<I>solidius</I>) (9). With these hypotheses, the | |
17053 author attempts to prove (Props. 1, 3, 5) that, of bodies which | |
17054 traverse unequal spaces in equal times, that which traverses | |
17055 the greater space has the greater <I>power</I> and that, of bodies of | |
17056 the same kind, the <I>power</I> is proportional to the size, and con- | |
17057 versely, if the <I>power</I> is proportional to the size, the bodies are | |
17058 of the same kind. We recognize in the <I>potentia</I> or <I>virtus</I> | |
17059 the same thing as the <G>du/namis</G> and <G>i)sxu/s</G> of Aristotle.<note>Aristotle, <I>Physics,</I> Z. 5.</note> The | |
17060 <pb n=446><head>EUCLID</head> | |
17061 property assigned by the author to bodies <I>of the same kind</I> is | |
17062 quite different from what we attribute to bodies of the same | |
17063 specific gravity; he purports to prove that bodies of the | |
17064 same kind have <I>power</I> proportional to their size, and the effect | |
17065 of this, combined with the definitions, is that they move at | |
17066 speeds proportional to their volumes. Thus the tract is the | |
17067 most precise statement that we possess of the principle of | |
17068 Aristotle's dynamics, a principle which persisted until Bene- | |
17069 detti (1530-90) and Galilei (1564-1642) proved its falsity. | |
17070 <p>There are yet other fragments on mechanics associated with | |
17071 the name of Euclid. One is a tract translated by Woepcke | |
17072 from the Arabic in 1851 under the title ‘Le livre d'Euclide | |
17073 sur la balance’, a work which, although spoiled by some com- | |
17074 mentator, seems to go back to a Greek original and to have | |
17075 been an attempt to establish a theory of the lever, not from a | |
17076 general principle of dynamics like that of Aristotle, but from | |
17077 a few simple axioms such as the experience of daily life might | |
17078 suggest. The original work may have been earlier than | |
17079 Archimedes and may have been written by a contemporary of | |
17080 Euclid. A third fragment, unearthed by Duhem from manu- | |
17081 scripts in the Bibliothèque Nationale in Paris, contains four | |
17082 propositions purporting to be ‘liber Euclidis de ponderibus | |
17083 secundum terminorum circumferentiam’. The first of the | |
17084 propositions, connecting the law of the lever with the size of | |
17085 the circles described by its ends, recalls the similar demon- | |
17086 stration in the Aristotelian <I>Mechanica</I>; the others attempt to | |
17087 give a theory of the balance, taking account of the weight of | |
17088 the lever itself, and assuming that a portion of it (regarded as | |
17089 cylindrical) may be supposed to be detached and replaced by | |
17090 an equal weight suspended from its middle point. The three | |
17091 fragments supplement each other in a curious way, and it is a | |
17092 question whether they belonged to one treatise or were due to | |
17093 different authors. In any case there seems to be no indepen- | |
17094 dent evidence that Euclid was the author of any of the | |
17095 fragments, or that he wrote on mechanics at all.<note>For further details about these mechanical fragments see P. Duhem, | |
17096 <I>Les origines de la statique,</I> 1905, esp. vol. i, pp. 61-97.</note> |